Candelore v. Tinder, Inc. ( 2018 )


Menu:
  • Filed 1/29/18
    CERTIFIED FOR PUBLICATION
    IN THE COURT OF APPEAL OF THE STATE OF CALIFORNIA
    SECOND APPELLATE DISTRICT
    DIVISION THREE
    ALLAN CANDELORE,                           B270172
    Plaintiff and Appellant,            (Los Angeles County
    Super. Ct. No. BC583162)
    v.
    TINDER, INC.,
    Defendant and Respondent.
    APPEAL from a judgment of the Superior Court of Los
    Angeles County, William F. Highberger, Judge. Reversed.
    The Kralowec Law Group, Kimberly A. Kralowec, Kathleen
    Styles Rogers; Rava Law Firm and Alfred G. Rava for Plaintiff
    and Appellant.
    Manatt, Phelps & Phillips, Robert H. Platt, Donald R.
    Brown and Christopher A. Rheinheimer for Defendant and
    Respondent.
    _________________________
    1
    INTRODUCTION
    Tinder, Inc. owns and operates the smartphone-based
    dating application, Tinder. The original app began, and is still
    offered, as a free online dating service. It presents users with
    photos of potential dates. The user can swipe right to express
    approval, or swipe left to express disapproval. In March 2015,
    Tinder released a premium service called “Tinder Plus,” which
    allows users to access additional features of the app for a monthly
    fee.
    Plaintiff, Allan Candelore, commenced this action on behalf
    of himself and a putative class of California consumers who were
    over 30 years old when they subscribed to Tinder Plus. The
    complaint alleges that Tinder charges consumers who are age 30
    and older $19.99 per month for Tinder Plus, while it charges
    consumers under the age of 30 only $9.99 or $14.99 per month for
    the Tinder Plus features.1 Candelore sued for age discrimination
    in violation of the Unruh Civil Rights Act (Civ. Code, § 51; the
    Unruh Act or the Act) and the Unfair Competition Law
    (Bus. & Prof. Code, § 17200 et seq.; the UCL).2 The trial court
    sustained Tinder’s demurrer without leave to amend, ruling in
    part that Tinder’s age-based pricing practice did not constitute
    arbitrary or invidious discrimination because it was reasonably
    based on market testing showing “younger users” are “more
    1     There is some inconsistency in the record about whether
    the $19.99 monthly charge applies to individuals “over 30 years
    of age” versus “age 30 and older.” For purposes of our decision,
    the distinction makes no difference.
    2     Statutory references are to the Civil Code, unless otherwise
    stated.
    2
    budget constrained” than older users, “and need a lower price to
    pull the trigger.”
    But, as discussed below, the Unruh Act provides broad
    protection against arbitrary age-based price discrimination. No
    matter what Tinder’s market research may have shown about the
    younger users’ relative income and willingness to pay for the
    service, as a group, as compared to the older cohort, some
    individuals will not fit the mold. Some older consumers will be
    “more budget constrained” and less willing to pay than some in
    the younger group. We conclude the discriminatory pricing
    model, as alleged, violates the Unruh Act and the UCL to the
    extent it employs an arbitrary, class-based, generalization about
    older users’ incomes as a basis for charging them more than
    younger users. Because nothing in the complaint suggests there
    is a strong public policy that justifies the alleged discriminatory
    pricing, the trial court erred in sustaining the demurrer.
    Accordingly, we swipe left, and reverse.
    STANDARD OF REVIEW
    This appeal followed a judgment of dismissal after the trial
    court sustained Tinder’s demurrer without leave to amend. “The
    purpose of a demurrer is to test the sufficiency of a complaint by
    raising questions of law.” (Sargoy v. Resolution Trust Corp.
    (1992) 
    8 Cal.App.4th 1039
    , 1041 (Sargoy).) The court is to accept
    as true all allegations of fact contained in the complaint. (Id. at
    pp. 1041-1042) When a demurrer is sustained, the reviewing
    court must determine whether the complaint alleges sufficient
    facts to state a cause of action, adopting a liberal construction of
    the pleading and drawing all reasonable inferences in favor of the
    asserted claims. (Harris v. Capital Growth Investors XIV (1991)
    
    52 Cal.3d 1142
    , 1170, fn. 16 (Harris).)
    3
    FACTS AND PROCEDURAL BACKGROUND
    In addition to the factual allegations set forth in the
    Introduction to this opinion, Candelore’s complaint included the
    following excerpt from a news report on the website TakePart,
    offering Tinder’s justification for its age-based pricing:
    “The logic Tinder executives supplied for the age-
    related pricing? It benefits their bottom line. ‘During
    our testing we’ve learned, not surprisingly, that
    younger users are just as excited about Tinder Plus,
    but are more budget constrained, and need a lower
    price to pull the trigger,’ Tinder’s vice president of
    corporate communications, Rosette Pambakian, told
    TakePart in an email. [¶] ‘We’ve priced Tinder Plus
    based on a combination of factors, including what
    we’ve learned through our testing, and we’ve found
    that these price points were adopted very well by
    certain age demographics,’ Pambakian wrote.”
    Tinder demurred to each cause of action, arguing the
    complaint failed to state a claim because (1) age-based pricing
    does not “implicate the irrational, invidious stereotypes” that the
    Unruh Act was intended to proscribe; (2) the public statement by
    Tinder’s executive, as quoted in the complaint, “refute[d] any
    notion that the alleged discrimination in pricing [was] arbitrary”;
    and (3) age-based pricing is neither “unlawful” nor “unfair” under
    the UCL.
    The trial court sustained Tinder’s demurrer without leave
    to amend. With respect to the Unruh Act claim, the court ruled
    (1) there is “no basis in the published decisions for applying the
    Unruh Act to age-based pricing differentials”; (2) “Tinder’s
    rationale that customers age 30 and younger have less capacity to
    4
    pay for premium services” demonstrates “the differential is not
    ‘arbitrary, invidious or unreasonable’ within the meaning of the
    Act”; and (3) Tinder’s alleged pricing furthers the “ ‘public
    policies’ ” of “(a) increased access to services for the general public
    and (b) profit maximization by the vendor, a legitimate goal in
    our capitalistic economy.” As for the UCL claims, the court ruled
    (1) Candelore’s failure to allege an Unruh Act violation defeats
    his “ ‘unlawful’ ” prong claim; and (2) the alleged business
    practice is not “ ‘unfair’ ” under the UCL because “it is entirely
    proper for Tinder to charge alternative prices in the pursuit of
    profit maximization” and “the rationale for this price distinction
    (quoted by plaintiff in the Complaint . . . ) is a sufficient business
    reason for doing so.”
    The trial court entered judgment for Tinder, from which
    Candelore appeals.
    DISCUSSION
    1.      Overview of the Unruh Act
    “Enacted in 1959, the Unruh Act secures equal access to
    public accommodations and prohibits discrimination by business
    establishments. Its predecessor, our state’s first public
    accommodations statute, became law in 1897.” (Harris, supra,
    52 Cal.3d at p. 1150.) “The 1897 act was patterned in part after
    the National Civil Rights Act of 1875 (
    18 Stat. 335
    , ch. 114,
    §§ 1-2) which guaranteed to all persons within United States
    jurisdiction ‘the full and equal enjoyment of the accommodations,
    advantages, facilities, and privileges of inns, public conveyances
    on land or water, theaters, and other places of public amusement
    . . . .’ ” (Harris, at p. 1150, fn. 3.) After the United States Supreme
    Court invalidated the federal act, many states, including
    California, responded by enacting their own statutes assuring
    5
    access to public accommodations on a nondiscriminatory basis.
    (Id. at pp. 1150-1151, fn. 3., citing Civil Rights Cases (1883)
    
    109 U.S. 3
    .)
    The Unruh Act provides that “[a]ll persons within the
    jurisdiction of this state are free and equal, and no matter what
    their sex, race, color, religion, ancestry, national origin,
    disability, medical condition, genetic information, marital status,
    sexual orientation, citizenship, primary language, or immigration
    status are entitled to the full and equal accommodations,
    advantages, facilities, privileges, or services in all business
    establishments of every kind whatsoever.” (§ 51, subd. (b).) The
    Act’s “fundamental purpose” is “to secure to all persons equal
    access to public accommodations ‘no matter’ ” their personal
    characteristics. (Harris, 
    supra,
     52 Cal.3d at p. 1169.) To
    accomplish this purpose, the Act prohibits “arbitrary
    discrimination by business establishments.” (In re Cox (1970)
    
    3 Cal.3d 205
    , 216 (Cox); Sargoy, supra, 8 Cal.App.4th at p. 1043
    [the Act renders unlawful “arbitrary, invidious or unreasonable
    discrimination”].)
    Although its text identifies particular kinds of
    discrimination – such as sex, race, and national origin – this list
    is “illustrative, rather than restrictive,” and the Unruh Act’s
    proscription against arbitrary discrimination extends beyond
    these enumerated classes. (Cox, supra, 3 Cal.3d at p. 212; Marina
    Point, Ltd. v. Wolfson (1982) 
    30 Cal.3d 721
    , 730, 732 (Marina
    Point).) Nevertheless, the enumerated categories, bearing the
    “common element” of being “personal” characteristics of an
    individual, necessarily confine the Act’s reach to forms of
    discrimination based on characteristics similar to the statutory
    classifications – such as “a person’s geographical origin, physical
    6
    attributes, and personal beliefs.” (Harris, supra, 52 Cal.3d at
    p. 1160.) The “personal characteristics” protected by the Act are
    not defined by “immutability, since some are, while others are not
    [immutable], but that they represent traits, conditions, decisions,
    or choices fundamental to a person’s identity, beliefs and self-
    definition.” (Koebke v. Bernardo Heights Country Club (2005)
    
    36 Cal.4th 824
    , 842–843 (Koebke).)
    Thus, while not all discrimination is prohibited (see Harris,
    
    supra,
     52 Cal.3d at pp. 1160-1161), there is no dispute that, as
    relevant here, the Unruh Act proscribes arbitrary discrimination
    based on an individual’s age – a personal characteristic similar to
    the classifications enumerated in the Act. (See Marina Point,
    supra, 30 Cal.3d at p. 730; Pizarro v. Lamb’s Players Theatre
    (2006) 
    135 Cal.App.4th 1171
    , 1174 (Pizarro) [“Age discrimination
    may violate the Act if used as an arbitrary class-based
    generalization”]; see also Harris, at p. 1153 [“the Legislature
    affirmed that section 51 prohibits age discrimination in the sale
    or rental of housing”]; Koebke, 
    supra,
     36 Cal.4th at p. 842 [“the
    phrase ‘personal characteristic’ in Harris, . . . encompasse[s] both
    the categories enumerated in the Act and those categories added
    to the Act by judicial construction” prior to the Harris opinion].)
    The Act applies not merely in situations where businesses
    exclude individuals altogether, but also “where unequal
    treatment is the result of a business practice.” (Koire v. Metro Car
    Wash (1985) 
    40 Cal.3d 24
    , 29 (Koire).) “Unequal treatment
    includes offering price discounts on an arbitrary basis to certain
    classes of individuals.” (Pizarro, supra, 135 Cal.App.4th at
    p. 1174; Koire, at p. 29.)
    7
    2.      Tinder’s Alleged Pricing Model Uses a Personal
    Characteristic to Discriminate Against Older
    Customers Based on a Generalization About Income
    Candelore asserts Tinder’s alleged pricing model violates
    the Unruh Act because it discriminates against customers who
    are age 30 and over by requiring them to pay more than twice as
    much as younger customers to access Tinder Plus. In response,
    Tinder maintains this allegation is insufficient to state a claim
    for arbitrary age discrimination, because its pricing model
    rationally treats “youth [as] a reasonable proxy for economic
    disadvantage.” (Italics added.) By Tinder’s account, it is “self-
    evident that people under 30 face financial challenges,” and this
    “common knowledge provides a reasonable and non-arbitrary
    basis for Tinder to offer a discount to people under 30.” The trial
    court likewise reasoned that Tinder’s age-based pricing model
    was “not ‘arbitrary, invidious or unreasonable’ within the
    meaning of the Act” because the complaint admitted “Tinder’s
    rationale” was based on market research showing “customers age
    30 and younger have less capacity to pay for premium services.”
    Although past cases have suggested age can serve as a
    reasonable proxy for income, we conclude Tinder’s alleged
    practice contravenes “the individual nature of the statutory right
    of equal access to business establishments that is afforded ‘all
    persons’ by the Unruh Act.” (Marina Point, supra, 30 Cal.3d at
    p. 725, italics added.)
    Our Supreme Court’s decision in Marina Point is
    controlling. There, the Supreme Court was asked to address
    whether, under the Unruh Act, an apartment complex owner
    could lawfully refuse to rent its apartments to a family solely
    because the family included a minor child. (Marina Point, supra,
    8
    30 Cal.3d at p. 724.) In the landlord’s action to eject one such
    family, the municipal court found that “ ‘[c]hildren are rowdier,
    noisier, more mischievous and more boisterous than adults,’ and
    upheld the landlord’s policy of excluding all families with minor
    children.” (Ibid.) Based on this finding, the landlord defended the
    policy on appeal, claiming it was permitted “to achieve its
    legitimate interest in a quiet and peaceful residential atmosphere
    by excluding all minors from its housing accommodations, thus
    providing its adult tenants with a ‘child free’ environment.”
    (Id. at p. 725.) The Supreme Court disagreed.
    The Supreme Court concluded the landlord’s blanket
    exclusion of families with minor children contravened “the
    individual nature of the statutory right of equal access to
    business establishments that is afforded ‘all persons’ by the
    Unruh Act.” (Marina Point, supra, 30 Cal.3d at p. 725, italics
    added.) Drawing a parallel to the “individual nature” of the
    federal Civil Rights Act, the court embraced the following holding
    by the United States Supreme Court regarding the federal
    statute: “ ‘The statute’s focus on the individual . . . precludes
    treatment of individuals as simply components of a racial,
    religious, sexual or national class. If height is required for a job, a
    tall woman may not be refused employment merely because, on
    the average, women are too short. Even a true generalization
    about the class is an insufficient reason for disqualifying an
    individual to whom the generalization does not apply.’ ” (Id. at
    p. 740, quoting City of Los Angeles, Dept. of Water v. Manhart
    (1978) 
    435 U.S. 702
    , 708.) Applying this principle to the
    landlord’s adults-only policy, the Marina Point court held that,
    while the landlord retained the right to exclude persons whose
    individual conduct had disrupted its legitimate business
    9
    pursuits, the Unruh Act did “not permit [the landlord] to exclude
    an entire class of individuals on the basis of a generalized
    prediction that the class ‘as a whole’ is more likely to commit
    misconduct than some other class of the public.” (Marina Point,
    at p. 739, second italics added; accord O’Connor v. Village Green
    Owners Assn. (1983) 
    33 Cal.3d 790
    , 793 (O’Connor) [restrictive
    covenant limiting residency to persons over the age of 18 declared
    invalid under the Unruh Act].)
    Having concluded the “potential misbehavior of children as
    a class [did] not justify [the landlord’s] exclusionary practice,” the
    Marina Point court turned to whether the policy might
    “nonetheless be sustained as reasonable on the ground that the
    presence of children basically does not accord with the nature of
    [the landlord’s] business enterprise and of the facilities provided.”
    (Marina Point, supra, 30 Cal.3d at p. 741.) With respect to this
    issue, the court rejected the landlord’s effort to analogize the
    restriction to the age-limited admission policies of retirement and
    senior living communities, which were supported by “specific
    ‘age-conscious’ legislative measures” addressed to the “special
    housing needs of the elderly in contemporary American society.”
    (Id. at p. 742, citing Health & Saf. Code, § 51230 [reserving
    proportion of state-financed low income housing for occupancy by
    elderly]; 12 U.S.C. § 1701q [federal loan program for housing for
    10
    elderly families].)3 In light of the public policies reflected in these
    legislative enactments, the court recognized that “age
    qualifications as to a housing facility reserved for older citizens
    can operate as a reasonable and permissible means under the
    Unruh Act of establishing and preserving specialized facilities for
    those particularly in need of such services or environment.”
    (Marina Point, at pp. 742-743.) The court held the landlord
    “[could not] plausibly claim that its exclusionary policy serve[d]
    any similarly compelling societal interest,” observing, the
    landlord could “hardly contend, for example, that the class of
    persons for whom Marina Point seeks to reserve its housing
    accommodation, i.e., single adults or families without children,
    are more in need of housing than the class of persons whom the
    landlord has excluded from its apartment complex.” (Id. at
    p. 743.)
    Even crediting Tinder’s stated rationale, its alleged
    discriminatory pricing model violates the principle articulated in
    Marina Point by operating on the “generalized prediction” that
    an individual over the age of 30 earns more and is less budget
    3      The Marina Point court also found the contemplated
    adults-only apartment complex was distinguishable from
    businesses such as bars and adult book stores, which could
    likewise “be defended by reference to . . . statutorily sanctioned
    restriction[s] on the activities of children.” (Marina Point, supra,
    30 Cal.3d at p. 741, citing Bus. & Prof. Code, § 25658 [furnishing
    alcoholic beverages to person under 21] & Pen. Code, § 313.1
    [distributing “ ‘harmful matter’ ” to a minor].)
    11
    constrained than another individual under the age of 30.4
    (Marina Point, supra, 30 Cal.3d at p. 739.) Because we may
    reasonably infer that this generalization does not hold for all
    members of the respective age classes (see, e.g., Pizarro, supra,
    135 Cal.App.4th at p. 1176), we may also infer that Tinder’s
    pricing model will, in some cases, result in older individuals who
    earn less than some younger users being charged more than
    twice what those younger users must pay to access the Tinder
    Plus features. A blanket, class-based pricing model like this,
    when based upon a personal characteristic such as age,
    constitutes prohibited arbitrary discrimination under the Unruh
    Act. (See Marina Point, at p. 740 [“ ‘Even a true generalization
    about the class is an insufficient reason for disqualifying an
    individual to whom the generalization does not apply,’ ” italics
    omitted].)
    We recognize, however, that past cases have embraced the
    notion that age may serve as a reasonable proxy for income in
    upholding age-based discounts against Unruh Act claims. (See,
    e.g., Starkman v. Mann Theaters Corp. (1991) 
    227 Cal.App.3d 1491
    , 1499 (Starkman); Pizarro, supra, 135 Cal.App.4th at
    p. 1176; Javorsky v. Western Athletic Clubs, Inc. (2015) 
    242 Cal.App.4th 1386
    , 1402-1403 (Javorsky); see also Sargoy, supra,
    4      Candelore rightly points out that the complaint alleges only
    that Tinder has publicly stated the budget constraints of its
    younger users were one among “ ‘a combination of factors’ ” that
    led it to adopt the chosen price points for “ ‘certain age
    demographics.’ ” We agree with his contention that the allegation
    concerning Tinder’s public statement does not preclude him from
    amending his complaint should discovery reveal other factors
    that influenced Tinder’s pricing decision.
    12
    8 Cal.App.4th at pp. 1044-1045 [applying rationale to uphold
    bank program offering higher interest rates to seniors].) These
    cases have invariably relied upon dictum from our Supreme
    Court’s opinion in Koire, where, in the course of holding sex-
    based price discounts at Ladies’ Day car wash and Ladies’ Night
    bar events violated the Act, the court observed that “[c]harging
    different prices to children and senior citizens is sometimes
    permissible and socially desirable,” in part because “[c]hildren
    and elderly persons frequently have limited earning capacities
    which justify differential treatment in some circumstances.”
    (Koire, supra, 40 Cal.3d at pp. 36–37.) We are mindful that the
    dictum of the Supreme Court, “while not controlling authority,
    carries persuasive weight and should be followed where it
    demonstrates a thorough analysis of the issue or reflects
    compelling logic.” (Smith v. County of Los Angeles (1989)
    
    214 Cal.App.3d 266
    , 297.) Nevertheless, because it conflicts with
    the Supreme Court’s holding in Marina Point, which makes
    discrimination based on generalized assumptions about an
    individual’s personal characteristics “arbitrary” under the Act, we
    decline to follow the dictum from Koire on this point. (See Marina
    Point, supra, 30 Cal.3d at pp. 738–740.)
    Our decision to break with Koire’s dictum is bolstered by
    the fact that discounts for children and seniors are independently
    justified by compelling “social policy considerations as evidenced
    by legislative enactments.” (Koire, supra, 40 Cal.3d at p. 38, italics
    added.) In Koire, the court remarked that while it “need not
    determine the validity of any specific age-based discount,
    especially without the benefit of briefing on the issue from parties
    actually affected by the practice,” there were “several important
    and distinguishing features” that differentiated such practices
    13
    from the sex-based discounts under review. (Id. at p. 37.) Among
    those distinguishing features, the Koire court emphasized that
    “[n]umerous statutes in California provide for differential
    treatment of children and adults,” “state and federal legislation
    ha[d] been enacted to address the special needs of our elderly
    citizens,” and “the Legislature ha[d] specifically provided for
    certain price discounts for senior citizens.” (Id. at pp. 37-38,
    citing, e.g., Civ. Code, § 1556 [limitation on minors’ capacity to
    contract]; 
    42 U.S.C. § 1381
     et seq. [supplemental security income
    for seniors]; Welf. & Inst. Code, § 12050 et seq. [senior security
    benefits]; former Veh. Code, § 13001 [reduced transit fares for
    seniors]; Ed. Code, § 89330 [waiver of fees at California State
    University campuses for seniors].) Indeed, although the court
    identified the limited earning capacities of children and seniors
    as an additional justification for differential treatment, that
    consideration too was driven by statutory enactments reflecting
    the Legislature’s judgment to limit work opportunities for these
    age demographics. (Koire, at pp. 37-38, citing, e.g., Lab. Code,
    §§ 1285 et seq., 1290 & 1391 [establishing conditions and
    sanctions for employing minors]; Gov. Code, § 75000 et seq.
    [the Judges’ Retirement Law].)
    Although past cases have followed the Koire dictum in
    citing generalized assumptions about income disparity as
    grounds to uphold age-based price discounts, in most of those
    cases the discounts were independently justified by social policy
    considerations evidenced in legislative enactments.
    (See Starkman, supra, 227 Cal.App.3d at pp. 1499-1500 [citing
    statutes limiting child employment and providing public
    assistance for seniors as evidence of social policy justifying
    discounted movie tickets for children and seniors]; Pizarro, supra,
    14
    135 Cal.App.4th at p. 1176 [citing United States Supreme Court
    case discussing federal Age Discrimination in Employment Act
    protections for 40-to-65 age group as justification for “baby-
    boomer” discount];5 see also Sargoy, supra, 8 Cal.App.4th at
    p. 1045 [statutory enactments favoring retirement established
    public policy justifying bank program offering higher interest
    rates to senior citizens]; Lazar v. Hertz Corp. (1999)
    
    69 Cal.App.4th 1494
    , 1503 (Lazar) [because “legislative
    scheme . . . expressly approves the adoption of minimum age
    requirements by car rental companies,” plaintiff could not
    maintain Unruh Act claim on basis of company’s refusal to rent
    vehicles to persons under age 25].)6 These statutory enactments,
    which reflect the considered judgment of a legislative body to
    advance certain social policy objectives by treating children and
    seniors differently from the rest of the public, justified the use of
    5     The Pizzaro court also observed that providing “discounted
    theater admissions to ‘baby-boomers’ to attend a musical about
    that generation does not perpetuate any irrational stereotypes,”
    thus, recognizing that the price discounts were not based on
    “ ‘some arbitrary, class-based generalization’ ” about the age
    group, but rather on the fact that the musical was about the
    baby-boomer generation. (Pizarro, supra, 135 Cal.App.4th at
    p. 1176.)
    6      The trial court understandably relied upon these cases in
    concluding Candelore could not state a claim because there was
    “no basis in the published decisions for applying the Unruh Act to
    age-based pricing differentials.” That conclusion, while consistent
    with these appellate authorities, failed to recognize that the cases
    were fundamentally different than this one because, in each, the
    differential treatment at issue was consonant with recognized
    public policies reflected in legislative enactments.
    15
    class-based criteria in those cases, without requiring the courts to
    engage in the sort of generalizations about age and income that
    run counter to the individual nature of the right secured to all
    persons by the Unruh Act. These cases can thus be reconciled
    with the Supreme Court’s holding in Marina Point,
    notwithstanding their partial reliance on the incongruous dictum
    from Koire. (See Marina Point, supra, 30 Cal.3d at p. 742
    [recognizing age-limited admission policies of retirement and
    senior living communities were supported by “specific ‘age-
    conscious’ legislative measures”].)
    The only outlier is Javorsky, where the court approved a
    luxury health club’s age-based discount for 18- to 29-year-olds,
    despite scant indication of a legislative policy favoring
    differential treatment for this age group. (Javorsky, supra,
    242 Cal.App.4th at p. 1404.)7 The Javorsky court held the age-
    based discount was nevertheless justified because “(1) it expands
    7      While concluding a supporting statutory enactment was
    unnecessary to uphold the discriminatory policy, the Javorsky
    court noted that “the law is not entirely bereft of indications that
    persons under 30 – including students and those just beginning
    their careers – might feel economic pressures worthy of attention
    and assistance as a public policy matter.” (Javorsky, supra,
    242 Cal.App.4th at p. 1404.) In support of that observation, the
    court cited statements made by Senator Durbin in connection
    with Congressional debate over extending the dependent
    coverage provisions of the Affordable Care Act to 24- and 25-year-
    olds. (Ibid., citing Remarks of Sen. Durbin, 155 Cong. Rec. 32915
    (2009).) Notwithstanding Senator Durbin’s remarks, however, the
    Javorsky court acknowledged that “[n]o statute or published
    decision identifies 18 to 29 year olds in the San Francisco Bay
    Area as a ‘financially disadvantaged’ group entitled to a ‘luxury’
    health and fitness club.” (Javorsky, at p. 1403.)
    16
    access to beneficial, recreational activities; (2) it benefits an age
    group with limited financial resources; and (3) it does not
    perpetuate any invidious stereotypes.” (Id. at p. 1401.) With
    respect to the second point, the plaintiff argued “[a]ge brackets
    [were] poor indicators of income,” citing census data and other
    evidence offered in opposition to the health club’s motion for
    summary judgment showing that “people age 28 have equal to or
    greater median income than people ages 33, 35, 41, 44, 46, 47, 49,
    and 51 to 89.” (Id. at p. 1403.) The Javorsky court rejected the
    argument, responding that the Unruh Act required only a
    showing that “persons ages 18 to 29, as a group, have less income
    than persons age 30 and over” to demonstrate the discriminatory
    practice was “not arbitrary.”8 (Ibid., italics added.) Respectfully,
    we find that reasoning to be inconsistent with the “individual
    nature” of the right secured by the Unruh Act, which protects
    individuals from unequal treatment based on generalizations
    8     The Javorsky court also remarked that the plaintiff’s
    argument, if accepted, “would obliterate all age-based discounts –
    including those upheld in Starkman and Pizarro – since all age
    groups include persons with higher incomes and persons with
    lower incomes.” (Javorsky, supra, 242 Cal.App.4th at p. 1403.)
    That conclusion ignores the fact that the age-based discounts in
    Starkman and Pizarro were independently justified by
    compelling social policy considerations as evidenced by legislative
    enactments – a justification which, as discussed, has been
    present in all cases upholding age-based business practices,
    except Javorsky. (See Starkman, supra, 227 Cal.App.3d at
    pp. 1499-1500; Pizarro, supra, 135 Cal.App.4th at pp. 1175-1176;
    Sargoy, supra, 8 Cal.App.4th at p. 1045; Lazar, supra,
    69 Cal.App.4th at p. 1503.)
    17
    about “a group” to which they belong.9 (Marina Point, supra,
    30 Cal.3d at p. 739-740; Koire, supra, 40 Cal.3d at pp. 35-36.)
    The danger of using age as a proxy for income to justify
    age-discriminatory pricing becomes more apparent when one
    acknowledges that such pricing operates not merely as a
    “discount” for the favored age group, but effectively as a
    surcharge on the disfavored one. (See Koire, supra, 40 Cal.3d at
    p. 34 [“plaintiff was adversely affected by the price discounts”
    insofar as “he had to pay more than any woman customer, based
    solely on his sex”].) Were Tinder’s justification sufficient,
    generalizations about the relative incomes of different age groups
    could be employed to rationalize higher prices for all consumers
    30 and older in even the most essential areas of commerce – such
    as grocery shopping, gasoline purchases, etc. – even in instances
    where an individual did not in fact enjoy the economic
    advantages that are presumed about his or her age group as a
    whole. (See Marina Point, supra, 30 Cal.3d at p. 739 [warning
    that Unruh would be “drastically undermined” if class-based
    discrimination could be justified simply because a business had
    9     Tinder filed a request asking this court to take judicial
    notice of (1) several charts published by the United States Census
    Bureau regarding “ ‘Selected Characteristics of People 15 Years
    Old and Over by Total Money Income,’ ” and (2) a declaration
    offered by the defendant’s expert in Javorsky, purporting to
    analyze census data regarding the financial resources of different
    age demographics in California. Because we conclude group data
    about income by age demographic is insufficient to justify the
    alleged discrimination, we deny Tinder’s request for judicial
    notice. (See People ex rel. Lockyer v. Shamrock Foods Co. (2000)
    
    24 Cal.4th 415
    , 422, fn. 2 [“any matter to be judicially noticed
    must be relevant to a material issue”].)
    18
    “reason to believe that the class, taken as a whole, might present
    greater problems than other groups”].) It is inconceivable that an
    antidiscrimination law like the Unruh Act would countenance a
    grocer charging an unemployed 31-year-old patron twice as much
    as an employed 28-year-old customer merely on the basis of
    market testing showing that those over the age of 30 “as a group”
    generally earn more than 18- to 29-year-olds. Nor have the
    parties identified any legislative pronouncements that would
    justify such a departure from the Unruh Act’s language and
    provenance. Insofar as the Act entitles individuals to “full and
    equal accommodations, advantages, facilities, privileges, or
    services in all business establishments of every kind whatsoever”
    (§ 51, subd. (b), italics added), it follows that the same analysis
    must apply evenly to arguably less essential commercial services,
    such as premium features of an online dating app or luxury
    health club memberships.
    Consistent with Marina Point, we conclude Tinder’s alleged
    discriminatory pricing model cannot be justified by a
    generalization about the relative incomes and budget limitations
    of the two implicated age groups. We turn now to whether the
    public policies cited by the trial court compelled the finding that
    Tinder’s alleged discrimination was justified, as a matter of law.
    3.     The Complaint’s Allegations Do Not Compel the
    Finding that Public Policy Justifies Tinder’s Age-
    based Classification
    In sustaining the demurrer, the trial court concluded
    Tinder’s alleged age-based pricing model was justified by “ ‘public
    policies’ ” that promote “(a) increased access to services for the
    general public and (b) profit maximization by the vendor, a
    legitimate goal in our capitalistic economy.” Similar justifications
    19
    were rejected by the Supreme Court in Koire when advanced by
    the bar owner in defense of its Ladies’ Nights discounts. Further,
    while our Supreme Court recognized in Harris that vendors may
    pursue legitimate business interests by making economic
    distinctions among customers, it held such distinctions were
    permissible because they employed criteria that could conceivably
    be met by any customer, regardless of the customer’s personal
    characteristics. (Harris, supra, 52 Cal.3d at p. 1163.) The
    Supreme Court’s holdings in Koire and Harris control our
    resolution of this issue.
    Drawing on its prior holding in Marina Point, our Supreme
    Court in Koire explained that an otherwise prohibited
    “discriminatory practice” will be upheld as reasonable, and
    therefore not arbitrary, “when there is a strong public policy in
    favor of such treatment.” (Koire, supra, 40 Cal.3d at p. 31, citing
    Marina Point, supra, 30 Cal.3d at pp. 742-743.) The Koire court
    continued: “Public policy may be gleaned by reviewing other
    statutory enactments. For example, it is permissible to exclude
    children from bars or adult bookstores because it is illegal to
    serve alcoholic beverages or to distribute ‘ “harmful matter” ’ to
    minors. [Citations.] This sort of discrimination is not arbitrary
    because it is based on a ‘compelling societal interest’ [citation]
    and does not violate the Act.” (Koire, at p. 31, citing Marina
    Point, at p. 743.)
    In Koire, the Supreme Court rejected the argument that
    increasing patronage among women at Ladies’ Day carwash
    events and Ladies’ Night bar events was a sufficiently compelling
    societal interest to justify discriminatory sex-based pricing.
    (Koire, supra, 40 Cal.3d at p. 33.) The court reasoned that the
    asserted objective was “a far cry from the social policies which
    20
    have justified other exceptions to the Unruh Act,” like the
    “compelling societal interest in ensuring adequate housing for the
    elderly which justifies differential treatment based on age.”
    (Ibid.) The same analysis holds with respect Tinder’s purported
    objective here. Unlike children’s and senior’s discounts, which are
    justified by compelling societal interests that can be “gleaned
    [from] statutory enactments” (id. at p. 31), whatever interest
    society may have – if any – in increasing patronage among those
    under the age of 30 who may be interested in the premium
    features of an online dating app, that interest is not sufficiently
    compelling to justify discriminatory age-based pricing that may
    well exclude less economically advantaged individuals over the
    age of 30 from enjoying the same premium features.
    As for profit maximization, we have no quarrel with the
    trial court’s conclusion that it can be an acceptable business
    objective and can be advanced by price discrimination. As anyone
    who has attended an auction can attest, individuals may and
    often do value goods and services differently. Some are willing
    and able to pay a higher price than others for the same product.
    And, as any student of elementary microeconomics knows, sellers
    of goods and services could (at least theoretically) maximize
    profits if they could engage in price discrimination by charging
    higher prices to those consumers willing to pay them, and lower
    prices to the rest. For example, a seller might offer several
    versions of its product, with different features, trim, branding,
    etc., each at a different price, in an effort to increase overall
    profits. Or a seller might seek to attract bargain hunters by
    offering temporary price reductions during a sale or other
    promotion. But the quest for profit maximization can never serve
    21
    as an excuse for prohibited discrimination among potential
    customers.
    The Koire court made this point emphatically. It directly
    addressed and rejected the contention that a merchant’s interest
    in profit maximization could justify discriminatory sex-based
    pricing, relying again on its prior holding in Marina Point. The
    Koire court explained:
    “In Marina Point, this court held that the fact that a
    business enterprise was ‘ “proceed[ing] from a motive
    of rational self-interest” ’ did not justify
    discrimination. [Citation.] This court noted that ‘an
    entrepreneur may pursue many discriminatory
    practices “from a motive of rational self-interest,”
    e.g., economic gain, which would unquestionably
    violate the Unruh Act. For example, an entrepreneur
    may find it economically advantageous to exclude all
    homosexuals, or alternatively all nonhomosexuals,
    from his restaurant or hotel, but such a “rational”
    economic motive would not, of course, validate the
    practice.’ [Citation.] It would be no less a violation of
    the Act for an entrepreneur to charge all
    homosexuals, or all nonhomosexuals, reduced rates in
    his or her restaurant or hotel in order to encourage
    one group’s patronage and, thereby, increase profits.
    The same reasoning is applicable here, where
    reduced rates were offered to women and not men.”
    (Koire, supra, 40 Cal.3d at p. 32.) And, the same reasoning is
    likewise applicable here, where Tinder allegedly offers reduced
    rates to those under the age of 30, but not individuals who are
    30 or older.
    22
    Recognizing that a business’s interest in maximizing profits
    is insufficient to justify discrimination based on an individual’s
    personal characteristics does not preclude a business like Tinder
    from employing rational economic distinctions to broaden its user
    base and increase profitability. (See Harris, 
    supra,
     52 Cal.3d at
    p. 1163.) But, as Koire and Harris teach, those distinctions must
    be drawn in such a way that they could conceivably be met by
    any customer, regardless of the customer’s age or other personal
    characteristics. (See Koire, supra, 40 Cal.3d at p. 36; Harris, at
    p. 1163.) For instance, Tinder could establish different
    membership levels for its Tinder Plus service that would allow
    more budget constrained customers, regardless of age, to access
    certain premium features at a lower price, while offering
    additional features to those less budget conscious users who are
    willing to pay more. Tinder could also offer discounts for
    purchasing several months of Tinder Plus in advance that would
    likewise allow budget constrained users cheaper access to its
    premium features, without arbitrarily discriminating against
    older users on the basis of age. “The key,” as our Supreme Court
    put it in Koire, “is that the discounts must be ‘applicable alike to
    persons of every sex, color, race, [and age, etc.]’ (§ 51), instead of
    being contingent on some arbitrary, class-based generalization.”
    (Koire, at p. 36; accord Harris, at p. 1163 [“discounts based on
    quantity, advance reservations, time of purchase or other
    conditions ‘which any patron could satisfy’ [are] ‘clearly
    permissible’ ”].)
    As alleged, Tinder’s pricing model discriminates against
    users age 30 and over, and the complaint’s allegations do not
    compel the finding that this discrimination is justified by a strong
    public policy in favor of such differential treatment. While we
    23
    make no judgment about the true character of Tinder’s pricing
    model, or whether evidence exists to establish a sufficient
    justification for charging older users more than younger users, we
    conclude the complaint’s allegations are sufficient to state a claim
    for age discrimination in violation of the Unruh Act. The trial
    court erred in sustaining Tinder’s demurrer to the Unruh Act
    claim.
    4.     The Complaint States a Claim for Violation of the
    UCL
    The UCL prohibits, and provides civil remedies for, “unfair
    competition,” which includes “any unlawful, unfair or fraudulent
    business act or practice.” (Bus. & Prof. Code, § 17200.) Its
    purpose “ ‘is to protect both consumers and competitors by
    promoting fair competition in commercial markets for goods and
    services.’ [Citations.] In service of that purpose, the Legislature
    framed the UCL’s substantive provisions in ‘ “broad sweeping
    language” ’ [citations] and provided ‘courts with broad equitable
    powers to remedy violations’ [citation].” (Kwikset Corp. v.
    Superior Court (2011) 
    51 Cal.4th 310
    , 320.)
    The UCL’s “unlawful” prong “borrows violations of other
    laws . . . and makes those unlawful practices actionable under the
    UCL.” (Lazar, supra, 69 Cal.App.4th at p. 1505.) “ ‘[V]irtually any
    law or regulation – federal or state, statutory or common law –
    can serve as [a] predicate for [an] . . . “unlawful” [prong]
    violation.’ ” (Paulus v. Bob Lynch Ford, Inc. (2006)
    
    139 Cal.App.4th 659
    , 681.) Because we conclude the complaint
    adequately states a claim for violation of the Unruh Act, we also
    conclude the allegations are sufficient to state a claim under the
    “unlawful” prong of the UCL. (See Klein v. Chevron U.S.A., Inc.
    (2012) 
    202 Cal.App.4th 1342
    , 1384.)
    24
    Further, in view of our conclusion that Tinder’s alleged
    discriminatory pricing model violates the public policy embodied
    in the Unruh Act, the UCL’s “unfair” prong provides an
    independent basis for relief on the facts alleged. The standard for
    finding an “unfair” practice in a consumer action is
    “ ‘intentionally broad, thus allowing courts maximum discretion
    to prohibit new schemes to defraud. [Citation.] The test of
    whether a business practice is unfair “involves an examination of
    [that practice’s] impact on its alleged victim, balanced against the
    reasons, justifications and motives of the alleged wrongdoer. In
    brief, the court must weigh the utility of the defendant’s conduct
    against the gravity of the harm to the alleged victim . . . .
    [Citations.]” . . . [A]n “unfair” business practice occurs when that
    practice “offends an established public policy or when the practice
    is immoral, unethical, oppressive, unscrupulous or substantially
    injurious to consumers.” [Citation.]’ ” (Smith v. State Farm
    Mutual Automobile Ins. Co. (2001) 
    93 Cal.App.4th 700
    , 718-719;
    accord Ticconi v. Blue Shield of California Life & Health Ins. Co.
    (2008) 
    160 Cal.App.4th 528
    , 539.)
    As discussed, the Unruh Act protects “all persons” from
    status-based discriminatory business practices that operate to
    deprive innocent individuals of “full and equal accommodations,
    advantages, facilities, privileges, or services in all business
    establishments of every kind whatsoever.” (§ 51, subd. (b);
    Marina Point, supra, 30 Cal.3d at p. 740.) Insofar as the
    complaint sufficiently alleges a violation of the Act and the public
    policy it embodies, a claim for violation of the UCL has also been
    stated.
    25
    DISPOSITION
    The judgment is reversed. Candelore is entitled to his costs.
    CERTIFIED FOR PUBLICATION
    CURREY, J.*
    We concur:
    EDMON, P. J.
    LAVIN, J.
    *     Judge of the Los Angeles Superior Court, assigned by the
    Chief Justice pursuant to article VI, section 6 of the California
    Constitution.
    26