Brian Fields v. Speaker of the Pennsylvania ( 2019 )


Menu:
  •                                   PRECEDENTIAL
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE THIRD CIRCUIT
    ________________
    Nos. 18-2974 & 18-3167
    ________________
    BRIAN FIELDS; PAUL TUCKER; DEANA WEAVER;
    SCOTT RHOADES; JOSHUA E. NEIDERHISER;
    PENNSYLVANIA NONBELIEVERS, INC.;
    DILLSBURG AREA FREETHINKERS;
    LANCASTER FREETHOUGHT SOCIETY;
    REV. DR. NEAL JONES; PHILADELPHIA ETHICAL
    SOCIETY; RICHARD KINIRY
    BRIAN FIELDS; PAUL TUCKER;
    DEANA WEAVER; SCOTT
    RHOADES;
    JOSHUA E. NEIDERHISER;
    PENNSYLVANIA
    NONBELIEVERS, INC.;
    DILLSBURG AREA
    FREETHINKERS; LANCASTER
    FREETHOUGHT SOCIETY;
    REV. DR. NEAL JONES;
    PHILADELPHIA ETHICAL
    SOCIETY
    Appellants (18-3167)
    v.
    SPEAKER OF THE PENNSYLVANIA
    HOUSE OF REPRESENTATIVES;
    PARLIAMENTARIAN OF THE PENNSYLVANIA
    HOUSE OF REPRESENTATIVES;
    DIRECTOR OF SPECIAL EVENTS OF THE
    PENNSYLVANIA HOUSE OF REPRESENTATIVES;
    REPRESENTATIVE FOR PENNSYLVANIA
    HOUSE DISTRICT 92;
    REPRESENTATIVE FOR PENNSYLVANIA
    HOUSE DISTRICT 95;
    REPRESENTATIVE FOR PENNSYLVANIA
    HOUSE DISTRICT 97;
    REPRESENTATIVE FOR PENNSYLVANIA HOUSE
    DISTRICT 165;
    REPRESENTATIVE FOR PENNSYLVANIA HOUSE
    DISTRICT 167;
    REPRESENTATIVE FOR PENNSYLVANIA HOUSE
    DISTRICT 182;
    REPRESENTATIVE FOR PENNSYLVANIA HOUSE
    DISTRICT 193;
    REPRESENTATIVE FOR PENNSYLVANIA HOUSE
    DISTRICT 196,
    all solely in their official Capacities
    Appellants (18-2974)
    ________________
    Appeal from the United States District Court
    for the Middle District of Pennsylvania
    (D.C. Civil Action No. 1-16-cv-01764)
    District Judge: Honorable Christopher C. Conner
    ________________
    2
    Argued June 17, 2019
    Before: AMBRO, RESTREPO, and FISHER, Circuit Judges
    (Opinion filed: August 23, 2019)
    Jonathan F. Bloom
    Karl S. Myers (Argued)
    Spencer R. Short
    Kyle A. Jacobsen
    Stradley Ronon Stevens & Young
    2005 Market Street, Suite 2600
    Philadelphia, PA 19103
    Mark E. Chopko
    Stradley Ronon Stevens & Young
    1250 Connecticut Avenue NW
    Washington, DC 20036
    Counsel for Appellant/Cross Appellee
    Speaker of the Pennsylvania House of Representatives
    Patrick Grubel
    Richard B. Katskee
    Alexander J. Luchenitser (Argued)
    Americans United for Separation of Church & State
    1310 L Street NW, Suite 200
    Washington, DC 20005
    Allen C. Warshaw
    1035 McCormick Avenue
    Mechanicsburg, PA 17055
    3
    Eric O. Husby
    American Atheists
    306 South Blvd
    Tampa, FL 33606
    Counsel for Appellee/Cross Appellant
    Brian Fields
    Randall L. Wenger
    Jeremy L. Samek
    Independence Law Center
    23 North Front Street
    Harrisburg, PA 17101
    John J. Bursch
    David A. Cortman
    Jeremy Tedesco
    Alliance Defending Freedom
    440 First Street NW, Suite 600
    Washington, DC 20001
    Counsel for Amicus Appellants/Cross Appellees
    Mike Kelly, Scott Perry, Lloyd Smucker, Glenn
    Thompson
    Steven W. Fitschen
    James A. Davids
    The National Legal Foundation
    2224 Virginia Beach Blvd, Suite 204
    Virginia Beach, VA 23454
    Counsel for Amicus Appellants/ Cross Appellee
    Congressional Prayer Caucus
    4
    Foundation, International
    Conference of Evangelical Chaplain
    Endorsers, National Legal Foundation,
    Veterans in Defense of Liberty
    Eric S. Baxter
    Chase T. Harrington
    Becket Fund for Religious Liberty
    1200 New Hampshire Avenue NW, Suite 700
    Washington, DC 20036
    Counsel for Proposed Amicus
    Aleph Institute
    Gregory E. Ostfeld
    Greenberg Traurig
    77 West Wacker Drive, Suite 3100
    Chicago, IL 60601
    Alan Hersh
    Greenberg Traurig
    300 West 6th Street, Suite 2050
    Austin, TX 78701
    Vitaliy Kats
    Greenberg Traurig
    101 East Kennedy Blvd., Suite 1900
    Tampa, FL 33602
    Gregory M. Lipper
    Clinton & Peed
    777 6th Street NW, 11th Floor
    Washington, DC 20001
    5
    Monica L. Miller
    American Humanist Association
    1821 Jefferson Place NW
    Washington, DC 20036
    Counsel for Amicus Appellees/ Cross Appellants
    Anti-Defamation League, Central Conference of
    American Rabbis, Hindu American Foundation,
    Interfaith Alliance Foundation, Jewish Social Policy
    Action Network, Keshet, Men of Reform Judaism,
    National Council of Jewish Women, Asian Pacific
    American Advocates, People for the American Way
    Foundation, Truah Rabbinic Call for Human Rights,
    Union for Reform Judaism, Women of Reform
    Judaism, American Humanist Association, Jamie
    Raskin, Representative Jared Huffman
    Patrick C. Elliott
    Colin E. McNamara
    Freedom from Religion Foundation
    10 North Henry Street
    Madison, WI 53703
    Counsel for Amicus Appellee
    Freedom from Religion Foundation
    ________________
    OPINION OF THE COURT
    ________________
    6
    AMBRO, Circuit Judge
    The Pennsylvania House of Representatives begins
    most legislative sessions with a prayer. The practice has two
    features that are challenged in this appeal. First, the House
    invites guest chaplains to offer the prayer, but it excludes
    nontheists (those who do not espouse belief in a god or gods,
    though not necessarily atheists) from serving as chaplains on
    the theory that “prayer” presupposes a higher power. Second,
    visitors to the House chamber pass a sign asking them to stand
    for the prayer, and the Speaker of the House requests that
    audience members “please rise” immediately before the
    prayer. At least once a House security guard pressured two
    visitors who refused to stand.
    A group of nontheists have challenged the theists-only
    policy under the Establishment, Free Exercise, Free Speech,1
    and Equal Protection Clauses2 of our Constitution. As to the
    Establishment Clause, we uphold the policy because only
    theistic prayer can satisfy the historical purpose of appealing
    for divine guidance in lawmaking, the basis for the Supreme
    1
    The First Amendment states in part that “Congress shall
    make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or
    prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom
    of speech . . . .” U.S. Const. amend. I. These limits on
    government action are applied to the states per Everson v. Bd.
    of Educ. of Ewing Twp., 
    330 U.S. 1
    , 15–16 (1947)
    (Establishment Clause); Cantwell v. Connecticut, 
    310 U.S. 296
    , 303–04 (1940) (Free Exercise Clause); and Gitlow v. New
    York, 
    268 U.S. 652
    , 666 (1925) (Free Speech Clause).
    2
    “[N]or shall any State . . . deny to any person within its
    jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws.” U.S. Const.
    amend. XIV, § 1.
    7
    Court taking as a given that prayer presumes a higher power.
    For the Free Exercise, Free Speech, and Equal Protection
    Clauses, we hold that legislative prayer is government speech
    not open to attack via those channels.
    The nontheists also challenge as unconstitutionally
    coercive the requests to “please rise” for the prayer. We hold
    that the single incident involving pressure from a security
    guard is moot. As for the sign outside the House chamber and
    the Speaker’s introductory request that guests “please rise,” we
    hold that these are not coercive.
    Thus we affirm in part and reverse in part the ruling of
    the District Court.
    Background
    A. Guest Chaplain Policy – Exclusion of Nontheists
    A member of the Pennsylvania House or a guest
    chaplain opens most legislative sessions with a prayer. A guest
    chaplain must be “a member of a regularly established church
    or religious organization.” The House defines “opening
    prayer” as a chance for its members “to seek divine
    intervention in their work and their lives.” Taken together, the
    House rules do not allow nontheists to give the opening prayer.
    Once a guest chaplain is selected, he or she is told to
    craft a prayer “respectful of all religious beliefs.” Fields v.
    Speaker of the Pa. House of Representatives, 
    251 F. Supp. 3d 772
    , 777 (M.D. Pa. 2017) (Fields I). The 203 members of the
    House “com[e] from a wide variety of faiths,” so “efforts to
    deliver an inter-faith prayer are greatly appreciated.” Fields v.
    Speaker of the Pa. House of Representatives, 
    327 F. Supp. 3d 748
    , 751 (M.D. Pa. 2018) (Fields II). Still, no House member
    reviews the prayer ahead of time.
    8
    From 2008 to 2016 the House prayer practice was as
    follows. For 678 legislative sessions, 575 began with a prayer.
    Of those prayers, 310 were offered by House members and 265
    by guest chaplains. Among the 265 guest chaplains were 238
    Christian clergy, 23 Jewish rabbis, three Muslim imams, and
    one monotheistic (yet otherwise unrecognizable) speaker.
    Fields I, 251 F. Supp. 3d at 777. The House branched out in
    2017 from the Abrahamic faiths with its first Sikh guest
    chaplain. Fields II, 327 F. Supp. 3d at 752.
    The plaintiffs here wish to offer the opening prayer as
    well. They represent a variety of nontheist organizations,
    including Secular Humanists, Unitarian Universalists, and
    Freethinkers.3 Most of these groups self-identify as “religious”
    organizations, and their practices parallel those of a church.
    For instance, they gather regularly to discuss their worldviews,
    study important texts, observe annual celebrations, and
    participate in community service. Fields I, 251 F. Supp. 3d at
    776. Their “clergy” even perform weddings and officiate at
    funerals. In short, they look and act like a church or synagogue
    in all ways but one: they do not profess belief in the existence
    of a higher power.
    For this reason alone, the House denied their requests to
    offer a prayer. Each group had proposed an uplifting secular
    message — a “nontheistic” prayer touching on themes such as
    equality, unity, decency, hope, peace, compassion, tolerance,
    and justice. Fields II, 327 F. Supp. 3d at 750. But because
    3
    While not identical, Secular Humanism and
    Freethought both posit that humans can be moral without any
    god; truth and morality should be based on logic, reason, and
    evidence, rather than on authority, tradition, or dogma. The
    nontheistic branches of Unitarian Universalism assert no creed,
    instead emphasizing tolerance and intellectual freedom.
    9
    their proposed invocations would not appeal to a “higher
    power,” they were turned away. Id. at 753.
    B. Prayer Practice – Request to “Please Rise”
    Two features of the prayer practice changed in response
    to this lawsuit. First, the Speaker of the House had asked
    guests to “please rise.” Id. In 2017 he elaborated that guests
    “please rise as able.” Id. Second, a sign outside the House
    chamber had explained that legislative sessions begin with a
    prayer and the Pledge of Allegiance, and it had asked that all
    guests “who are physically able” rise “during this order of
    business.” After this lawsuit, “physically” was dropped. Id. at
    754. On appeal, the parties dispute only whether the pre-2017
    practice was unconstitutionally coercive.
    The nontheists also challenge the coercive nature of one
    incident in 2012. After the Speaker’s general request to
    “please rise,” plaintiffs Brian Fields and Scott Rhoades
    remained seated. A House security guard singled them out and
    pressured them to stand. Id. at 753. However, they were not
    asked to leave, and no action was taken against them.
    C. Procedural History
    The leaders of several nontheist groups, along with the
    groups themselves, brought this suit under 
    42 U.S.C. § 1983
    against the Speaker of the House, the House Parliamentarian,
    and several House members. The plaintiffs took aim at the
    guest chaplain policy and the practice of asking that guests
    “please rise” for the prayer. First, they asserted that the policy
    of excluding nontheists from serving as guest chaplains
    violated the Establishment, Free Speech, Free Exercise, and
    Equal Protection Clauses. Second, they claimed that asking
    guests to “please rise” for the prayer was unconstitutionally
    coercive in violation of the Establishment Clause.
    10
    At the motion-to-dismiss stage, the District Court
    winnowed the claims to the alleged Establishment Clause
    violations. Reasoning that legislative prayer is government
    speech rather than speech by private citizens, the Court
    dismissed the claims brought under the Free Exercise, Free
    Speech, and Equal Protection Clauses. The Establishment
    Clause claims survived, however, because the Court needed a
    record at summary judgment to determine (1) “[w]hether
    history and tradition sanctify the House’s line of demarcation
    between theistic and nontheistic chaplains,” and (2) whether
    the Speaker’s request to “please rise” for the prayer was
    unconstitutionally coercive. Fields I, 251 F. Supp. 3d at 789.
    After discovery, both sides moved for summary
    judgment. The Court held that the guest chaplain policy
    violated the Establishment Clause and issued a permanent
    injunction. As for the requests to “please rise” for the opening
    prayer, it held that the current policy (amended in response to
    the lawsuit) was not coercive, but that the pre-2017 policy was.
    Both sides have appealed.
    Jurisdiction and Standard of Review
    The District Court had jurisdiction under 
    28 U.S.C. § 1331
    . We have jurisdiction per 
    28 U.S.C. § 1291
    . We review
    the Court’s findings of fact for clear error and its conclusions
    of law de novo. VICI Racing, LLC v. T-Mobile USA, Inc., 
    763 F.3d 273
    , 282–83 (3d Cir. 2014).
    11
    Discussion
    A. Guest Chaplain Policy – Establishment Clause
    Challenge
    Principally before us is whether the Pennsylvania House
    may intentionally exclude nontheists from offering prayers to
    open the legislative session. Because the House’s policy
    preferring theistic over nontheistic prayers fits squarely within
    the historical tradition of legislative prayer, we part with the
    District Court on this point and uphold the prayer policy.
    1. Pennsylvania’s Policy is Consistent with Historical
    Practice.
    (i) Background on the Historical Framework —
    History supplies our method of analyzing cases involving
    legislative prayer. In Establishment Clause challenges like
    this, we ask “whether the prayer practice” in question “fits
    within the tradition long followed in Congress and the state
    legislatures.” Town of Greece v. Galloway, 
    572 U.S. 565
    , 577
    (2014). The early legislative practice of those who drafted the
    Establishment Clause “reveal[s] their intent” as to its scope.
    Marsh v. Chambers, 
    463 U.S. 783
    , 790 (1983); see also New
    Doe Child #1 v. United States, 
    901 F.3d 1015
    , 1020 (8th Cir.
    2018) (“[H]istorical practices often reveal what the
    Establishment Clause was originally understood to permit.”).
    In other words, we employ “a history and tradition test.” Am.
    Legion v. Am. Humanist Ass’n, 
    139 S. Ct. 2067
    , 2092 (2019)
    (Kavanaugh, J., concurring); see also Freedom From Religion
    Found., Inc. v. Cty. of Lehigh, No. 17-3581, 
    2019 WL 3720709
    , — F.3d — (3d Cir. Aug. 8, 2019) (noting “the
    Supreme Court’s more recent focus on evaluating challenges
    to government action in the context of historical practices and
    understandings,” id. at *2, and explaining that “[a] practice’s
    12
    fit within our Nation’s public traditions may confirm its
    constitutionality,” id. at *5).
    Twice the Supreme Court has drawn on early
    congressional practice to uphold legislative prayer. It
    emphasized that Congress approved the draft of the First
    Amendment in the same week it established paid congressional
    chaplains to provide opening prayers. Marsh, 
    463 U.S. at 790
    ;
    see also Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 575 (“The First Congress
    made it an early item of business to appoint and pay official
    chaplains, and both the House and Senate have maintained the
    office virtually uninterrupted since that time.”). Congress
    approved theistic religious expression in other ways as well; a
    day after proposing the First Amendment, it “urged President
    Washington to proclaim ‘a day of public thanksgiving and
    prayer, to be observed by acknowledging with grateful hearts,
    the many and signal favours of Almighty God.’” Lynch v
    Donnelly, 
    465 U.S. 668
    , 675 n.2 (1984) (quoting A. Stokes &
    L. Pfeffer, Church and State in the United States 87 (rev. 1st
    ed. 1964)).
    These insights — paired with the general use of history
    as the decisional framework — paved the way to the holdings
    in both Marsh and Town of Greece. The former upheld
    Nebraska’s practice of offering legislative prayer by the same
    paid Presbyterian minister for 16 years. “In light of the
    unambiguous and unbroken history of more than 200 years,
    there can be no doubt that the practice of opening legislative
    sessions with prayer has become part of the fabric of our
    society.” Marsh, 
    463 U.S. at 792
    . Likewise, Town of Greece
    upheld sectarian (for example, invocations “in Jesus’ name”
    for a given sect) as opposed to ecumenical (for example,
    nonsectarian or nondenominational invocations to a “generic
    God”) legislative prayer by guest chaplains. Town of Greece,
    572 U.S. at 572–73. The Court refused to “sweep away” a
    13
    practice that “was accepted by the Framers and has withstood
    the critical scrutiny of time and political change.” Id. at 577.
    The D.C. Circuit recently deployed this historical
    framework to answer the same question before us today. See
    Barker v. Conroy, 
    921 F.3d 1118
     (D.C. Cir. 2019) (Tatel, J.).
    There it considered the U.S. House of Representatives’
    practice of excluding nontheists from offering legislative
    prayers. Following the path charted by Marsh and Town of
    Greece, the Court defined its task as “determin[ing] whether
    that practice falls within the tradition the Supreme Court has
    recognized as consistent with the Establishment Clause.” Id.
    at 1130. Put another way, “does the House’s decision to limit
    the opening prayer to religious prayer fit ‘within the tradition
    long followed in Congress and the state legislatures’?” Id.
    (quoting Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 577). The answer was
    “yes.” Id.
    Even more recently, the Supreme Court has expanded
    its historical framework beyond the confines of legislative
    prayer. In rejecting an Establishment Clause challenge to a
    Christian cross commemorating World War I on state property,
    the Court held that the memorial “must be viewed in [its]
    historical context.” Am. Legion, 
    139 S. Ct. at 2074
    . It also
    announced “a presumption of constitutionality for
    longstanding monuments, symbols, and practices.” 
    Id. at 2082
    .
    Indeed, our Court just reiterated the “strong presumption of
    constitutionality” for practices like the one before us. See
    Freedom From Religion Found., 
    2019 WL 3720709
    , at *3
    (quoting Am. Legion, 
    139 S. Ct. at 2085
    ). That presumption
    applies to the longstanding practice of theistic prayer in the
    United States; since the first congressional prayers in 1789, the
    U.S. House of Representatives “has never had an openly atheist
    or agnostic guest chaplain.” Barker, 921 F.3d at 1122.
    14
    With this background on the historical framework —
    and bearing in mind the thumb on the scale for the
    constitutionality of longstanding practices like that of
    Pennsylvania House, see Am. Legion, 
    139 S. Ct. at
    2085 — we
    turn to two reasons why Pennsylvania’s practice is historically
    sound. First, only theistic prayer can satisfy all the traditional
    purposes of legislative prayer. Second, the Supreme Court has
    long taken as given that prayer presumes invoking a higher
    power.
    (ii) Purposes of Legislative Prayer — Legislative
    prayer has historically served many purposes, both secular and
    religious. Because only theistic prayer can achieve them all,
    the historical tradition supports the House’s choice to restrict
    prayer to theistic invocations.
    To be sure, legislative prayer achieves several secular
    purposes. It solemnizes the occasion by “lend[ing] gravity” to
    the proceedings and placing legislators in a “deliberative frame
    of mind.” Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 587, 570. It provides
    a moment of “quiet reflection” that “sets the mind to a higher
    purpose.” Id. at 587. It unifies lawmakers by inviting them “to
    reflect upon shared ideals and common ends before they
    embark on the fractious business of governing.” Id. at 583.
    And it stresses the values of justice, peace, and wisdom. Id.
    No surprise, then, that even the D.C. Circuit in Barker
    saw it was “at least plausible” that the word “prayer” could
    “encompass[] a secular invocation.” 921 F.3d at 1125.
    Channeling these secular purposes, at least seven state
    legislative chambers (including the Pennsylvania Senate) have
    begun to allow nontheistic invocations. See Br. of Amici
    Curiae U.S. Reps. Jared Huffman & Jaime Raskin at 5–11.
    But, as a matter of traditional practice, a petition to
    human wisdom and the power of science does not capture the
    15
    full sense of “prayer,” historically understood. At bottom,
    legislative prayers seek “divine guidance” in lawmaking.
    Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 570; Marsh, 
    463 U.S. at 792
    . See
    generally Br. of Amici Curiae Pa. Members of Congress at 4–
    15. They also allow the legislature to “acknowledge the place
    religion holds in the lives of many private citizens.” Town of
    Greece, 572 U.S. at 587; see also Am. Legion, 
    139 S. Ct. at 2089
     (“The practice begun by the First Congress stands out as
    . . . a recognition of the important role that religion plays in the
    lives of many Americans. Where . . . practices with a
    longstanding history follow in that tradition, they are likewise
    constitutional.”). And they “connect [lawmakers] to a tradition
    dating to the time of the Framers,” Town of Greece, 572 U.S.
    at 588, one that has always included a higher power.
    Finally, prayers “accommodate the spiritual needs of
    lawmakers.” Id. Though this purpose is now accepted by the
    Supreme Court, see id., one might wonder whether a religious
    minister can accommodate the spiritual needs of a “secular
    agnostic” member of the Pennsylvania House, see Fields II,
    327 F. Supp. 3d at 763, or vice versa. Or, for that matter, can
    a Catholic priest in the U.S. Senate accommodate the spiritual
    needs of Chuck Schumer, or a Jewish rabbi those of Mitt
    Romney? These questions are as old as the Republic, but they
    have been settled since the Founding. In the Continental
    Congress, John Jay and John Rutledge opposed legislative
    prayer on the theory that the delegates were “so divided in
    religious sentiments” that they “could not join in the same act
    of worship.” Marsh, 
    463 U.S. at 791
     (quotations omitted). The
    two future Chief Justices could not see what an Episcopalian
    minister could possibly offer a Presbyterian or
    Congregationalist lawmaker. Their view lost out, however,
    when Samuel Adams countered that “he was no bigot” and
    would gladly “hear a prayer from a gentleman of piety and
    virtue,” no matter his denomination. 
    Id. at 792
     (quotations
    omitted); see also Am. Legion, 
    139 S. Ct. at 2088
    . Hence we
    16
    take as given that an invocation by a prayer-giver of one
    theistic faith can accommodate the spiritual needs of listeners
    of other theistic faiths.
    In sum, the view that prayer “necessarily requires that a
    ‘higher power’ be invoked” may be “overly narrow” by current
    standards. Williamson v. Brevard Cty., 
    276 F. Supp. 3d 1260
    ,
    1281 (M.D. Fla. 2017), aff’d in part on other grounds, 
    928 F.3d 1296
     (11th Cir. 2019). But modern, evolving standards are not
    our lodestar when evaluating a practice like this; instead, past
    is prologue for our inquiry. And history tells us that only
    theistic invocations can achieve all the purposes of legislative
    prayer. Thus the historical tradition supports the House’s
    choice to restrict its invocations to theistic prayer.
    (iii) “Prayer” Presumes a Higher Power. — The
    Supreme Court has long taken as given that prayer presumes a
    higher power. To begin, the Court in Marsh described
    legislative prayer as “invok[ing] Divine guidance on a public
    body entrusted with making the laws,” 
    463 U.S. at 792
    , and
    quoted with approval Justice Douglas’s statement that “we are
    a religious people whose institutions presuppose a Supreme
    Being,” 
    id.
     (quoting Zorach v. Clauson, 
    343 U.S. 306
    , 313
    (1952)). Even the dissent in Marsh stressed that “prayer is
    fundamentally and necessarily religious,” and distinguished it
    from a nontheistic “moral sense” or “aesthetic feeling.” Id. at
    810 (Brennan, J., dissenting) (quotations omitted).
    The assumption that prayer must be theistic apparently
    persuaded then-Judge Ruth Bader Ginsburg that Congress’s
    practice of excluding nontheists from offering opening prayers
    did not violate the Establishment Clause. See Kurtz v. Baker,
    
    829 F.2d 1133
    , 1147 (D.C. Cir. 1987) (R.B. Ginsburg, J.,
    dissenting). Although the challenge was dismissed on standing
    grounds, she wrote separately that she would have upheld
    Congress’s policy on the merits. “The common feature” of
    17
    legislative prayer was “the invocation of ‘Divine guidance.’”
    
    Id.
     (quoting Marsh, 
    463 U.S. at 792
    ). Thus we believe later-
    Justice Ginsburg would have rejected the challenger’s “claim
    of a constitutional right not to be excluded, because he is a
    nontheist, from the opportunity” to offer a prayer. Id. at 1146.
    More recently, the notion that prayer is definitionally
    theistic suffuses the opinions in Town of Greece. The majority
    opinion described prayer as a chance to “show respect for the
    divine,” 572 U.S. at 584, and to “address [one’s] own God or
    gods,” id. at 582. Prayer is an “acknowledgment[] of the
    divine,” id. at 587, or of “belief in a higher power,” id. at 591.
    It is a “reference to the sacred,” id. at 581, or, more simply, it
    is “religious worship,” id. at 588 (quotations omitted). Even
    the dissent cast legislative prayers as “[c]eremonial references
    to the divine,” id. at 635 (Kagan, J., dissenting), and,
    pejoratively, as “government-sponsored worship,” id. at 628.
    Urging nonsectarian prayer, it asserted that an ecumenical
    message would still “unite[]” listeners with “a respect paid
    higher providence.” Id. at 632 (quoting Joyner v. Forsyth
    Cty., 
    653 F.3d 341
    , 347 (4th Cir. 2011)).
    Just as Marsh persuaded then-Judge Ginsburg that
    Congress’s policy excluding nontheistic prayers was
    permissible, Marsh and Town of Greece together convinced the
    D.C. Circuit to hold that the policy did not violate the
    Establishment Clause. See Barker, 921 F.3d at 1121. It
    explained that Marsh “took as a given the religious nature of
    legislative prayer,” and quoted that “we are a religious people
    whose institutions presuppose a Supreme Being.” Id. at 1130
    (quoting Marsh, 
    463 U.S. at 792
    ). Turning to Town of Greece,
    the Court saw the same assumption that prayer requires a deity,
    stressing Town of Greece’s statement that “legislative
    prayer, while religious in nature, has long been understood as
    compatible with the Establishment Clause.” Id. at 1131
    (quoting Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 575) (emphasis added by
    18
    Barker). Since Barker, the Supreme Court has underscored the
    point yet again: “prayer is by definition religious.” Am.
    Legion, 
    139 S. Ct. at 2087
    .
    Recognizing that prayer has traditionally presumed a
    higher power does not amount to “instituting a religious
    orthodoxy.” Dissenting Op. at 10. Our dissenting colleague
    thinks otherwise; in his view, accepting that prayer has (until
    very recently) been an entreaty to a divine being is tantamount
    to “the government actively lend[ing] its power and prestige to
    the religious theory that a ‘higher power’ or God indeed
    exists.” Id. at 10. But if that were so, then we would have to
    rethink settled law upholding, for example, the motto “In God
    We Trust” on our coinage. See, e.g., New Doe Child #1, 901
    F.3d at 1019 (8th Cir. 2018); Mayle v. United States, 
    891 F.3d 680
    , 684–86 (7th Cir. 2018); Newdow v. Peterson, 
    753 F.3d 105
    , 108 (2d Cir. 2014) (per curiam); Newdow v. Lefevre, 
    598 F.3d 638
    , 645 (9th Cir. 2010); Gaylor v. United States, 
    74 F.3d 214
    , 217–18 (10th Cir. 1996); O’Hair v. Murray, 
    588 F.2d 1144
    , 1144 (5th Cir. 1979) (per curiam). We would also need
    to scrub the phrase “under God” from the Pledge of Allegiance
    — again upending established precedent. See, e.g., Freedom
    From Religion Found. v. Hanover Sch. Dist., 
    626 F.3d 1
    , 6 n.13
    (1st Cir. 2010); Croft v. Perry, 
    624 F.3d 157
    , 166 (5th Cir.
    2010); Newdow v. Rio Linda Union Sch. Dist., 
    597 F.3d 1007
    ,
    1037 (9th Cir. 2010); Myers v. Loudoun Cty. Pub. Sch., 
    418 F.3d 395
    , 408 (4th Cir. 2005); Sherman v. Cmty. Consol. Sch.
    Dist. 21, 
    980 F.2d 437
    , 445 (7th Cir. 1992); see also Elk Grove
    Unified Sch. Dist. v. Newdow, 
    542 U.S. 1
    , 18 (2004)
    (Rehnquist, C.J., concurring in the judgment). Instead of
    rocking the constitutional boat, today we merely observe what
    the Supreme Court has long taken as given: that prayer
    traditionally presumes a higher power. Because this notion
    flows from the historical understanding and practice of
    legislative prayer, it lends further support to the policy of the
    Pennsylvania House.
    19
    Nor is our observation about traditional prayer
    “tantamount to a holding that legislative prayer must be theistic
    in nature.” Dissenting Op. at 8 n.4 (emphasis in text). A
    legislative body is free to open its sessions with secular
    invocations. We hold only that it is not required to do so.
    (iv) Effect of Challengers’ Status as “Religions” —
    The nontheistic organizations that brought this challenge may
    be “religions” for First Amendment purposes. See Torcaso v.
    Watkins, 
    367 U.S. 488
    , 495 n.11 (1961). Indeed, the Supreme
    Court “has moved considerably beyond the wholly theistic
    interpretation” of the term “religion.”             Africa v.
    Commonwealth of Pennsylvania, 
    662 F.2d 1025
    , 1031 (3d Cir.
    1981).     Its understanding of “religion” now “includes
    nontheistic and atheistic beliefs, as well as theistic ones.”
    Kaufman v. McCaughtry, 
    419 F.3d 678
    , 682 (7th Cir. 2005);
    accord Dissenting Op. at 1.
    Still, the policy of the Pennsylvania House does not
    transgress the rule against favoring “one religion over another,
    or religion over irreligion.” McCreary Cty. v. ACLU of Ky.,
    
    545 U.S. 844
    , 875 (2005). That is because “whether atheism
    is a ‘religion’ for First Amendment purposes is a . . . different
    question than whether its adherents believe in a supreme
    being.” Kaufman, 
    419 F.3d at 681
    . And only the latter
    question — the existence of a high power to whom one can
    pray for divine guidance in lawmaking — is a necessary
    element of traditional legislative prayer. The nontheists here
    may be members of “religions” for First Amendment purposes,
    but, because they do not proclaim the existence of a higher
    power, they cannot offer religious prayer in the historical
    sense. Cf. Williamson, 
    928 F.3d 1296
     (concluding that policy
    of chaplain selection barring prayers from nontheistic Secular
    Humanists, as well as from Rastafarians, Deists, Wiccans, and
    Hindus, 
    id.
     at 1313–14, was unconstitutional discrimination
    “on the basis of religion,” id. at 1316, but only as against the
    20
    theistic religions, id. at 1311, while refusing to decide “whether
    atheists and secular humanists must be allowed to deliver non-
    theistic invocations,” id. at 1299, even as the Court recognized
    that atheistic beliefs constitute a “religion” for Establishment
    Clause purposes, id. at 1300). And because history guides our
    inquiry in matters of legislative prayer, the Pennsylvania
    House may insist on traditional, theistic prayers.
    In doing so, the House does not “impermissibly direct[]
    or control[] the content of the prayers delivered by guest
    chaplains.” Dissenting Op. at 13. To the contrary, no House
    member reviews a guest chaplain’s prayer ahead of time.
    Chaplains are simply instructed to be “respectful of all
    religious beliefs,” Fields I, 251 F. Supp. 3d at 777, and are
    encouraged to “deliver an inter-faith prayer,” Fields II, 327 F.
    Supp. 3d at 751.
    2. Further Exclusions are Impermissible.
    Our decision today does not open the door to more
    extreme exclusions. Neutrality principles emanating from
    Marsh and Town of Greece hold the historical framework in
    check and prevent grandfathering antiquated discrimination
    into the present day.
    Taken too far, importing historical legislative-prayer
    practices would justify excluding all sorts of theists. For
    instance, Justice Scalia maintained that, in matters of “public
    acknowledgment of religious belief,” the nation’s “historical
    practices” demonstrate that the government could exclude not
    only “devout atheists” but also “polytheists” (those who
    believe in multiple gods). McCreary Cty., 
    545 U.S. at 893
    (Scalia, J., dissenting). In the same vein, the Fourth Circuit has
    approved the exclusion of polytheist guest chaplains from
    legislative prayer. Simpson v. Chesterfield Cty. Bd. of
    Supervisors, 
    404 F.3d 276
    , 286 (4th Cir. 2005) (Wilkinson, J.).
    21
    There a county opened its board meetings with prayers from
    the leaders of “monotheistic congregations” but denied a
    Wiccan witch the chance to offer a prayer. 
    Id. at 284
    . The
    Court noted the more restrictive practice approved in Marsh —
    one permanent Presbyterian minister for 16 years. Compared
    to that baseline, it reasoned, the county’s monotheists-only rule
    was “an indisputably broad and inclusive legislative invocation
    practice.” 
    Id.
     at 285 n.4. “[T]he practice here is in many ways
    more inclusive than that approved by the Marsh Court.” 
    Id. at 285
    . As a result, even after a lawmaking body opens its door
    to guest chaplains, it may still opt not “to go beyond the
    monotheistic tradition.” 
    Id. at 286
    . But see Williamson, 928
    F.3d at 1315 (striking down county policy of chaplain selection
    that “categorically exclude[d] certain faiths — some
    monotheistic and apparently all polytheistic ones — based on
    their belief systems”).
    The Pennsylvania House pushes this exclusionary logic
    to the extreme, claiming that a prayer practice is permissible
    unless it allows chaplains from only a single sect. The House
    emphasizes “legislatures’ long history of turning away all but
    a few faiths,” and urges that “[h]istory confirms the
    constitutionality of prayer practices far more exclusive” than
    the theists-only rule here. Opening Br. of Appellants/Cross-
    Appellees at 40. So long as two sects are represented — even
    to the exclusion of all others — the House argues that the
    prayer practice is constitutional. After all, by approving the
    sole use of a chaplain from a single sect for 16 years, Marsh
    was even more exclusive. Cf. Ctr. for Inquiry, Inc. v. Marion
    Circuit Court Clerk, 
    758 F.3d 869
    , 874 (7th Cir. 2014)
    (Easterbrook, J.) (dictum) (“Marsh and Greece show that a
    government may, consistent with the First Amendment, open
    legislative sessions with Christian prayers while not inviting
    leaders of other religions.”).
    22
    What the House sees as the outer bound of its
    constitutional authority, its opponents abhor as the bottom of a
    slippery slope greased by our decision today. Given the specter
    of the House’s proposed two-sect rule, amici on the side of the
    nontheists warn that their exclusion could justify barring the
    legislative pulpit to other religious minorities as well. See Br.
    of Amici Curiae Anti-Defamation League et al. at 6. If the
    House may rely on historical practice to exclude nontheists,
    may it also do so to prohibit prayers by Hindus, Jews, and
    Quakers?
    Plainly not. To begin, our decision today rests on only
    two pillars: (1) the purpose of legislative prayer is to invoke
    divine guidance, and (2) “prayer” presupposes a higher power.
    Neither supports excluding any group of theists. And contrary
    to our dissenting colleague’s assertion, our reasoning today
    could not be twisted to exclude Buddhists — an outcome we
    agree would be “unconscionable.” Dissenting Op. at 7; see,
    e.g., Alex Rogers, Dalai Lama Gives Prayer on Senate Floor,
    Time (Mar. 6, 2014), https://time.com/14056/dalai-lama-
    senate-prayer/ (recounting that the Dalai Lama opened his
    invocation before the U.S. Senate in 2014 with the exhortation
    to “pray to Buddha and all other gods”).
    Next, the two-sect rule is unworkable. At what level of
    generality are we to define a sect? Is “Christianity” a sect?
    Compare Lund v. Rowan Cty., 
    863 F.3d 268
    , 280 (4th Cir.
    2017) (en banc) (disapproving of government’s alignment with
    the “particular faith” of Christianity), with Am. Legion, 
    139 S. Ct. at 2096
     (Thomas, J., concurring in the judgment)
    (“Christianity is not a ‘sect.’”), and 
    id.
     at 2107 n.7 (Ginsburg,
    J.,   dissenting)     (“Christianity     comprises      numerous
    denominations.”). If not, does Protestantism comprise one sect
    or many? Is the Anglican Communion a single sect despite
    theological divisions among its churches?
    23
    More fundamentally, the two-sect rule is inconsistent
    with nondiscrimination principles in Marsh and Town of
    Greece. Per Marsh, the “prayer opportunity” may not be
    “exploited to proselytize or advance any one, or to disparage
    any other, faith or belief.” Marsh, 
    463 U.S. at
    794–95; see also
    Am. Legion, 
    139 S. Ct. at 2088
     (noting the First Congress saw
    that “legislative prayer needed to be inclusive rather than
    divisive”).
    As to the selection of the prayer-giver, Marsh instructed
    that a chaplain’s appointment could not “stem[] from an
    impermissible motive.” 
    463 U.S. at 793
    . The Eleventh Circuit
    has read Marsh’s “impermissible motive” standard to
    “prohibit[] purposeful discrimination.” Pelphrey v. Cobb Cty.,
    
    547 F.3d 1263
    , 1281 (11th Cir. 2008). The Court concluded
    this rule had been violated when the phone book used by a
    county in Georgia to invite guest chaplains contained “a long
    and continuous line through certain categories of faiths,”
    including Muslims and Latter-day Saints. 
    Id. at 1282
    . “The
    categorical exclusion of certain faiths based on their beliefs,”
    it explained, “is unconstitutional.” 
    Id.
     This statement is
    enough to foreclose the House’s two-sect rule.
    But, as we have explained, a prayer by a Muslim is
    different in kind from one by a nontheist — different enough
    that a legislature may permissibly exclude the latter but not the
    former. The Eleventh Circuit itself sees discrimination against
    theists as unlike discrimination against nontheists. The Court
    recently drew on its rule that legislators “may not categorically
    exclude from consideration speakers from a religion simply
    because they do not like the nature of its beliefs,” Williamson,
    928 F.3d at 1299, to strike down a county’s invocation policy
    of “favoring some monotheistic religions over others and
    disfavoring and excluding — at least — religions that are
    polytheistic, pantheistic [belief that the entire universe and God
    are one — “God is everything and everything is God,” Africa,
    24
    
    662 F.2d at
    1033 n.16 (quotation omitted)], or otherwise
    outside of the ‘mainstream,’” Williamson, 928 F.3d at 1311.
    But it stopped short of applying the same rule to the categorical
    exclusion of prayers by nontheists, refusing to decide “whether
    the [c]ounty is obliged to allow . . . atheists and Secular
    Humanists . . . the opportunity to deliver an invocation at the
    start of one of its board meetings.” Id. at 1316.
    Turning to the opinion in Town of Greece, three features
    relating to nondiscrimination stand out. First, it noted that an
    1853 study by Congress of its own prayer practice found that
    “no faith was excluded by law, nor any favored.” Town of
    Greece, 572 U.S. at 576; see Am. Legion, 
    139 S. Ct. at 2089
    (“The practice begun by the First Congress stands out as . . . an
    honest      endeavor       to    achieve     inclusivity     and
    nondiscrimination . . . .”). Such a finding is inconsistent with
    the House’s proposed two-sect rule. As to nontheists,
    however, we doubt whether the Congress of 1853 understood
    atheism as a “faith,” given that its study was from an era that
    still defined “religion” as “one’s views of his relations to his
    Creator.” Cf. Davis v. Beason, 
    133 U.S. 333
    , 342 (1890).
    Second, as for the specific prayer practice at issue in
    Town of Greece, the Court stressed that the town’s selection of
    guest chaplains was admirably inclusive. “The town at no
    point excluded or denied an opportunity to a would-be prayer
    giver.” Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 571. “[A] minister or
    layperson of any persuasion, including an atheist, could give
    the invocation.” Id. Even the D.C. Circuit, in upholding
    Congress’s theists-only rule, marveled that the practice in
    Town of Greece was “significantly more inclusive than the one
    in Marsh.” Barker, 921 F.3d at 1131.
    The en banc Fourth Circuit contrasted the inclusivity in
    Town of Greece with the comparatively “rigid, restrictive
    practice” of a North Carolina county in which only the county
    25
    commissioners (all Christians) were permitted to offer the
    prayer. See Lund, 863 F.3d at 282. “By opening its prayer
    opportunity to all comers, the [T]own [of Greece] cultivated an
    atmosphere of greater tolerance and inclusion.” Id. The Fourth
    Circuit struck down the county’s practice as falling short of the
    “flexible, inclusive approach” upheld in Town of Greece. Id.
    By allowing guest chaplains of any theistic tradition, the
    Pennsylvania House is more inclusive than the county in Lund;
    by excluding nontheists, the House is less inclusive than the
    town in Town of Greece, at least as a facial matter, but
    permissibly so.
    Third, Town of Greece held that a guest chaplain policy
    resulting in prayers of predominantly one religion is
    permissible so long as the selection process is not
    discriminatory:
    That nearly all of the congregations in
    town turned out to be Christian does not
    reflect an aversion or bias on the part of
    town leaders against minority faiths. So
    long as the town maintains a policy of
    nondiscrimination, the Constitution does
    not require it to search beyond its borders
    for non-Christian prayer givers in an
    effort to achieve religious balancing.
    Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 585–86 (emphasis added). Justice
    Alito’s concurrence reinforced these nondiscrimination
    principles. The town’s failure to invite the rabbis of certain
    Jewish synagogues “was at worst careless, and it was not done
    with a discriminatory intent.” Id. at 597 (Alito, J., concurring).
    “I would view this case very differently if the omission of these
    synagogues were intentional.” Id. Likewise, the Sixth Circuit
    has taken the “policy of nondiscrimination” language in Town
    of Greece to mean that a policy of prayer-giver selection must
    26
    be “facially neutral.” Bormuth v. Cty. of Jackson, 
    870 F.3d 494
    , 514 (6th Cir. 2017) (en banc).
    There appears to be a dispute brewing over whether a
    “policy of nondiscrimination” is needed to render a prayer
    practice constitutional. For Justice Kagan, “neutrality” is a
    “constitutional requirement” that calls for “pluralism and
    inclusion.” Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 616 (Kagan, J.,
    dissenting); see also Am. Legion, 
    139 S. Ct. at 2094
     (Kagan, J.,
    concurring) (stressing “the values of neutrality and inclusion
    that the First Amendment demands”). For Justice Kavanaugh,
    by contrast, equal treatment is only one way to salvage a
    challenged practice; even a non-neutral practice passes muster
    if it is “not coercive” and is “rooted in history and tradition.”
    
    Id. at 2093
     (Kavanaugh, J., concurring).
    We need not resolve that issue. The D.C. Circuit in
    Barker sidestepped the nondiscrimination requirement as
    applied to nontheists. “[A]lthough the [Supreme] Court has
    warned against discriminating among religions,” the Circuit
    Court reasoned, “it has never suggested that legislatures must
    allow secular as well as religious prayer.” Barker, 921 F.3d at
    1131. We share that view.
    3. Further Inclusion is Not Needed.
    Before moving on from the Establishment Clause claim,
    we explain why a supercharged nondiscrimination rule does
    not apply to legislative prayer. To begin, “there is no single
    formula for resolving Establishment Clause challenges.” Am.
    Legion, 
    139 S. Ct. at 2090
     (Breyer, J., concurring). Instead,
    legislative prayer “fits into a special nook — a narrow space
    tightly sealed off from otherwise applicable [F]irst
    [A]mendment doctrine.” Kurtz, 
    829 F.2d at 1147
     (R.B.
    Ginsburg, J., dissenting). And on this doctrinal island,
    27
    principles of neutrality must not be so onerous that they signal
    the end of legislative prayer altogether.
    Taken too far, a nondiscrimination rule in legislative
    prayer provides a heckler’s veto to voices on the fringe. If, in
    the name of nondiscrimination, the House must abide prayers
    from nontheists, Satanists, and groups that deride religion, it
    will stop accepting guest chaplains altogether. This will result
    in less diversity of religious expression — a “particularly
    perverse result.” Simpson, 
    404 F.3d at 287
     (upholding
    exclusion of Wiccan from prayer practice to avoid “push[ing]
    localities intent on avoiding litigation to select only one
    minister from only one faith”); cf. Freedom from Religion
    Found., Inc. v. City of Warren, 
    707 F.3d 686
    , 694 (6th Cir.
    2013) (noting, in the context of religious holiday displays, that
    “requiring governments to add all comers to the mix” would
    create a “poison pill”). In matters of promoting religious
    diversity, the perfect should not be the enemy of the good.
    A nondiscrimination rule that regulates guest-chaplain
    programs out of existence would also be a step backward as a
    constitutional matter. Under a permanent-chaplain model, in
    which “the governmental body hires a faith leader (necessarily
    of one faith) to say the prayers,” the risk of an impermissible
    endorsement of religion “grows, rather than diminishes.”
    Bormuth, 870 F.3d at 523 (Sutton, J., concurring). By contrast,
    the use of guest chaplains weighs in favor of constitutionality
    because it promotes diversity of religious expression. See
    Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 632 (Kagan, J., dissenting)
    (urging legislatures to invite “clergy of many faiths to serve as
    chaplains” so that “the government does not identify itself with
    one religion”). Congress’s adoption of a guest-chaplain
    program in the mid-1800s allowed it to hear an opening prayer
    from a Jewish rabbi as early as 1860 and, eventually, prayers
    from Muslims, Hindus, and Buddhists. Am. Legion, 
    139 S. Ct. at 2088
    .
    28
    Finally, a nondiscrimination rule that parks guest-
    chaplain programs would contrast incongruously with
    permissive rules for permanent chaplains. In the world of
    permanent chaplains, a legislature may leave one paid chaplain
    from a single denomination in place for decades. See Marsh,
    
    463 U.S. at 793
    . For guest chaplains, however, a stringent rule
    against exclusions would mean a legislature would have to
    accept all comers. Cf. Dissenting Op. at 15. This asymmetry
    makes little sense.
    B. Guest Chaplain Policy – Free Speech Challenge
    The nontheists argue that the House has violated their
    free-speech rights by allowing only theistic prayers. Because
    legislative prayer is government speech, we affirm the District
    Court’s dismissal of that claim.
    1. Legislative Prayer Is Government Speech.
    Like the District Court, we conclude that legislative
    prayer is government speech. (This conclusion bears not only
    on the free-speech claim, but also on the free-exercise and
    equal-protection claims.) The Supreme Court has identified
    several factors relevant for distinguishing government speech
    from private speech, including a reasonable observer’s
    perception of the speaker and the government’s control over
    the message. See, e.g., Walker v. Texas Div., Sons of
    Confederate Veterans, Inc., 
    135 S. Ct. 2239
    , 2248–50 (2015).
    The prayer here falls on the government side of the line.
    To begin, legislative prayer is expression by a
    government. It is “symbolic expression,” Town of Greece, 572
    U.S. at 575, that allows lawmakers to convey their own
    message by “show[ing] who and what they are,” id. at 588. A
    legislative prayer, even one offered by a guest chaplain, is a
    “chance to pray on behalf of the government.” Turner v. City
    29
    Council of Fredericksburg, 
    534 F.3d 352
    , 356 (4th Cir. 2008)
    (O’Connor, J.) (emphasis added). The government may
    control “what is or is not expressed” in order to “convey its
    own message.” Simpson, 
    404 F.3d at 288
     (quotations omitted).
    The prayer is “what a chosen agent of the government says as
    part of the government’s own operations.” Ctr. for Inquiry,
    758 F.3d at 874. At bottom, the government is the speaker.
    The government is the listener as well. “The principal
    audience for these invocations is not, indeed, the public but
    lawmakers themselves.” Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 587.
    Unlike prayer in schools, in the legislative setting “government
    officials invoke spiritual inspiration entirely for their own
    benefit.” Lee v. Weisman, 
    505 U.S. 577
    , 630 n.8 (1992)
    (Souter, J., concurring); see also Freedom From Religion
    Found., Inc. v. Chino Valley Unified Sch. Dist. Bd. of Educ.,
    
    896 F.3d 1132
    , 1142 (9th Cir. 2018) (explaining that legislative
    prayer is “directed at lawmakers themselves”). This is so even
    though the prayer here is given by a member of the public who
    faces the public — the same conditions that existed in Town of
    Greece. “[T]he government speech doctrine may apply even
    when the government uses other parties to express its
    message.” Sutliffe v. Epping Sch. Dist., 
    584 F.3d 314
    , 330 (1st
    Cir. 2009). As a largely internal matter — by lawmakers and
    primarily for lawmakers — legislative prayer receives double
    deference.
    Legislative prayer is government speech even though
    some limits exist on what the government may say. Legislative
    prayers may not “proselytize” or “denigrate” any faith, see
    Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 585; Marsh, 
    463 U.S. at
    794–95,
    and the government may not “mandate a civic religion” by
    requiring that guest chaplains offer only nonsectarian prayer,
    Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 581. But these restrictions all
    flow from the Establishment Clause. Because “government
    speech must comport with the Establishment Clause” anyway,
    30
    Pleasant Grove City v. Summum, 
    555 U.S. 460
    , 469 (2009),
    any Establishment Clause–based limits do not change the
    conclusion that legislative prayer is government speech.
    Supporting this conclusion is a recent three-Justice
    dissent from a denial of certiorari that cited Marsh as an
    example of “government-sponsored prayer” in which “the
    government itself is engaging in religious speech.” See Morris
    Cty. Bd. of Chosen Freeholders v. Freedom From Religion
    Found., 
    139 S. Ct. 909
    , 910–11 (2019) (Kavanaugh, J., joined
    by Justices Alito and Gorsuch, dissenting from denial of
    certiorari). And, as explained above, the Seventh and Fourth
    Circuits agree. See Ctr. for Inquiry, 758 F.3d at 874; Simpson,
    
    404 F.3d at 288
    .
    Evidently, only one Court disagrees. The District Court
    in Williamson was “not persuaded that legislative prayer
    claims are necessarily subject to analysis under only the
    Establishment Clause.” Williamson, 276 F. Supp. 3d at 1294.
    Instead, it explained that the availability of a potential cause of
    action “depends on the circumstances of each case and the
    nature of the claim being asserted.” Id. On appeal, however,
    the Eleventh Circuit refused to adopt this case-by-case
    approach. See Williamson, 928 F.3d at 1316 (“The trial court’s
    injunction goes too far and says too much.”). We follow suit
    and join the Seventh and Fourth Circuits, as well as at least
    three Supreme Court Justices, in holding that legislative prayer
    is government speech.
    2. The Free Speech Clause Does Not Regulate
    Government Speech.
    Because legislative prayer is government speech, the
    analysis is straightforward. “[T]he Free Speech Clause does
    not regulate government speech.” Matal v. Tam, 
    137 S. Ct. 1744
    , 1757 (2017) (quoting Summum, 
    555 U.S. at 467
    ). The
    31
    nontheists’ claim thus fails. See Simpson, 
    404 F.3d at
    287–88
    (same); see also Kurtz, 
    829 F.2d at 1147
     (R.B. Ginsburg, J.,
    dissenting) (predicting that the Supreme Court would reject a
    free-speech challenge to Congress’s theists-only chaplain
    policy and dismissing challenger’s argument to the contrary as
    exhibiting “little realism and large indulgence in wishful
    thinking”). As a result, we affirm the District Court on this
    issue.
    C. Guest Chaplain Policy – Free Exercise Challenge
    The nontheists also challenge the guest chaplain policy
    on free-exercise grounds. Because legislative prayer is
    government speech, the Free Exercise Clause does not apply,
    and the nontheists’ free-exercise claim fails. See Simpson, 
    404 F.3d at
    287–88 (same). Judge Niemeyer concurred in Simpson
    to stress this point: “when members of a governmental body
    participate in a prayer for themselves and do not impose it on
    or prescribe it for the people, the religious liberties secured to
    the people by the First Amendment are not directly
    implicated.” 
    Id. at 289
     (Niemeyer, J., concurring). In a
    subsequent Fourth Circuit case, retired Justice O’Connor
    (sitting by designation) made a similar point: although the
    challenger refused to offer a legislative prayer “in the manner
    that the government had proscribed,” he remained “free to pray
    on his own behalf, in nongovernmental endeavors, in the
    manner dictated by his conscience.” Turner, 
    534 F.3d at 356
    .
    Because the free-exercise challenge fails, we affirm the District
    Court as well.
    D. Guest Chaplain Policy – Equal Protection Challenge
    The nontheists argue that the House’s theists-only guest
    chaplain policy violates their equal-protection rights. But
    private citizens “have no personal interest in government
    speech on which to base an equal protection claim.” Johnson
    32
    v. Poway Unified Sch. Dist., 
    658 F.3d 954
    , 970 (9th Cir. 2011)
    (citing Downs v. L.A. Unified Sch. Dist., 
    228 F.3d 1003
    , 1017
    (9th Cir. 2000)). “It is the very business of government to favor
    and disfavor points of view.” Id. at 975 (quoting Nat’l
    Endowment for Arts v. Finley, 
    524 U.S. 569
    , 598 (1998)
    (Scalia, J., concurring)). For this reason, the Fourth Circuit has
    rejected an equal-protection challenge to legislative prayer.
    See Simpson, 
    404 F.3d at
    287–88. The Sixth Circuit has done
    the same in the context of a city’s choice to accept some, and
    reject other, holiday displays on city property. See Freedom
    from Religion Found., 707 F.3d at 698 (“To the extent the
    Foundation means to claim that the City’s government speech
    commemorating the holiday disparately treats its preferred
    message, the answer is: welcome to the crowd.”). The Court
    drew on this precedent to rebuff an equal-protection challenge
    to the motto “In God We Trust” on U.S. coinage brought by
    atheists claiming the government’s speech “disparately
    treat[ed]” their views. New Doe Child #1 v. Cong. of United
    States, 
    891 F.3d 578
    , 594 (6th Cir. 2018).
    Likewise, the Fifth Circuit concluded that a private
    plaintiff lacked standing to bring an equal-protection challenge
    to the Confederate flag’s presence in the Mississippi state flag,
    explaining that “exposure to a discriminatory message, without
    a corresponding denial of equal treatment, is insufficient to
    plead injury in an equal protection case.” Moore v. Bryant, 
    853 F.3d 245
    , 250 (5th Cir. 2017). To be sure, the Court explained,
    “discriminatory government speech would certainly be useful
    in proving a discriminatory treatment claim, because it loudly
    speaks to discriminatory purpose.” 
    Id.
     at 251 n.4. On its own,
    however, disparate messaging is not enough to make out an
    equal-protection violation. “[T]he gravamen of an equal
    protection claim is differential governmental treatment, not
    differential governmental messaging.” Id. at 250.
    33
    We acknowledge that the First and D.C. Circuits have
    suggested (without deciding and without explanation) that the
    Equal Protection Clause might apply to government speech.
    See Sutliffe, 584 F.3d at 331 n.9 (noting that the Equal
    Protection Clause “may be . . . another restraint on government
    speech”); People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals, Inc. v.
    Gittens, 
    414 F.3d 23
    , 28 (D.C. Cir. 2005) (noting that the Equal
    Protection Clause “might . . . limit the government as speaker,”
    but observing that “[t]he curator of a state-owned museum, for
    example, may decide to display only busts of Union Army
    generals of the Civil War, or the curator may decide to exhibit
    only busts of Confederate generals.”). And in a concurrence in
    Summum, Justice Stevens stated that “government speakers are
    bound by” both “the Establishment and Equal Protection
    Clauses.” Summum, 
    555 U.S. at 482
     (Stevens, J., concurring).
    Even so, we join the authority holding that the Equal Protection
    Clause does not apply to government speech. As a result, we
    affirm the District Court’s rejection of this claim.4
    E. Coercion Claim
    The nontheists have not appealed the District Court’s
    ruling that the House’s current practice of asking visitors to
    “please rise as able” is not coercive. As a result, we review
    only the pre-2017 practice, which had two features. First, the
    4
    Although she didn’t couch her conclusion as a matter of
    government speech, then-Judge Ginsburg also stated that a
    nontheist’s equal-protection challenge to Congress’s theists-
    only prayer policy should fail. Because “the historic practice
    of an opening prayer burdens no ‘fundamental right’ of non-
    theists,” the challenger could not “salvage his failed first
    amendment claim by cloaking it in a fifth amendment due
    process (equal protection component) mantle.” Kurtz, 
    829 F.2d at
    1147 n.3 (R.B. Ginsburg, J., dissenting).
    34
    sign outside the House chamber read, “[a]ll guests who are
    physically able are requested to stand during [the prayer],” and
    the Speaker introduced the prayer by requesting that
    “[m]embers and all guests, please rise.” Second, in the 2012
    incident, a House security guard singled out Fields and
    Rhoades and pressured them to stand.
    To begin, we assess whether the challenge to either
    feature is moot. The House has voluntarily ceased both aspects
    of its pre-2017 practice. It has amended the sign and Speaker
    statement to their current (undisputed) form, and it has
    instructed its security guards not to single out visitors who
    remain seated during the prayer.
    Voluntary cessation of challenged activity will moot a
    case only if it is “absolutely clear that the allegedly wrongful
    behavior could not reasonably be expected to recur.” Parents
    Involved in Cmty. Sch. v. Seattle Sch. Dist. No. 1, 
    551 U.S. 701
    ,
    719 (2007) (quoting Friends of Earth, Inc. v. Laidlaw Envtl.
    Servs. (TOC), Inc., 
    528 U.S. 167
    , 189 (2000)); see also United
    States v. Gov’t of Virgin Islands, 
    363 F.3d 276
    , 285 (3d Cir.
    2004). The party urging mootness bears the “heavy burden” of
    showing that it will not “revert to” its prior policy. Trinity
    Lutheran Church of Columbia, Inc. v. Comer, 
    137 S. Ct. 2012
    ,
    2019 n.1 (2017) (quoting Friends of the Earth, 
    528 U.S. at 189
    ).
    Here, the House continues to defend the
    constitutionality of the pre-2017 sign and Speaker statement
    despite its counsel’s statements at oral argument that it would
    not reinstate them. As a result, it is not “absolutely clear” that
    the House would not revert to its pre-2017 policy in the future.
    In fact, it only changed the sign and statement in response to
    this litigation, which weighs against mootness. See Marcavage
    v. Nat’l Park Serv., 
    666 F.3d 856
    , 861 (3d Cir. 2012). And the
    nontheists seek not only an injunction, but also a declaratory
    35
    judgment about the pre-2017 practice. In this context, the sign-
    and-statement feature of the coercion claim is not moot.
    But the 2012 incident of pressure from a security guard
    is moot. The House has disavowed the security guard’s actions
    in this one-off incident. See Second Br. of Appellants/Cross-
    Appellees at 48 n.31 (“The House has not argued, and would
    not argue, that visitors should be publicly confronted for
    refusing to stand.”). Its choice not to defend the security
    guard’s actions weighs in favor of mootness. Cf. Marcavage,
    666 F.3d at 861 (finding mootness when the Park Service did
    not challenge an adverse injunction on appeal and had stopped
    enforcing its enjoined rule). Its decision not to defend on this
    practice is wise, given that the security guard’s behavior almost
    certainly crossed the constitutional line. See Town of Greece,
    572 U.S. at 588 (suggesting that coercion occurs when a
    lawmaker “direct[s] the public to participate in the prayers” or
    “single[s] out dissidents for opprobrium”).
    Turning from mootness to the merits of the coercion
    claim, both sides agree that Justice Kennedy’s plurality opinion
    in Town of Greece controls on the question of coercion in
    legislative prayer. See, e.g., Br. of Appellees/Cross-Appellants
    at 66 n.10; see also Lund, 863 F.3d at 286 (looking to plurality
    opinion for rule on coercion). Aside from holding that
    legislative prayer could be sectarian, the Court in Town of
    Greece rejected the challenger’s claim that the prayer practice
    was unconstitutionally coercive. See 572 U.S. at 591. Writing
    for himself, Chief Justice Roberts, and Justice Alito, Justice
    Kennedy stated that “government may not coerce its citizens
    to support or participate in any religion or its exercise.” Id. at
    586 (quotations omitted). The coercion inquiry “remains a
    fact-sensitive one that considers both the setting in which the
    prayer arises and the audience to whom it is directed.” Id. at
    587. (Justice Thomas, joined by Justice Scalia, would have
    gone further to hold that a prayer practice is not coercive unless
    36
    religious orthodoxy is enforced by “force of law and threat of
    penalty.” Id. at 608 (Thomas, J., concurring) (quotations
    omitted).)
    Applying this “fact-sensitive” test to the House practice
    here, we hold that the pre-2017 sign and Speaker statement
    were not coercive. To begin, the sign and statement were
    merely requests to rise, which on their own are permissible.
    See Bormuth, 870 F.3d at 517 (concluding that asking “adult
    members of the public” to “ris[e] and remain[] quiet in a
    reverent position” was not coercive). “[L]egislative prayer
    does not force religious practice on an audience.” Mayle, 891
    F.3d at 685. The challengers here are adults, “presumably not
    readily susceptible to religious indoctrination or peer
    pressure.” Marsh, 
    463 U.S. at 792
     (quotations omitted). Nor
    is this situation analogous to a request to stand in a school
    setting. See Lee, 
    505 U.S. at
    596–97 (Kennedy, J.) (school-
    prayer coercion case explicitly distinguishing Marsh); Town of
    Greece, 572 U.S. at 590 (explicitly distinguishing Lee).
    Next, the setting here is even less conducive to coercion
    than it was in Town of Greece. Unlike the intimate meeting
    room there, the Pennsylvania House chamber accommodates
    over 200 members and nearly 100 visitors in the gallery. A
    small townhall is more coercive than a large legislative
    chamber. See, e.g., Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 625–27
    (Kagan, J., dissenting). Unlike Pennsylvania House members,
    county commissioners and town councilors have more direct
    control over their constituents’ daily lives and typically hear
    citizen petitions immediately after the prayer. See Lund, 863
    F.3d at 287–88.
    That Fields and Rhoades felt offended by the prayers
    does not aid their claim of coercion. “[L]egislative bodies do
    not engage in impermissible coercion merely by exposing
    37
    constituents to prayer they would rather not hear and in which
    they need not participate.” Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 590.
    To be sure, one aspect of the House practice weighing
    in favor of coercion is the identity of the person asking visitors
    to rise: the Speaker of the House. This makes the situation
    more coercive than one in which a guest chaplain makes the
    request, and it separates our case from Town of Greece. See id.
    at 588. The Fourth Circuit in Lund distinguished Town of
    Greece in the same way to strike down a practice in which
    county commissioners asked attendees to rise and led them in
    prayer. See Lund, 863 F.3d at 272. When the words “[l]et us
    pray” come from “elected representatives acting in their
    official capacity,” the Court concluded, “they become a request
    on behalf of the state.” Id. at 287.
    Even so, two factors cut against the importance of the
    Speaker’s role in the request to rise. His request is typically
    followed by a prayer from a guest chaplain (not from another
    lawmaker, as in Lund). And the Speaker still asks visitors to
    rise today, yet the nontheists have abandoned their challenge
    to the current policy.
    In sum, the pre-2017 sign and Speaker statement were
    not coercive.
    Conclusion
    We affirm in part and reverse in part. The House’s
    policy preferring theistic over nontheistic prayers does not
    violate the Establishment Clause because it fits squarely within
    the historical tradition of legislative prayer. Next, legislative
    prayer is government speech, so the policy is not susceptible to
    an attack on free-speech, free-exercise, or equal-protection
    grounds. Finally, the sole incident of pressure from a security
    38
    guard is moot, and the general practice pre-2017 of asking the
    visitors’ gallery to rise for the opening prayer was not coercive.
    39
    RESTREPO, Circuit Judge, concurring in part and dissenting
    in part.
    I join the majority opinion only with respect to the
    majority’s analysis of the Pennsylvania House’s pre-2017
    policy of requesting that members of the public “please rise”
    during opening prayers, in which the majority holds that all
    aspects of the policy are either constitutionally permissible or
    moot. I respectfully dissent from the remainder of the majority
    opinion because, in my view, the Pennsylvania House’s
    process of selecting guest chaplains violates the Establishment
    Clause of the First Amendment.1
    As the Supreme Court has recognized, Plaintiffs are
    members of “religions” for purposes of the First Amendment.
    See Torcaso v. Watkins, 
    367 U.S. 488
    , 495 n.11 (1961)
    (“Among religions in this country which do not teach what
    would generally be considered a belief in the existence of God
    are . . . Ethical Culture, Secular Humanism[,] and others.”
    (emphasis added)). Plaintiffs simply seek the opportunity to
    deliver prayers at the opening of the Pennsylvania House’s
    legislative days that reflect their religious beliefs. The
    Pennsylvania House, however, denied Plaintiffs such an
    opportunity solely on the grounds that their religious beliefs do
    not comport with the Pennsylvania House’s preferred religious
    beliefs and that Plaintiffs, thus, are incapable of delivering a
    1
    Because I would hold that the Pennsylvania House’s
    guest-chaplain policy violates the Establishment Clause, I
    would not reach—and, in this opinion, I do not discuss—
    Plaintiffs’ claims arising under the Free Speech and Free
    Exercise Clauses of the First Amendment and the Equal
    Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.
    “prayer” within the Pennsylvania House’s conception of that
    term. In my view, the Pennsylvania House’s policy of
    explicitly and purposefully excluding certain persons from
    serving as guest chaplains solely on the basis of their religions
    and religious beliefs finds no refuge in the history and tradition
    of legislative prayer in this country. Further, even assuming
    arguendo that the Pennsylvania House’s purposeful
    exclusionary policy indeed fits within the history and tradition
    of legislative prayer in the United States, the policy
    nonetheless violates core tenets of the Establishment Clause by
    instituting an impermissible “religious orthodoxy,” Town of
    Greece v. Galloway, 
    572 U.S. 565
    , 581 (2014), and by, in
    effect, “direct[ing] and controll[ing] the content of . . .
    prayers,” Lee v. Weisman, 
    505 U.S. 577
    , 588 (1992).
    Rather than acknowledging these violations of the
    Establishment Clause, the majority accommodates the
    Pennsylvania House’s purposeful discrimination against
    Plaintiffs, their religions, and their religious beliefs by
    concluding that (i) “the purpose of legislative prayer is to
    invoke divine guidance,” (ii) “‘prayer’ presupposes a higher
    power,” and (iii) Plaintiffs, because their religious beliefs do
    not include a belief in a “higher power” or God, cannot offer a
    “prayer.” This line of reasoning by necessity involves
    answering sensitive questions about what constitutes the
    “divine” and what words must be strung together for a speech
    to constitute a “prayer,” which, in my view, are precisely the
    type of questions that the Establishment Clause forbids the
    government—including courts—from answering. I therefore
    respectfully dissent.
    2
    I.
    In analyzing whether the Pennsylvania House’s guest-
    chaplain policy is permissible under the Establishment Clause,
    we must “determine whether the prayer practice . . . fits within
    the tradition long followed in Congress and the state
    legislatures.” Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 577. When framing
    the contours of the relevant prayer practice, courts should be
    “specific,” and “where history shows that the specific practice
    is permitted,” “it is not necessary [for courts] to define the
    precise boundary of the Establishment Clause.” Id. (emphasis
    added) (citing Marsh v. Chambers, 
    463 U.S. 783
     (1983)).
    In devising the key inquiry in this case, the majority, in
    my view, frames the Pennsylvania House’s guest-chaplain
    policy in a way that is too broad and that does not capture the
    true exclusionary nature of the policy. Relying on the D.C.
    Circuit’s opinion in Barker v. Conroy, 
    921 F.3d 1118
     (D.C.
    Cir. 2019), the majority formulates the key inquiry as whether
    “the House’s decision to limit the opening prayer to religious[2]
    prayer fit[s] ‘within the tradition long followed in Congress
    and the state legislatures,’” id. at 1130 (quoting Town of
    Greece, 572 U.S. at 577).
    Conceptualizing the Pennsylvania House’s guest-
    chaplain policy as “limiting” prayer to theistic prayer is not
    technically an incorrect way to express the contours of the
    2
    I assume that by “religious prayer,” the majority
    intended to convey that the Pennsylvania House “limits the
    opening prayer to theistic prayer.” If the Pennsylvania House
    limited opening prayer to “religious” prayer, Plaintiffs would
    not have been excluded because they are indeed members of
    “religions.” See Torcaso, 
    367 U.S. at
    495 n.11.
    3
    policy, but framing the policy in such a way omits the most
    notable and constitutionally suspect facet of the policy: the
    Pennsylvania House purposefully excludes adherents of
    certain religions and persons who hold certain religious beliefs
    from serving as guest chaplains and, consequently, prohibits
    them from delivering opening prayers. Saying that the
    Pennsylvania House merely “limits” legislative prayer to
    theistic prayer fails to capture the purposeful exclusionary
    actions undertaken by the Pennsylvania House to ensure that
    its prayer practice is “limited” to theistic prayer; under the
    majority’s formulation, it is equally as likely that the prayer
    offered by guest chaplains simply is “confine[d] within [the]
    limits” of theistic prayer through no voluntary action on the
    part of the Pennsylvania House whatsoever. Limit, Oxford
    English Dictionary (3d ed. 2014).
    By framing the Pennsylvania House’s prayer practice as
    simply being “limited” to theistic prayer, the majority’s
    ultimate holding is nothing more than a foregone conclusion:
    the prayer practice at issue in Town of Greece v. Galloway, 572
    U.S. at 571, which the Supreme Court upheld, could properly
    be described as one that was “limited” to theistic prayer
    because all of the guest ministers in that case belonged to
    theistic religions and were nearly all Christian. What
    distinguishes Town of Greece from this case, however, is that
    the town council in Town of Greece “at no point excluded or
    denied an opportunity to a would-be prayer giver,” and “[i]ts
    leaders maintained that a minister or layperson of any
    persuasion, including an atheist, could give the invocation.”
    Id. In Town of Greece, the prayers offered at the beginning of
    town board meetings were “limited” to theistic prayers simply
    by virtue of the fact that “nearly all of the congregations in
    town were Christian,” and therefore ministers of other religions
    4
    generally were not available to deliver the prayers. Here, by
    contrast, the Pennsylvania House explicitly and purposefully
    excludes persons who hold Plaintiffs’ religious beliefs from
    serving as guest chaplains and from delivering opening
    prayers, but the majority’s framing of the Pennsylvania
    House’s guest-chaplain policy fails to capture this crucial
    distinction.
    Thus, in my view, the key inquiry in this case is more
    properly formulated as “whether the Pennsylvania House’s
    policy of purposefully excluding persons of certain religious
    faiths from serving as guest chaplains fits ‘within the tradition
    long followed in Congress and the state legislatures.’” Id. at
    577. When framed in this way, the answer to this question is
    clearly “no.” The First Congress intended legislative prayer
    “to be inclusive rather than divisive.” Am. Legion v. Am.
    Humanist Ass’n, 
    139 S. Ct. 2067
    , 2088 (2019) (Kavanaugh, J.)
    (plurality opinion). Members of the First Congress held
    divergent views regarding the motion to appoint a
    congressional chaplain, but Samuel Adams ended debate on
    the motion by supporting it: “I am no bigot. I can hear a prayer
    from a man of piety and virtue, who is at the same time a friend
    of his country.” Derek H. Davis, Religion and the Continental
    Congress, 1774–1778, at 74 (2000) (quoting Adams).
    Throughout the early years of the Republic, Congress
    maintained this policy of inclusion. In 1853, the Judiciary
    Committees of the House of Representatives and the Senate
    concluded that “no faith was excluded by law, nor any favored”
    in the selection of congressional chaplains. Town of Greece,
    572 U.S. at 576.
    This history demonstrates that legislative prayer, as
    envisioned by the First Congress and as subsequently practiced
    5
    by Congress since then, never involved the purposeful
    exclusion of persons from consideration to serve as chaplains
    on the basis of their religions or religious beliefs. This lack of
    a history of purposeful, religion-based discrimination in
    legislative prayer is what, in my view, animates the anti-
    discrimination language in Town of Greece. See id. at 585–86
    (“So long as the town maintains a policy of nondiscrimination,
    the Constitution does not require it to search beyond its borders
    for non-Christian prayer givers in an effort to achieve religious
    balancing.”). And by virtue of the fact that the history and
    tradition of legislative prayer in this country is thus devoid of
    any history of purposeful exclusion of persons from serving as
    chaplains based on their religions or religious beliefs, the
    Pennsylvania       House’s     guest-chaplain      policy—which
    purposefully excludes adherents of Plaintiffs’ religions and
    persons who hold Plaintiffs’ religious beliefs from serving as
    guest chaplains—does not fit “within the tradition long
    followed in Congress and the state legislatures” and therefore
    violates the Establishment Clause. Id. at 577.
    The majority’s response to this line of reasoning is that
    it “doubt[s] whether the Congress of 1853”—which found that
    “no faith was excluded by law, nor any favored” in the
    selection of congressional chaplains, id. at 576—“understood
    atheism as a ‘faith,’ given that its study was from an era that
    still defined ‘religion’ as ‘one’s views of his relations to his
    Creator.’” This cannot possibly be a standard around which to
    build Establishment Clause jurisprudence. Such a standard
    would permit, for example, a legislature to purposefully
    exclude all adherents of Buddhism, the world’s fourth largest
    religion by population, from delivering legislative prayers
    because Buddhists do not believe in a “Creator”: “If absence
    of a Creator-God is atheism, Buddhism is atheistic.” Huston
    6
    Smith, The World’s Religions 114 (rev. & updated ed. 1991).
    It is unconscionable to think that the Establishment Clause
    permits legislatures to purposefully exclude all Buddhists from
    delivering legislative prayers, and it should be equally
    unconscionable to think that the Establishment Clause permits
    such purposeful exclusion of persons who hold Plaintiffs’
    religious beliefs because there is no principled difference
    between Buddhism and Plaintiffs’ religions in this regard.3
    In sum, the majority, in my view, paints with too broad
    a brush in framing the question with respect to whether the
    Pennsylvania House’s guest-chaplain policy fits within the
    tradition of legislative prayer that has long been followed in
    Congress and the state legislatures. The defining characteristic
    3
    The fact that a Buddhist previously has delivered a
    prayer in the United States Senate is immaterial to the issue of
    whether Congress—or any other legislature—may later
    purposefully exclude Buddhists from delivering legislative
    prayers under the majority opinion. The only manageable
    standard that I can glean from the majority opinion in this
    regard is that a legislature cannot, at some later point,
    purposefully exclude members of a nontheistic religion from
    delivering legislative prayers once that legislature welcomes a
    member of that nontheistic religion to deliver a legislative
    prayer. Such a rule would lead to absurd results. For example,
    the Pennsylvania Senate, which previously has welcomed
    adherents of Plaintiffs’ religions to serve as guest chaplains,
    would be prohibited from later choosing to exclude adherents
    of such religions from serving as guest chaplains, even though
    the majority today holds that the Pennsylvania House can, as a
    matter of constitutional law, exclude such persons from serving
    as guest chaplains.
    7
    of the Pennsylvania House’s policy is that it purposefully
    excludes adherents of Plaintiffs’ religions and persons who
    hold Plaintiffs’ religious beliefs from serving as guest
    chaplains, but the majority’s formulation of the key inquiry in
    this case omits any reference to such purposeful exclusion.
    Purposeful exclusion of adherents of certain religions or
    persons who hold certain religious beliefs has never been
    countenanced in the history of legislative prayer in the United
    States, and, therefore, viewed in the proper context, the
    Pennsylvania House’s guest-chaplain policy does not fit
    “within the tradition long followed in Congress and the state
    legislatures” because it purposefully excludes persons from
    serving as guest chaplains solely on the basis of their religions
    and religious beliefs.4 Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 577.
    4
    I am not persuaded otherwise by what the majority
    construes as the Supreme Court’s alleged “tak[ing] as given
    that prayer presumes a higher power.” To support this
    contention, the majority primarily cites passages from Marsh
    v. Chambers, 
    463 U.S. 783
    , and Town of Greece in which the
    Supreme Court, in the words of the majority, “described
    legislative prayer” as a practice that involves the invocation of
    a “higher power” or God. It is only natural that the Supreme
    Court described legislative prayer in these terms: until
    recently, nearly all legislative prayer in this country happens to
    have been explicitly theistic in nature. It is quite a different
    thing to construe this description in dicta as tantamount to a
    holding that legislative prayer must be theistic in nature to
    qualify as such.
    The majority also lends a great deal of weight to then-
    Judge Ginsburg’s dissenting opinion in Kurtz v. Baker, 829
    
    8 F.2d 1133
     (D.C. Cir. 1987), a dissent in a case decided in 1987
    by a court of appeals other than our own. In relying heavily on
    this dissent, the majority implicitly makes a number of
    presumptions that I am not willing to make, including (i) that
    now-Justice Ginsburg’s views on this issue have not evolved
    in the intervening thirty-two years; (ii) that Justice Ginsburg’s
    views would not change given the particular facts of this case,
    which are distinguishable from those in Kurtz insofar as the
    plaintiff in that case did not wish to deliver a “prayer,” but
    rather “opening remarks” as a “guest speaker, id. at 1146
    (Ginsburg, J., dissenting), whereas here, Plaintiffs explicitly
    wish to deliver “prayers” as “guest chaplains”; and (iii) that,
    for reasons not stated, the views expressed solely by Justice
    Ginsburg in a dissenting opinion in a factually distinguishable
    case decided by a court of appeals thirty-two years ago are
    apparently decisive on this particular issue.
    Finally, it is not clear to me how the Eleventh Circuit’s
    opinion in Williamson v. Brevard County, 
    928 F.3d 1296
     (11th
    Cir. 2019), supports the majority’s position. The Eleventh
    Circuit did not reach the issue of whether a government can
    exclude persons with nontheistic religious beliefs from
    delivering legislative prayers, and it chose not to reach that
    issue explicitly as a matter of “judicial restraint.” See id. at
    1317 (emphasis added) (quoting Lyng v. Nw. Indian Cemetery
    Protective Ass’n, 
    485 U.S. 439
    , 445 (1988)). That court
    already had found that the relevant legislative body’s prayer
    practice “plainly” violated the Constitution, even setting aside
    the discrimination against persons with nontheistic beliefs in
    particular, and thus the court determined, as a prudential
    matter, that it was unnecessary to adjudicate any of the
    plaintiffs’ further claims. Id. at 1316. Thus, the Eleventh
    9
    II.
    Even assuming arguendo that the Pennsylvania House’s
    guest-chaplain policy indeed fits within the tradition of
    legislative prayer that has long been followed in Congress and
    the state legislatures, that fact alone, in my view, would not
    save the policy. The Supreme Court has held that, “standing
    alone, historical patterns cannot justify contemporary
    violations of constitutional guarantees” in the context of
    legislative prayer. Marsh, 
    463 U.S. at 790
    ; see also Town of
    Greece, 572 U.S. at 576 (“Marsh must not be understood as
    permitting a practice that would amount to a constitutional
    violation if not for its historical foundation.”). In my view,
    even if the Pennsylvania House’s exclusionary guest-chaplain
    policy fits within the history and tradition of legislative prayer
    in this country—which, for the reasons stated above, it does
    not—the policy nonetheless additionally runs afoul of the
    Establishment Clause by instituting a religious orthodoxy and
    by directing and controlling the content of legislative prayer.
    At its core, the Establishment Clause requires the
    government to remain “neutral in matters of religious theory,
    doctrine, and practice,” and the government “may not aid,
    foster, or promote one religion or religious theory against
    another.” Epperson v. Arkansas, 
    393 U.S. 97
    , 103–04 (1968).
    This neutrality principle mandates that the “[g]overnment may
    not . . . prescribe a religious orthodoxy.” Town of Greece, 572
    U.S. at 581.
    Circuit did not, as the majority argues, draw a constitutional
    distinction between theistic prayer and nontheistic prayer—it
    simply concluded that it was neither necessary nor prudent to
    take up the issue of nontheistic prayer. See id. at 1316–17.
    10
    The Establishment Clause also prohibits the
    government from “defin[ing] permissible categories of
    religious speech.” Id. at 582. For example, “government in
    this country, be it state or federal, is without power to prescribe
    . . . any particular form of prayer which is to be used as an
    official prayer in carrying on any program of governmentally
    sponsored religious activity.” Engel v. Vitale, 
    370 U.S. 421
    ,
    430 (1962). The Supreme Court has held that it is a
    “cornerstone principle of . . . Establishment Clause
    jurisprudence” that the government may not “direct[] and
    control[] the content of . . . prayers” delivered at government-
    sponsored public events. Lee, 
    505 U.S. at 588
    .
    Through the implementation of its guest-chaplain
    policy, the Pennsylvania House violates both of these tenets of
    the Establishment Clause. By mandating that all guest
    chaplains profess a belief in a “higher power” or God, the
    Pennsylvania House fails to stay “neutral in matters of
    religious theory”; in effect, the Pennsylvania House
    “promote[s] one . . . religious theory”—belief in God or some
    sort of supreme deity—“against another”—the denial of the
    existence of such a deity. Epperson, 
    393 U.S. at
    103–04. This
    is not to say that a government violates the neutrality principle
    simply by consistently selecting guest ministers who happen to
    believe in a “higher power”—legislative prayer that is even
    explicitly sectarian and almost uniformly Christian in nature
    has been approved by the Supreme Court. See Town of Greece,
    572 U.S. at 581. But when, as here, the government subjects
    prospective guest chaplains to a litmus test of whether they
    believe in the existence of a “higher power” or God, the
    government actively lends its power and prestige to the
    religious theory that a “higher power” or God indeed exists,
    thus violating the Establishment Clause’s neutrality principle
    11
    and instituting belief in a supreme deity as “religious
    orthodoxy.”5 See Engel, 
    370 U.S. at 431
     (“When the power
    [and] prestige . . . of government is placed behind a particular
    religious belief, the indirect coercive pressure upon religious
    5
    To be clear, I do not believe that the inclusion of the
    phrases “In God We Trust” on United States currency and
    “under God” in the Pledge of Allegiance raises similar
    constitutional concerns. In my view, the government’s passive
    speech in the form of text on currency and through the approval
    of the official text of the Pledge is categorically different than
    the government’s actively and purposefully excluding persons
    from participating in a government-sponsored activity based
    solely on their belief or disbelief in a “higher power” or God.
    The nature of the actions are meaningfully different: in the
    former case, the government exercises its power merely to
    approve text and mottos, but in the latter case, the government
    plays an active role, exercising its power to purposefully
    discriminate against citizens solely on the basis of their
    religious beliefs. Indeed, even in the context of the Pledge,
    when the government has attempted to exercise its power in a
    way that exceeds the mere approval of text, the Supreme Court
    has held that such actions violate the First Amendment. See
    W. Va. State Bd. of Educ. v. Barnette, 
    319 U.S. 624
    , 642 (1943)
    (holding that the government cannot enforce a policy to compel
    persons to recite the Pledge because “[i]f there is any fixed star
    in our constitutional constellation, it is that no official, high or
    petty, can prescribe what shall be orthodox in politics,
    nationalism, religion, or other matters of opinion,” and thus
    such a policy “transcends constitutional limitations on the[
    government’s] power”).
    12
    minorities to conform to the prevailing officially approved
    religion is plain.”).
    The Pennsylvania House also impermissibly directs and
    controls the content of the prayers delivered by guest chaplains
    by only permitting persons who profess a belief in a “higher
    power” or God to serve as guest chaplains. If the Pennsylvania
    House instituted a rule that required all guest chaplains to
    include references to a “higher power” or God in their prayers,
    we undoubtedly would hold that such a rule clearly violates the
    Establishment Clause under current precedent. Cf. Lee, 
    505 U.S. at 588
     (holding that the government violated the
    Establishment Clause by “advis[ing a clergyman] that his
    prayers [delivered at a high school graduation] should be
    nonsectarian” because such an attempt to “direct[] and
    control[] the content of the prayers” violates the “cornerstone
    principle of our Establishment Clause jurisprudence that ‘it is
    no part of the business of government to compose official
    prayers’” (quoting Engel, 
    370 U.S. at 425
    )). The record
    suggests that the Pennsylvania House sought to accomplish
    this very goal—ensuring that prayers include references to a
    “higher power” or God—albeit indirectly through the guest-
    chaplain selection process. For example, the Speaker of the
    Pennsylvania House testified that a “prayer” should be “an
    appeal to a benevolent higher being” and that Plaintiffs were
    excluded because they could not deliver such a “prayer.” App.
    650:13–23 (emphasis added). The former Speaker of the
    Pennsylvania House testified that for a “prayer” to be
    acceptable, it must be directed “to a higher being and ask[] for
    intervention,” 
    id.
     at 712:18–19 (emphasis added), and that he
    would have rejected any prospective guest chaplains who
    indicated that they would not “spell [out] an actual [higher]
    being that [would] be[] addressed” in their prayers, 
    id.
     at
    13
    714:24–25 (emphasis added). Further, the Parliamentarian of
    the Pennsylvania House testified that he was “very concerned
    about the content” of potential prayers, 
    id. at 519:5
     (emphasis
    added), and that there was a certain “type of prayer we would
    be looking for,” 
    id. at 523:22
     (emphasis added).
    Rather than instituting an outright requirement that
    guest chaplains include references to a “higher power” or God
    in their prayers, the Pennsylvania House simply addressed the
    issue one step earlier in the process by only selecting persons
    who professed a belief in a “higher power” or God to serve as
    guest chaplains and by purposefully excluding all others.
    While this action is more indirect in nature than an outright
    requirement that guest chaplains include references to a
    “higher power” or God in their prayers, the intentional effect
    on the content of the prayers that were actually delivered is the
    same; the Pennsylvania House exerted its power over the
    guest-chaplain selection process to ensure that the “prayers
    [that were] recited . . . promote[d] a preferred system of
    belief”—namely, belief in a “higher power” or God. Town of
    Greece, 572 U.S. at 581.
    Thus, even setting aside the issue of whether the
    Pennsylvania House’s guest-chaplain policy fits “within the
    tradition long followed in Congress and the state legislatures,”
    id. at 577, the actions of the Pennsylvania House amount to an
    Establishment Clause violation. Pursuant to the Establishment
    Clause, a government can neither institute a religious
    orthodoxy nor direct or control the content of legislative
    prayer, but here, the Pennsylvania House sought to
    accomplish—and indeed succeeded in accomplishing—both
    of these constitutionally impermissible goals.
    14
    III.
    A legislature is free to appoint a single chaplain, of a
    single denomination, for nearly two decades to deliver
    Christian opening prayers on an almost permanent basis, so
    long as the chaplain’s appointment and reappointment did not
    “stem[] from an impermissible motive.” Marsh, 
    463 U.S. at 793
    . A legislature is free to select guest ministers that are
    nearly all Christian and who deliver explicitly sectarian
    prayers, so long as the selection of such ministers “does not
    reflect an aversion or bias on the part of [legislators] against
    minority faiths.” Town of Greece, 572 U.S. at 586. A
    legislature also is free to enact rules to exclude—as the
    majority phrases it—the “heckler,” who may, among other
    things, “denigrate nonbelievers or religious minorities,
    threaten damnation, . . . preach conversion,” or “disparage . . .
    other . . . faith[s] or belief[s].” Id. at 583 (quoting Marsh, 
    463 U.S. at
    794–95).
    What a legislature cannot do, however, is purposefully
    exclude persons from serving as guest chaplains—and thereby
    prohibit such persons from delivering legislative prayers—
    solely on the basis of such persons’ religions or religious
    beliefs. See 
    id.
     at 585–86. Yet that is precisely what the
    Pennsylvania House did here: the Pennsylvania House denied
    Plaintiffs—who, as the Supreme Court has recognized, are
    members of “religions” for the purposes of the First
    Amendment, see Torcaso, 
    367 U.S. at
    495 n.11—the
    opportunity to serve as guest chaplains solely on the basis of
    their religions and religious beliefs.
    The majority provides sanction to the Pennsylvania
    House’s purposeful, religion-based discrimination by
    reasoning that whether Plaintiffs are members of a “religion”
    15
    for the purposes of the First Amendment is immaterial to the
    question at hand; rather, the “only . . . question” that is relevant,
    in the majority’s view, is “whether [Plaintiffs] believe in a
    supreme being.” In other words, while the Supreme Court has
    held that Plaintiffs are members of “religions” for First
    Amendment purposes, the majority holds that Plaintiffs are not
    members of “religions” for these First Amendment purposes
    because the only religions that “count” for these purposes are
    those that profess a belief in a “higher being” or God. In
    essence, the majority, in my view, casts Plaintiffs’ religions as
    “second class.”
    The First Amendment knows no “first class” or “second
    class”; the Establishment Clause was intended to prohibit the
    government from making such distinctions. Courts should not
    make such distinctions, and we need not make such
    distinctions—including with respect to whether persons of
    certain religions possess the ability to offer a “prayer”—to
    adjudicate the facts of this case. When framed properly, the
    Pennsylvania House’s policy of purposefully excluding
    persons from serving as guest chaplains solely on the basis of
    their religions and religious beliefs does not fit within the
    inclusive tradition of legislative prayer that has long been
    followed in Congress and the state legislatures, and for this
    reason, among other reasons, the policy violates the
    Establishment Clause. I thus would affirm the judgment of the
    District Court in this regard.
    Therefore, for the reasons stated above, I respectfully
    dissent.
    16
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 18-2974

Filed Date: 8/23/2019

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 8/23/2019

Authorities (39)

Freedom From Religion Foundation v. Hanover School District , 626 F.3d 1 ( 2010 )

anne-n-gaylor-annie-laurie-gaylor-daniel-e-barker-glenn-v-smith-jeff , 74 F.3d 214 ( 1996 )

Pelphrey v. Cobb County, Ga. , 547 F.3d 1263 ( 2008 )

Frank Africa v. The Commonwealth of Pennsylvania Leroy S. ... , 662 F.2d 1025 ( 1981 )

Turner v. City Council of the City of Fredericksburg , 534 F.3d 352 ( 2008 )

United States v. Government of the Virgin Islands , 363 F.3d 276 ( 2004 )

Newdow v. Rio Linda Union School Dist. , 597 F.3d 1007 ( 2010 )

Newdow v. Lefevre , 598 F.3d 638 ( 2010 )

James J. Kaufman v. Gary R. McCaughtry , 419 F.3d 678 ( 2005 )

robert-ian-sherman-for-himself-and-as-natural-guardian-for-richard-harry , 980 F.2d 437 ( 1992 )

Croft v. Perry , 624 F.3d 157 ( 2010 )

Joyner v. Forsyth County, NC , 653 F.3d 341 ( 2011 )

Madalyn Murray O'Hair v. Jon Murray v. W. Michael ... , 588 F.2d 1144 ( 1979 )

cynthia-simpson-v-chesterfield-county-board-of-supervisors-national-legal , 404 F.3d 276 ( 2005 )

People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals, Inc. v. Gittens , 414 F.3d 23 ( 2005 )

Robert Downs v. Los Angeles Unified School District , 228 F.3d 1003 ( 2000 )

Johnson v. Poway Unified School District , 658 F.3d 954 ( 2011 )

Cantwell v. Connecticut , 60 S. Ct. 900 ( 1940 )

Paul Kurtz, Dr. v. James A. Baker, Secretary of the Treasury , 829 F.2d 1133 ( 1987 )

Davis v. Beason , 10 S. Ct. 299 ( 1890 )

View All Authorities »