United States v. Ho Ka Yung ( 2022 )


Menu:
  •                                         PRECEDENTIAL
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE THIRD CIRCUIT
    _______________
    Nos. 19-1640 & 20-3448
    _______________
    UNITED STATES OF AMERICA
    v.
    HO KA TERENCE YUNG,
    Appellant.
    _______________
    On Appeal from the United States District Court
    for the District of Delaware
    (D.C. No. 1:17-cr-00014-001)
    District Judge: Honorable Leonard P. Stark
    _______________
    Argued: January 12, 2022
    Before: RESTREPO, BIBAS, and ROTH, Circuit Judges
    (Filed: June 13, 2022)
    _______________
    Peter Goldberger                              [ARGUED]
    50 Rittenhouse Place
    Ardmore, PA 19003
    Edson A. Bostic
    Tieffa N. Harper
    FEDERAL PUBLIC DEFENDER’S OFFICE
    800 King Street, Suite 200
    Wilmington, DE 19801
    Counsel for Appellant
    Ruth Mandelbaum                                 [ARGUED]
    Shawn A. Weede
    UNITED STATES ATTORNEY’S OFFICE
    1313 N. Market St.
    Hercules Building, Suite 400
    Wilmington, DE 19801
    Counsel for Appellee
    _______________
    OPINION OF THE COURT
    _______________
    BIBAS, Circuit Judge.
    The First Amendment limits the government’s power to
    punish offensive or annoying speech. Convicted under a cyber-
    stalking statute, Ho Ka Terence Yung challenges that law as
    overbroad. But to avoid this problem, we read the statute nar-
    rowly and so will affirm his conviction.
    Yung also challenges his restitution order. Yung had
    waived much of his right to appeal, including any challenge to
    the restitution order. But enforcing that waiver would threaten
    the separation of powers, so we must hear Yung’s challenge.
    And because part of the restitution order was not authorized by
    statute, we will vacate that order.
    2
    I. THE SPURNED APPLICANT TURNS CYBERSTALKER
    Yung wanted to go to Georgetown Law. He had good
    grades and strong test scores. So Georgetown invited him to
    interview with an alumnus. But that interview went poorly.
    Yung thought his interviewer was insensitive and rude. And a
    few weeks later, Georgetown rejected him.
    Though Yung eventually got into a good law school,
    Georgetown’s rejection still stung. So a year later, he struck
    back against the interviewer. First, he launched a cyber-
    campaign: he created fake obituaries for the interviewer’s wife
    and son; social-media profiles littered with Ku Klux Klan con-
    tent in the interviewer’s name; and blog posts as the inter-
    viewer, bragging about raping women, a boy, and an eight-
    year-old girl. A Google search of the interviewer’s name re-
    vealed thousands of similar posts. As a reader of the posts re-
    marked: “Someone is really out to nail this guy to a cross.” JA
    219.
    Next, Yung filed false reports. Posing as a female
    Georgetown applicant on law school fora, he accused the inter-
    viewer of groping, bigotry, and threatening professional retal-
    iation. And in reports to the Better Business Bureau, he ac-
    cused the interviewer of sexually assaulting a female associate
    and berating prospective employees. He “strongly encouraged
    [the interviewer’s employer] to fire this dirty old man.” JA 176.
    Yung’s cyber-harassment spilled over into the real world.
    Impersonating the interviewer’s wife, he published an online
    ad seeking a sex slave. When one man responded to the ad,
    Yung ordered him to spy on the family. The wife, another ad
    3
    claimed, “like[d] it when a man puts his hand around [her]
    throat and threaten[s] [her] with a knife” and “gun” before forc-
    ing her to have sex. JA 168. Because of Yung’s antics, the in-
    terviewer’s family got hundreds of phone calls from men seek-
    ing sex with the interviewer, his wife, or their son. “[Y]ou pick
    up the phone and the first thing they ask is how big is your …
    genitalia,” the interviewer testified. JA 325. Responding to
    other sexual ads, strange men even came to the interviewer’s
    home in the wee hours of three consecutive mornings.
    This harassment campaign turned the family’s life into a
    “nightmare.” JA 295. They were terrified that every strange
    visitor sought to “rape and murder” them. JA 296. They
    worked with police to plan safe hiding places in their home in
    case someone broke in. They disconnected their phone every
    night and quit walking around the neighborhood. And they
    feared that they would “never know [normalcy] again.” JA
    296.
    Because the family’s son studied at Georgetown, the family
    informed it of the threat. Georgetown worried that the son
    would be targeted there too, so it added security.
    Eventually, the interviewer hired lawyers and cyber-inves-
    tigators, “begging” them to track down the puppeteer. JA 162.
    Working with the FBI, the investigators traced it all back to
    Yung.
    Yung was charged with cyberstalking. 18 U.S.C.
    §§ 2261A(2)(B) & 2261(b). Faced with a mountain of evi-
    dence, he challenged the cyberstalking law as overbroad under
    the First Amendment. But when that challenge failed, he
    4
    pleaded guilty. Though he waived most of his right to appeal,
    he reserved his right to appeal the overbreadth ruling and any
    sentence above the statutory maximum.
    Yung was sentenced to nearly four years in prison plus
    three years of probation. He was also ordered to pay restitution
    for the interviewer’s investigative costs (nearly $70,000) and
    Georgetown’s security measures ($130,000).
    On appeal, Yung revives his overbreadth challenge and
    contests the restitution order. The government responds that his
    plea agreement lets him appeal only overbreadth, not restitu-
    tion. We review each issue de novo. United States v. Gonzalez,
    
    905 F.3d 165
    , 190 (3d Cir. 2018); United States v. Quillen, 
    335 F.3d 219
    , 221 (3d Cir. 2003).
    II. THE CYBERSTALKING STATUTE IS NOT OVERBROAD
    Yung first challenges his conviction under the cyberstalk-
    ing law. He does not argue that it restricts his protected speech
    or is improper as applied to him. And he likely could not. The
    First Amendment does not protect defaming a private person
    or making “true threats”: that is, “serious[ly] express[ing] an
    intent to commit an act of unlawful violence to” particular peo-
    ple. Virginia v. Black, 
    538 U.S. 343
    , 359 (2003); see Chaplin-
    sky v. New Hampshire, 
    315 U.S. 568
    , 572 (1942).
    Rather than challenge the law as applied, Yung attacks it as
    overbroad and thus facially invalid. He says it “punishes a sub-
    stantial amount of [others’] protected free speech.” Yung Br.
    at 18–19 (quoting Virginia v. Hicks, 
    539 U.S. 113
    , 118–19
    (2003)).
    5
    Overbreadth doctrine is a constitutional anomaly. Ordinar-
    ily, litigants lack standing to challenge laws simply because
    they “may conceivably be applied unconstitutionally to
    others.” Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 
    413 U.S. 601
    , 610 (1973). But
    we have relaxed that standing requirement in First Amendment
    cases to stop overbroad laws from chilling protected speech.
    
    Id. at 612
    .
    Yet invalidating a law as overbroad is “strong medicine”
    that we should use “sparingly.” 
    Id. at 613
    . Courts must hesitate
    before stopping the government from prosecuting conduct that
    it has the power to ban. 
    Id. at 615
    . And the overbreadth excep-
    tion to ordinary standing rules has been cogently criticized. See
    United States v. Sineneng-Smith, 
    140 S. Ct. 1575
    , 1583–88
    (2020) (Thomas, J., concurring). So we will not expand it.
    Before striking down a law, we must ensure that any over-
    breadth is both “real” and “substantial.” Broadrick, 
    413 U.S. at 615
    . Because we can avoid reading this statute as overbroad,
    we will. 
    Id. at 613
    ; New York v. Ferber, 
    458 U.S. 747
    , 769 n.24
    (1982).
    A. The statute
    Congress enacted the cyberstalking law in 2006 and broad-
    ened it in 2013. As amended, it makes a defendant a cyber-
    stalker if he checks three boxes:
    • An act. The defendant must “use[ ] the mail, any
    interactive computer service or electronic
    communication service or … system …, or any
    other facility of interstate or foreign commerce”
    6
    at least twice. 18 U.S.C. § 2261A(2); see also
    § 2266(2).
    • An intent. He must have acted “with the intent to
    kill, injure, harass, intimidate, or place under
    surveillance with intent to kill, injure, harass, or
    intimidate another person.” § 2261A(2).
    • A result. Finally, his actions must cause some
    emotional response. They must either put the
    target “in reasonable fear of … death … or seri-
    ous bodily injury,” or “cause[ ], attempt[ ] to
    cause, or … be reasonably expected to cause sub-
    stantial emotional distress.” § 2261A(2)(A), (B).
    Because Yung pleaded guilty to the emotional-
    distress result element, we focus on that one.
    This is not the first time that we have entertained an over-
    breadth challenge to the statute. A few years ago, we rejected
    an overbreadth challenge to the 2006 version of Section
    2261A. Gonzalez, 905 F.3d at 190 n.10. But the 2013 amend-
    ment broadened its scope. Now the law punishes not only those
    who intend to harass, but also those who intend to intimidate.
    Compare 18 U.S.C. § 2261A(2) (2006), with id. (2013). Plus, a
    defendant no longer has to cause substantial emotional distress.
    It is enough that his conduct be “reasonably expected to cause”
    such distress. Compare id. (2006), with id. (2013). Because the
    revised law reaches further, we must review it again.
    The government argues that the act, intent, and result ele-
    ments limit prosecution to “prohibited actions with a serious
    criminal intent” that “cause serious harm.” Gov’t Br. 27; see
    7
    United States v. Ackell, 
    907 F.3d 67
    , 74–77 (1st Cir. 2018)
    (adopting the government’s position). Read that way, there
    would be no First Amendment problem. Yung counters that the
    law punishes lots of protected speech.
    Ultimately, we reject Yung’s argument. True, if read
    broadly, the statute would punish protected speech. We agree
    with Yung that the act and result elements are not enough to
    save it. But if we can, we must read the statute narrowly enough
    to avoid constitutional problems. And here, a narrow reading
    of the statute’s intent element is plausible. So the statute is not
    overbroad.
    B. The act element captures both conduct and speech
    By itself, the act element does not prevent overbreadth. The
    more speech a law punishes, the likelier it is to be overbroad.
    Hicks, 
    539 U.S. at 124
    . Here, we reject the government’s posi-
    tion that the cyberstalking “statute focuses on conduct, not
    speech.” Gov’t Br. at 24. Rather, it reaches a lot of speech: it
    targets emails, texts, and social media posts, like the ones Yung
    wrote. Thus, we must decide whether the speech it reaches is
    protected by the First Amendment.
    C. The result element alone does not save the statute
    The result element does little to confine the law to unpro-
    tected speech. The law, for instance, punishes people for acting
    in a way that “causes, attempts to cause, or would be reasona-
    bly expected to cause substantial emotional distress.” 18
    U.S.C. § 2261A(2)(B). True, the “[s]ubstantial” emotional dis-
    tress must be “fairly large,” more than mere annoyance. Sub-
    stantial (def. 9), The Oxford English Dictionary (2d ed. 2000).
    8
    Even so, the law captures much speech, in part because it does
    not require that emotional distress be objectively reasonable.
    Though we hope that Americans can discuss sensitive issues
    without taking offense, that is not always so. And the law pe-
    nalizes speech even when a listener’s distress is unexpected or
    idiosyncratic.
    That is a problem. The First Amendment protects lots of
    speech that is substantially emotionally distressing. Protesters
    may picket a marine’s funeral with signs like “Thank God for
    Dead Soldiers,” “God Hates Fags,” and “You’re Going to
    Hell.” Snyder v. Phelps, 
    562 U.S. 443
    , 448 (2011). And a por-
    nographer may parody a famous minister as having drunken
    sex with his mother. Hustler Mag. v. Falwell, 
    485 U.S. 46
    , 47–
    48, 51 (1988). These statements are deeply offensive, yet still
    covered by the First Amendment.
    So neither the act nor the result element suffices to narrow
    the law’s wide reach.
    D. The intent element, narrowly construed, saves the
    statute
    1. Broadly construing intent to harass or intimidate would
    raise constitutional problems. Recall that the statute punishes
    only defendants who “inten[d] to kill, injure, harass, intimi-
    date, or place under surveillance with intent to kill, injure, har-
    ass, or intimidate another person.” 18 U.S.C. § 2261A(2). Even
    speech “directed to inciting or producing imminent lawless ac-
    tion” is unprotected by the First Amendment. Brandenburg v.
    Ohio, 
    395 U.S. 444
    , 447 (1969) (per curiam). So “intent to kill,
    9
    injure, … or place under surveillance with intent to kill, [or]
    injure” is unprotected. § 2261A(2).
    But “intent to … harass [or] intimidate” is another matter.
    Id. If we read those words broadly, the law will reach protected
    speech. Take the verb “harass.” It can mean aggression, even
    violence: “worry[ing] and imped[ing] by repeated attacks.”
    Harass (def. 1b), Webster’s Third New International Diction-
    ary of the English Language Unabridged (1966); accord Har-
    ass (def. 3), Oxford English Dictionary (2d ed. 1989) (OED).
    But “harass” can also mean “to vex, trouble, or annoy contin-
    ually or chronically.” Harass (def. 2b), Webster’s Third; see
    also Harass (def. 4), OED. These poles mark a spectrum from
    repeated annoyance to outright violence.
    Like harassment, intimidation has both narrow and broad
    meanings. To “intimidate” can mean a specific, violent action.
    It “esp[ecially]” means “to force [someone] to or deter [him]
    from some action by threats or violence.” Intimidate, OED; ac-
    cord Intimidation, Black’s Law Dictionary (10th ed. 2014)
    (“Unlawful coercion; extortion.”). But “intimidate” can also
    mean broadly “[t]o render timid, inspire with fear; to overawe,
    cow.” Intimidate, OED.
    Harassment and intimidation, narrowly construed, are pun-
    ishable. “Intimidation in the constitutionally proscribable
    sense of the word … plac[es] the victim in fear of bodily harm
    or death.” Black, 
    538 U.S. at 360
     (emphasis added). Harassing
    debt collection and coercive threats are also unprotected. See,
    e.g., Barr v. Am. Ass’n of Pol. Consultants, 
    140 S. Ct. 2335
    ,
    2347 (2020) (suggesting that the Constitution lets Congress
    regulate the way people collect debts); Saxe v. State Coll. Area
    10
    Sch. Dist., 
    240 F.3d 200
    , 208 (3d Cir. 2001) (Alito, J.) (describ-
    ing a “robber’s demand ‘your money or your life’ ” as an un-
    protected threat); cf. Bronson v. Kinzie, 
    42 U.S. 311
    , 315–16
    (1843) (recognizing the ability of a state to “secure its citizens
    from unjust and harassing litigation”).
    Yet the broader definitions of “harass” and “intimidate” can
    describe nonviolent, nonthreatening speech. Filling a city
    councilman’s voicemail box with complaints about his vote on
    a controversial municipal ordinance may “vex” or “cow” him.
    Ranting in the comments section of a website that a senator
    voted to lock refugee kids in cages could well “annoy [her]
    continually or chronically” or “render [her] timid.” Or, to take
    a couple more mundane examples, “negative restaurant re-
    views left on Google or Yelp, irate emails sent to service pro-
    viders (contractors, plumbers, etc.), … or antagonistic com-
    ments left on news sites” are often persistently annoying or
    even scary. People v. Moreno, 
    2022 WL 894725
    , at *5 (Colo.
    Mar. 28, 2022). Each might satisfy the statute’s act and intent
    elements, read broadly, and (depending on the recipient’s reac-
    tion) the result element too.
    But criminalizing that speech would collide with the First
    Amendment. The First Amendment protects at least some
    speech that persistently annoys someone and makes him fear-
    ful or timid. As then-Judge Alito observed: “There is no cate-
    gorical ‘harassment exception’ to the First Amendment’s free
    speech clause.” Saxe, 
    240 F.3d at 204
    . Though “non-expres-
    sive, physically harassing conduct is entirely outside [its] am-
    bit,” “deeply offensive” speech is not. 
    Id. at 206
     (emphasis
    added). On the contrary, “the free speech clause protects a wide
    11
    variety of speech that listeners may consider deeply offensive.”
    
    Id.
    Thus, broad harassment laws that punish offensive speech
    “steer[ ] into the territory of the First Amendment.” DeAngelis
    v. El Paso Mun. Police Officers Ass’n, 
    51 F.3d 591
    , 596 (5th
    Cir. 1995) (Title VII); see also Dambrot v. Cent. Michigan
    Univ., 
    55 F.3d 1177
    , 1183 (6th Cir. 1995) (university speech
    policy). And courts have often struck them down. See, e.g.,
    State v. Brobst, 
    857 A.2d 1253
    , 1255–56 (N.H. 2004) (holding
    overbroad a harassment statute covering any speech made
    “with the intent to annoy or alarm another”); Ex parte Barton,
    
    586 S.W.3d 573
    , 584–85 (Tex. Ct. App. 2019) (same);
    Moreno, 
    2022 WL 894725
    , at *5–6 (same). So here too, we
    must ensure that the cyberstalking statute does not “present[ ]
    a ‘realistic danger’ [that] the [Government] could compro-
    mise” First Amendment protections. Dambrot, 
    55 F.3d at 1183
    .
    2. Though the text supports the broad reading, constitu-
    tional avoidance tells us to select the narrow one. To decide
    between the broad and narrow readings, we use ordinary tools
    of statutory interpretation. Here, those tools support the broad
    reading of the statute. Even so, the narrow reading is textually
    plausible. Because that definition will not “twist the text be-
    yond what it will bear,” we must adopt it. Amy Coney Barrett,
    Substantive Canons and Faithful Agency, 90 Boston U. L. Rev.
    109, 141 (2010) (defining constitutional avoidance); see Fer-
    ber, 
    458 U.S. at
    769 n.24.
    To start, we acknowledge the strong textual arguments in
    favor of the broad reading. For one, reading the statute broadly
    12
    fits with two canons of construction: consistent usage and sur-
    plusage. One of the statute’s result elements tracks the narrow
    definition of “intimidate” word for word: “places that person
    in reasonable fear of … death … or serious bodily injury.” 18
    U.S.C. § 2261A(2)(A); Black, 
    538 U.S. at 360
    . Yet the intent
    element merely says “intimidate,” without elaborating. So if
    we read the intent element’s use of “intimidate” to mean “plac-
    ing [a person] in fear of bodily harm or death,” we create an
    inconsistent-usage problem. Black, 
    538 U.S. at 360
    . Normally,
    where Congress uses different words, we read those words to
    have different meanings. See Antonin Scalia & Bryan A. Gar-
    ner, Reading Law: The Interpretation of Legal Texts 170
    (2012) (presumption of consistent usage). And that suggests
    Congress meant “intimidate” to mean something different from
    “intent to cause fear of harm or death.” The broad reading pro-
    duces that result; the narrow one does not.
    Plus, the other result element requires only that the act
    “cause[d] … substantial emotional distress.” § 2261A(2)(B).
    So causing “substantial emotional distress” presumably in-
    cludes something other than putting someone in fear of bodily
    harm. And someone who fears death or injury is usually dis-
    tressed too. Thus, the narrow reading would let the government
    charge most crimes under § 2261A(2)(B), leaving
    § 2261A(2)(A)’s fear element almost “meaningless.” Yates v.
    United States, 
    574 U.S. 528
    , 543 (2015) (canon against sur-
    plusage); see §§ 2261(b), 2261B(a) (setting the same penalties
    for both crimes). Statutes typically do not work that way.
    But though that problem borders on surplusage, it does not
    foreclose the narrower reading. Even under our narrow
    13
    reading, the result elements would not be entirely superfluous.
    Imagine a defendant who intended to make his victim fear
    death or injury but produced a lesser emotional result: perhaps
    an incompetent criminal whose vague “threats” succeed only
    in upsetting their recipient through sheer persistence. The
    emotional-distress result element would let the statute reach
    that cyberstalker.
    Besides, these surplusage and consistent-usage concerns
    are “not absolute.” Lamie v. U.S. Tr., 
    540 U.S. 526
    , 536 (2004).
    Congress is not always precise when drafting statutes; it occa-
    sionally “use[s] different words to denote the same concept.”
    Scalia & Garner, Reading Law 170. Thus, concerns about re-
    dundancy only “supply a clue as to the better interpretation of
    the statute.” Rimini St., Inc. v. Oracle USA, Inc., 
    139 S. Ct. 873
    ,
    881 (2019). And courts may accept a reading that creates sur-
    plusage if “some maxim point[s] in a different direction.”
    Chickasaw Nation v. United States, 
    534 U.S. 84
    , 94 (2001) (in-
    ternal quotation marks omitted). For instance, presuming “in-
    artful drafting,” the Supreme Court has accepted a construction
    of the Affordable Care Act that it acknowledged created sur-
    plusage. See King v. Burwell, 
    576 U.S. 473
    , 491 (2015).
    A second point in favor of the broad reading: it fits with
    how juries infer intent. We often instruct them to “consider the
    natural and probable results or consequences” of a defendant’s
    acts and ask if he “intended those results or consequences.”
    United States v. Sussman, 
    709 F.3d 155
    , 177 (3d Cir. 2013).
    Here, a jury would consider whether a defendant intended to
    cause the “substantial emotional distress” that resulted. On that
    approach, “intent to intimidate” could include intentionally
    14
    causing an emotional reaction generally (the broader reading),
    not just intentionally causing fear of physical harm (the nar-
    rower reading).
    But harassment statutes sometimes do limit a jury’s ability
    to lean on the natural and probable causes of conduct to infer
    the defendant’s intent. Indeed, a few states require prosecutors
    to show “intent to place [a] person in imminent fear of death or
    bodily injury” even when the result is mere “substantial emo-
    tional distress.” Commonwealth v. Cullen, 
    947 N.E.2d 1147
    ,
    1150 (Mass. App. Ct. 2011); accord State v. Diez, 
    811 So. 2d 1020
    , 1024 (La. Ct. App. 2002).
    Thus, though these textual clues suggest that the broader
    reading is the better reading, they do not render the narrower
    reading implausible. And other textual clues justify the nar-
    rower reading too: neighboring terms reinforce reading “intim-
    idate” and “harass” narrowly. When construing a word, we
    give it “more precise content” that fits with “the neighboring
    words with which it is associated.” Williams, 553 U.S. at 294
    (explaining the “commonsense canon of noscitur a sociis”).
    Here, both “kill” and “injure” are violent verbs. After those
    verbs, one naturally reads “intimidate” to mean putting the vic-
    tim in fear of death or injury. And one naturally reads “harass”
    to mean a course of conduct designed to distress the victim by
    threatening, intimidating, or the like. Yung’s campaign of ter-
    ror, inciting sexual violence against the interviewer and his
    family at their home, exemplifies the narrower kind of harass-
    ment and intimidation.
    To “intimidate,” we hold, a defendant must put the victim
    in fear of death or bodily injury. And to “harass,” he must
    15
    distress the victim by threatening, intimidating, or the like.
    That reading limits intent to harass to “criminal harassment,
    which is unprotected because it constitutes true threats or
    speech that is integral to proscribable criminal conduct.” Ac-
    kell, 907 F.3d at 76. It also limits “intent to intimidate” to what
    it “especially” means, a form of true threats or speech integral
    to a crime. Id.; Intimidate, OED. Those narrow readings ensure
    that protected speech largely escapes the law’s net. Thus, we
    can avoid the “strong medicine” of invalidating the statute as
    facially overbroad. Broadrick, 
    413 U.S. at 613
    .
    In reading the statute narrowly, we reaffirm our earlier de-
    cision upholding the cyberstalking statute. Gonzalez, 905 F.3d
    at 190 n.10 (2006 version). And we join every other circuit that
    has evaluated the law. United States v. Fleury, 
    20 F.4th 1353
    ,
    1362–63 (11th Cir. 2021) (current version); Ackell, 907 F.3d at
    77 (same); see also United States v. Sayer, 
    748 F.3d 425
    , 436
    (1st Cir. 2014) (2006 version); United States v. Bowker, 
    372 F.3d 365
    , 379 (6th Cir. 2004) (same), vacated on other
    grounds, 
    543 U.S. 1182
     (2005); United States v. Petrovic, 
    701 F.3d 849
    , 856 (8th Cir. 2012) (same); Osinger, 753 F.3d at
    944–45 (same).
    E. We will affirm, not vacate, Yung’s conviction
    Because we adopt this “limiting construction” to save the
    statute, Yung urges us not to affirm. Yung Br. 27 n.22. Rather,
    he claims, we should “vacate [his] conviction and remand with
    leave to withdraw his plea and reconsider his options under that
    new legal landscape.” Id. His brief does not say why. But at
    argument, his counsel hinted that, because Yung did not know
    16
    how we would later read the statute, his plea could not have
    been “knowing and intelligent.” Oral Arg. Tr. 9:13.
    Not so. For a defendant’s guilty plea to be knowing and in-
    telligent, he must be of sound mind, understand the nature of
    the charges and the direct penal consequences, and have the
    advice of competent counsel. Brady v. United States, 
    397 U.S. 742
    , 755–56 (1970). But he may not later withdraw his plea
    just because he “did not correctly assess every relevant factor
    entering into his decision.” 
    Id. at 757
    . For instance, even if a
    defendant pleaded guilty to avoid the threat of the death pen-
    alty, and a court later struck that threat down, his plea still
    stands as knowing. 
    Id. at 755
    .
    Indeed, at argument, Yung’s counsel argued that to vacate
    his conviction, we would have to craft a new guilty-plea rule
    for overbreadth challenges. Oral Arg. Tr. 10:13–11:9. But even
    if we were to consider that novel idea, Yung forfeited it: he
    tucks it into a single footnote, without supporting authority or
    analysis. John Wyeth & Bro. Ltd. v. CIGNA Int’l Corp., 
    119 F.3d 1070
    , 1076 n.6 (3d Cir. 1997) (Alito, J.). So his conviction
    stands.
    III. THE DISTRICT COURT PROPERLY ORDERED RESTITU-
    TION TO THE INTERVIEWER, BUT NOT GEORGETOWN
    The District Court ordered Yung to pay restitution to his
    victim and Georgetown. Yung challenges both orders, claim-
    ing that the statute does not authorize them. The government
    counters that Yung waived his right to appeal the orders. But
    any such waiver is unenforceable. And on the merits, only res-
    titution to the interviewer is authorized by statute.
    17
    A. Yung could not waive his claim that the restitution
    order exceeds the statute
    In his plea agreement, Yung waived “the right to file any
    appeal,” with limited exceptions. JA 122 ¶ 10. For instance, he
    “reserve[d] the right” to renew his overbreadth challenge and
    to contest any “sentence exceed[ing] the statutory maximum.”
    
    Id.
     Yet he never reserved the right to challenge the restitution
    order.
    Yung disagrees, arguing that his restitution order “exceeds
    the statutory maximum” because it is not “clearly authorized
    by [statute].” Reply Br. 8. But we have held that a restitution
    order can never exceed the “statutory maximum.” United
    States v. Leahy, 
    438 F.3d 328
    , 337–38 (3d Cir. 2006). That
    term implies some “range” of potential sentences from which
    the sentencing court must pick. 
    Id.
     Yet restitution statutes au-
    thorize only one award: “the full amount of each victim’s
    losses.” 
    Id.
     (quoting 
    18 U.S.C. § 3664
    (f)(1)(A)). “Thus, there
    is no restitution range” and no statutory maximum. 
    Id.
    Even so, we will not enforce Yung’s waiver of his right to
    challenge the restitution order. See United States v. Gordon,
    
    480 F.3d 1205
    , 1209–10 (10th Cir. 2007) (holding likewise).
    Doing so would let litigants subvert the Constitution’s struc-
    ture and thus “amount[ ] to a miscarriage of justice.” United
    States v. Khattak, 
    273 F.3d 557
    , 562 (3d Cir. 2001); see also
    United States v. Teeter, 
    257 F.3d 14
    , 25 n.10 (1st Cir. 2001).
    True, we let defendants waive most of their individual
    rights because we treat plea bargains like contracts. See United
    States v. Williams, 
    510 F.3d 416
    , 422 (3d Cir. 2007). A
    18
    defendant, for instance, can waive his rights to counsel, to a
    jury trial, and even to confront his accusers, if he does so know-
    ingly and voluntarily. United States v. Mezzanatto, 
    513 U.S. 196
    , 200–01 (1995).
    Still, there are limits. Plea bargains are agreements between
    the executive branch, charged with “tak[ing] Care that the
    Laws be faithfully executed,” and a defendant subject to those
    laws. U.S. Const. art. II, § 3. Judges must ensure that a bargain
    respects those laws. So if it offends these structural principles,
    we need not enforce it. See Nancy J. King, Priceless Process:
    Nonnegotiable Features of Criminal Litigation, 
    47 UCLA L. Rev. 113
    , 154–58, 166–72 (1999).
    Thus, when the executive branch threatens to intrude upon
    the legislature’s power in a case before us, judges must rebuff
    that encroachment. For instance, we should not let a defendant
    waive his right to appeal a conviction for acts that are not a
    crime. Cf. Brady, 
    397 U.S. at 758
    ; King, Priceless Process, at
    168–69. Otherwise, we would let the government and a private
    party de facto create a new crime. But only Congress has that
    power in our limited government. United States v. Hudson &
    Goodwin, 11 U.S. (7 Cranch) 32, 32 (1812). Even if the de-
    fendant consents, we cannot turn a blind eye to punishment for
    acts not criminalized by Congress. The judiciary must safe-
    guard the separation of powers.
    Likewise, a defendant cannot waive his right to appeal a
    sentence unauthorized by Congress. And we cannot enforce
    such a waiver. United States v. Cohen, 
    459 F.3d 490
    , 497–98
    (4th Cir. 2006); United States v. Thomas, 
    932 F.3d 1139
    , 1140–
    41 (8th Cir. 2019); United States v. Phillips, 
    174 F.3d 1074
    ,
    19
    1076 (9th Cir. 1999); Gordon, 
    480 F.3d at 1209
    ; see also
    United States v. Chem. & Metal Indus., 
    677 F.3d 750
    , 752 (5th
    Cir. 2012). If we did so, we would be crafting our own punish-
    ment and thus “intrud[ing] into areas committed to [an]other
    branch[ ] of government.” Flast v. Cohen, 
    392 U.S. 83
    , 95
    (1968). So Yung could not have waived his right to challenge
    whether the statute authorized his restitution order, and we
    must hear his appeal.
    B. The interviewer is entitled to restitution
    Now on to the merits. The District Court ordered Yung to
    pay the interviewer restitution for his investigative costs and
    attorney’s fees. The special restitution statute for cyberstalking
    victims is broad: it lets victims recover “attorneys’ fees” and
    “any … losses suffered … as a proximate result of the offense.”
    
    18 U.S.C. § 2264
    (b)(3)(E), (G); see also Lagos v. United
    States, 
    138 S. Ct. 1684
    , 1689 (2018) (discussing § 2264). The
    question, then, is whether the interviewer’s losses were a
    “direct and foreseeable” result of the crime. Paroline v. United
    States, 
    572 U.S. 434
    , 449 (2014) (parsing 
    18 U.S.C. § 2259
    (b),
    worded similarly to § 2264(b)).
    They were. Yung used pseudonyms to defame the inter-
    viewer and recruited others to threaten his family. To make that
    campaign of harassment stop, they needed to track Yung down,
    report him to the authorities, and get charges filed against him.
    Because those expenses were foreseeable, this restitution order
    is valid.
    20
    C. Georgetown is not entitled to restitution
    But Georgetown should not get restitution. Unlike the in-
    terviewer, Georgetown was never itself harassed. Though it
    worried that Yung might eventually target its campus, he never
    did. So Georgetown does not qualify for the special cyberstalk-
    ing restitution statute. See 
    18 U.S.C. § 2264
    (c) (defining “vic-
    tim[s]” eligible under that statute). Instead, it could claim res-
    titution only under the general restitution statute. That law is
    far more limited. It allows recovery only if Georgetown
    showed that Yung’s “offense result[ed] in damage to or de-
    struction of property.” 
    18 U.S.C. § 3663
    (b)(1). The govern-
    ment claims that the property that Yung damaged “was the
    safety and security of Georgetown’s campus.” Oral Arg. Tr.
    27:13.
    That is not enough, for two reasons. First, Georgetown can-
    not show that Yung damaged its property. Yung harmed no
    land, buildings, intellectual property, or the like. Rather, he
    threatened the safety of the campus, forcing Georgetown to
    beef up its security systems. We do not treat safety and security
    as a property right. True, we once extended restitution beyond
    tangible property to uphold restitution for a prosecutor’s loss
    of “hard-won convictions.” United States v. Hand, 
    863 F.2d 1100
    , 1104 (3d Cir. 1988). But Hand offered no definition or
    even explanation of how convictions could be property. And
    convictions are not analogous to safety on Georgetown’s cam-
    pus. So Hand does not persuade us to depart from the ordinary
    understanding of property here. See Gov’t of V.I. v. Davis, 
    43 F.3d 41
    , 46 (3d Cir. 1994) (distinguishing and limiting Hand).
    21
    Even if safety and security were property, Georgetown
    showed no damage to them. “Damage … reduces the value or
    usefulness of the [property] or spoils its appearance.” United
    States v. Quillen, 
    335 F.3d 219
    , 225 (3d Cir. 2003) (quoting
    Oxford American Dictionary 214 (1980)). For instance, we
    held that an anthrax scare damaged a mail room by making it
    temporarily “unusable.” 
    Id. at 222
    . Yet Yung’s threats never
    made Georgetown’s campus unusable for students and faculty,
    or its security systems unusable for run-of-the-mill disturb-
    ances. Nor does Georgetown say that its security systems were
    unhelpful in dealing with Yung. It says only that it “had to de-
    ploy numerous, continuous security measures above and be-
    yond the customary means and methods” to protect its prop-
    erty. JA 518–19. That is not enough.
    * * * * *
    Cyberstalking is a serious crime that calls for serious pun-
    ishment. But courts must be vigilant to keep crimes and pun-
    ishments within the bounds of law. Cyberstalking laws must be
    read narrowly to avoid punishing protected speech. We cannot
    enforce appellate waivers that violate the separation of powers.
    And we must keep penalties within the confines authorized by
    Congress.
    Here, we are confident that Yung’s conviction is lawful, as
    is his duty to compensate the interviewer for the harm he
    caused. But because Georgetown suffered no damage to any
    property right, we will vacate that restitution order.
    22