Bryan Manning v. Donald Caldwell , 900 F.3d 139 ( 2018 )


Menu:
  •                                           PUBLISHED
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE FOURTH CIRCUIT
    No. 17-1320
    BRYAN MANNING; RYAN WILLIAMS; RICHARD DECKERHOFF;
    RICHARD EUGENE WALLS,
    Plaintiffs - Appellants,
    v.
    DONALD CALDWELL, Commonwealth’s Attorney for the City of Roanoke;
    MICHAEL NEHEMIAH HERRING, Commonwealth’s Attorney for the City of
    Richmond,
    Defendants - Appellees,
    ------------------------------
    NATIONAL LAW CENTER ON HOMELESSNESS & POVERTY,
    Amicus Supporting Appellant.
    Appeal from the United States District Court for the Western District of Virginia, at
    Roanoke. Glen E. Conrad, District Judge. (7:16-cv-00095-GEC)
    Argued: January 24, 2018                                    Decided: August 9, 2018
    Before WILKINSON, NIEMEYER, and MOTZ, Circuit Judges.
    Affirmed by published opinion. Judge Wilkinson wrote the opinion, in which Judge
    Niemeyer joined. Judge Motz wrote an opinion concurring in the judgment.
    ARGUED: Jonathan Lee Marcus, SKADDEN, ARPS, SLATE, MEAGHER & FLOM,
    LLP, Washington, D.C., for Appellants. Trevor Stephen Cox, OFFICE OF THE
    ATTORNEY GENERAL OF VIRGINIA, Richmond, Virginia, for Appellees. ON
    BRIEF: Mark D. Young, Maureen A. Donley, Donald P. Salzman, Theodore M. Kneller,
    Shekida A. Smith, Daniel B. O’Connell, SKADDEN, ARPS, SLATE, MEAGHER, &
    FLOM, LLP, Washington, D.C.; Mary Frances Charlton, Angela Ciolfi, Elaine Poon,
    LEGAL AID JUSTICE CENTER, Charlottesville, Virginia, for Appellants. Mark R.
    Herring, Attorney General, Matthew R. McGuire, Assistant Solictor General, OFFICE
    OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF VIRGINIA, Richmond, Virginia, for Appellees.
    Eric S. Tars, NATIONAL LAW CENTER ON HOMELESSNESS & POVERTY,
    Washington, D.C.; Richard P. Bress, Andrew D. Prins, George C. Chipev, Ryan C.
    Grover, LATHAM & WATKINS LLP, Washington, D.C., for Amicus Curiae.
    2
    WILKINSON, Circuit Judge:
    Virginia law criminalizes the possession, purchase, or consumption of alcohol by
    someone who has been interdicted by a Virginia court. Interdiction is a civil order
    designating that a person is a “habitual drunkard” or has been convicted of driving while
    intoxicated. In this case, a group of homeless people suffering from alcoholism
    challenged the constitutionality of Virginia’s interdiction statute under the Eighth
    Amendment’s prohibition on criminalizing status, and the Fourteenth Amendment’s
    guarantee of Due Process and Equal Protection. The district court dismissed the suit,
    concluding that the statutory scheme criminalizes acts rather than status, affords adequate
    process, and implicates no suspect class. We agree with appellants that states must tread
    carefully to avoid criminalizing status. But for the reasons that follow, we affirm.
    I.
    Virginia regulates the consumption, purchase, manufacture, and sale of alcohol
    through a series of interconnecting provisions found in Title 4.1 of the Virginia Code.
    Under § 4.1-333, a Virginia court may, “after a hearing upon due notice,” issue a
    civil interdiction order to any person who “has been convicted of driving any automobile,
    truck, motorcycle, engine or train while intoxicated or has shown himself to be an
    habitual drunkard.”
    An interdicted person is subject to several restrictions on his conduct. Section 4.1-
    322 makes it a Class 1 misdemeanor for an interdicted person to “possess any alcoholic
    beverages” or to “be drunk in public” in violation of another statutory provision. Section
    4.1-305 similarly makes it a Class 1 misdemeanor for an interdicted person (or someone
    3
    under 21 years of age) to “consume, purchase or possess, or attempt to consume,
    purchase or possess, any alcoholic beverage,” except in certain statutorily exempt
    circumstances such as the use of medicines containing alcohol.
    In Virginia, a Class 1 misdemeanor is punishable by “confinement in jail for not
    more than twelve months and a fine of not more than $2,500, either or both.” 
    Va. Code Ann. § 18.2-11
     (2014). Any defendant charged with a Class 1 misdemeanor must be
    informed of his right to counsel, and “shall be allowed a reasonable opportunity to
    employ counsel,” or, if indigent, to obtain court-appointed counsel. 
    Va. Code Ann. §§ 19.2-157
    , 19.2-159 (2015).
    Appellants are four homeless men who were interdicted and later prosecuted for
    using or possessing alcohol. Bryan Manning was interdicted on October 5, 2010, in the
    Circuit Court for the City of Roanoke. Ryan Williams was interdicted on February 7,
    2012, in the Circuit Court for the City of Roanoke. Richard Deckerhoff was interdicted
    on August 21, 2009, in the Circuit Court for the City of Petersburg. And Richard Eugene
    Walls was interdicted on June 12, 2012, in the Circuit Court for the City of Richmond.
    Each has been prosecuted at least eleven times for violating the alcohol restrictions
    resulting from his interdiction order.
    Appellants filed suit in the United States District Court for the Western District of
    Virginia. The complaint, brought on behalf of a putative class of “all persons in Virginia
    who are homeless and who suffer from alcoholism,” sought declaratory and injunctive
    relief against Roanoke Commonwealth’s Attorney Donald Caldwell, Richmond
    Commonwealth’s Attorney Michael Herring, and “all Virginia Commonwealth’s
    4
    Attorneys with the authority to enforce the Interdiction Statute against homeless
    individuals suffering from alcoholism.” J.A. 28, 30. It alleged that Virginia Code §§ 4.1-
    333, 4.1-305, and 4.1-322 imposed cruel and unusual punishment by criminalizing the
    status of alcohol addiction; deprived plaintiffs of Due Process by converting the first step
    of a criminal proceeding into a civil proceeding; and violated Equal Protection by treating
    homeless alcoholics differently from non-homeless alcoholics.
    The district court dismissed the suit for failure to state a claim. With regard to the
    Eighth Amendment challenge, the court concluded that possession or consumption of
    alcohol “is an act, regardless of whether that possession or consumption is in public or in
    the confines of [one’s] own home,” and therefore the statute’s application to plaintiffs did
    not criminalize their status. J.A. 83. As to the Due Process claim, the court was “not
    convinced that plaintiffs have pled facts demonstrating that the civil interdiction hearings
    deprive them of their physical liberty,” and therefore found no constitutional defect in the
    process afforded by the statute. Id. at 85. Finally, with regard to the Equal Protection
    claim, the court found no discriminatory intent, no fundamental right, and no protected
    class to outweigh the Commonwealth’s legitimate interest in discouraging alcohol abuse.
    This appeal followed. We review de novo a district court’s grant of a motion to
    dismiss. E.I. du Pont de Nemours & Co. v. Kolon Indus., Inc., 
    637 F.3d 435
    , 440 (4th Cir.
    2011).
    II.
    5
    We first consider whether Virginia’s interdiction statute, § 4.1-333, qualifies as
    cruel and unusual punishment because it criminalizes appellants’ status as homeless
    alcoholics in violation of Robinson v. California, 
    370 U.S. 660
     (1962).
    The Eighth Amendment states that “[e]xcessive bail shall not be required, nor
    excessive fines imposed, nor cruel and unusual punishments inflicted.” U.S. Const.
    Amend. VIII. In addition to “limit[ing] the kinds of punishment that can be imposed on
    those convicted of crimes,” and “proscrib[ing] punishment grossly disproportionate to the
    severity of the crime,” the Eighth Amendment also “imposes substantive limits on what
    can be made criminal and punished as such.” Ingraham v. Wright, 
    430 U.S. 651
    , 667
    (1977).
    In Robinson v. California, the Supreme Court recognized one such substantive
    limit by holding that states could not declare someone a criminal simply on account of his
    status. 
    370 U.S. at 666-67
     (1962). The Court was considering a California law that made
    it a misdemeanor “to be addicted to the use of narcotics.” 
    Id.
     at 660 (citing Cal. Health
    and Safety Code § 11721). The statute did not require proof that an alleged drug addict
    had actually used or possessed drugs, but only that he was in fact a drug addict. Because
    a “person may be continuously guilty of this offense, whether or not he has ever used or
    possessed any narcotics within the State, and whether or not he has been guilty of any
    antisocial behavior there,” the Court invalidated the California law as cruel and unusual
    punishment. Id. at 666.
    The Robinson court was careful to note that the “broad power of the State to
    regulate the narcotic drugs traffic within its borders” was not at issue. Id. at 664. Indeed,
    6
    a “State might impose criminal sanctions, for example, against the unauthorized
    manufacture, prescription, sale, purchase, or possession of narcotics” because those
    things constitute punishable conduct, not status. Id. The Court in Robinson thus
    considered and rejected the possibility that its holding could be read to prevent states
    from criminalizing the “purchase, sale, or possession” of contraband. Because the holding
    of Robinson is so emphatic on this point, it is worth quoting the relevant paragraph in
    full:
    The broad power of the state to regulate the narcotic drug traffic within its
    borders is not here in issue. More than forty years ago, this Court explicitly
    recognized the validity of that power: There can be no question of the
    authority of the state in the exercise of its police power to regulate the
    administration, sale, prescription and use of dangerous and habitforming
    drugs. The right to exercise this power is so manifest in the interest of the
    public health and welfare, that it is unnecessary to enter upon a discussion
    of it beyond saying that it is too firmly established to be successfully called
    in question.
    Id. at 664 (quotations and alterations omitted).
    The Supreme Court revisited the distinction between conduct and status in Powell
    v. Texas, 
    392 U.S. 514
    , 514 (1968). In that case, an alcoholic challenged the
    constitutionality of a Texas law prohibiting public drunkenness on the ground that his
    status as an addict compelled him to violate the statute. In a divided opinion, the Supreme
    Court upheld the Texas law. 
    Id.
     A four-justice plurality found that it was not the lack of
    volition on the part of the offender, but the lack of any conduct whatsoever, that had
    created a constitutional infirmity in Robinson, and that no such defect existed in the
    Texas law. 
    Id. at 533
     (“[C]riminal penalties may be inflicted only if the accused has
    committed some act, has engaged in some behavior, which society has an interest in
    7
    preventing, or perhaps in historical common law terms, has committed some actus
    reus.”).
    Justice White, who cast the decisive fifth vote, wanted to leave open the question
    of whether conduct compelled by addiction might be protected under Robinson. But
    because Powell “made no showing that he was unable to stay off the streets on the night
    in question,” Justice White voted to uphold the conviction on the ground that Powell’s
    behavior involved a volitional act. 
    Id. at 553-54
    . Justice White wrote that it was
    “unnecessary to pursue at this point the further definition of the circumstances or the state
    of intoxication which might bar conviction of a chronic alcoholic for being drunk in a
    public place.” 
    Id. at 553
    .
    Appellants argue that Justice White’s opinion in Powell requires this court to hold
    that Virginia’s statutory scheme imposes cruel and unusual punishment because it
    criminalizes their status as homeless alcoholics. Specifically, appellants contend that
    because they face an irresistible compulsion to drink, they had no choice but to yield to
    their compulsion and consume alcohol in violation of the law. But that is not Powell’s
    holding. As Judge Wilkey wrote more than forty-five years ago, “the interpretation that
    Robinson held that it was not criminal to give in to the irresistible compulsion of a
    ‘disease[]’ weaves in and out of the Powell opinions, but there [was] definitely no
    Supreme Court holding to this effect.” Moore v. United States, 
    486 F.2d 1139
    , 1150
    (D.C. Cir. 1973) (en banc) (plurality opinion). Indeed, Justice White himself nowhere
    suggested that Powell provided the occasion for a broad holding of any nature, much less
    a platform for a declaration that Robinson was no longer good law or had been
    8
    overturned. Powell, 
    392 U.S. at 553
     (White, J. concurring in the result) (“For the
    purposes of this case, it is necessary to say only that Powell . . . made no showing that he
    was unable to stay off the streets on the night in question.”). The dissenters in Powell in
    fact sought an extension of Robinson along the lines of what our colleague advocates
    today, 
    id. at 567
     (Fortas, J. dissenting, joined by Douglas, Brennan, Stewart, JJ.), but
    Justice White did not join them.
    In fact, in the fifty years since the Supreme Court decided Powell, there has been a
    large chorus of circuit opinions—including in this court, Fisher v. Coleman, 
    639 F.2d 191
     (4th Cir. 1981)—upholding state laws criminalizing acts that were allegedly
    compelled. For instance, the Seventh Circuit held that an alcoholic who violated the
    terms of his parole by consuming alcohol “was not punished for his status as an alcoholic
    but for his conduct. Therefore, his claim for cruel and unusual punishment fails.” United
    States v. Stenson, 475 Fed.Appx 630, 631 (7th Cir. 2012) (“Under Powell, punishment
    for unlawful conduct resulting from alcoholism is permissible.”); see also Joshua v.
    Adams, 
    231 Fed.Appx. 592
    , 594 (9th Cir. 2007) (“Joshua also contends that the state
    court ignored his mental illness [schizophrenia], which rendered him unable to control his
    behavior, and his sentence was actually a penalty for his illness. . . . This contention is
    without merit because, in contrast to Robinson, where a statute specifically criminalized
    addiction, Joshua was convicted of a criminal offense separate and distinct from his
    “status” as a schizophrenic.”); Joel v. City of Orlando, 
    232 F.3d 1353
    , 1362 (11th Cir.
    2000) (“A distinction exists between applying criminal laws to punish conduct, which is
    constitutionally permissible, and applying them to punish status, which is not.”); United
    9
    States v. Benefield, 
    889 F.2d 1061
    , 1064 (11th. Cir. 1989) (“The considerations that make
    any incarceration unconstitutional when a statute punishes a defendant for his status are
    not applicable when the government seeks to punish a person’s actions.”). Our concurring
    colleague chides these decisions upholding the criminalization of various acts for their
    brevity. See Concurring Op. at 30 n.1. But brevity can serve as an indication that courts
    have simply found the resolution of this issue to be plain and straightforward.
    The Powell decision, as we earlier noted, was a 4-1-4 decision. In United States v.
    Hughes, decided earlier this year, the Supreme Court found that it was “unnecessary to
    consider” its holding in Marks that the lower federal courts should follow the narrowest
    rationale for the holding that received five votes. No. 17–155, slip op. at 3, 584 U.S. ____
    (2018) (discussing Marks v. United States, 
    430 U.S. 188
    , 193 (1977)). To the extent that
    post-Powell decisions have relied upon the plurality opinion in Powell, they have
    overextended themselves in doing so. There was no majority holding that nonvolitional
    conduct could invariably be criminalized. But again, as Judge Wilkey noted, neither was
    there any holding that Robinson or the status-act distinction was overturned. In the
    absence of such a ruling and any sort of clear signal from the Supreme Court that
    Robinson no longer remains good law, we think ourselves bound to respect that decision
    until some clearer and more definitive guidance emerges. Those who see in the Powell
    decision a fulsome embrace or a wholesale repudiation of Robinson are simply pushing
    the matter too far.
    What we are left with, then, is simply a matter of fact. And as a matter of fact, for
    the past fifty years courts have consistently affirmed Robinson’s basic holding: although
    10
    states may not criminalize status, they may criminalize actual behavior even when the
    individual alleges that addiction created a strong urge to engage in a particular act. In
    doing so, courts have respected the Supreme Court’s admonition that Robinson not be
    interpreted to undercut longstanding drug and alcohol laws. See Robinson, 
    370 U.S. at 664
     (affirming that states could continue to criminalize the “sale, purchase, or possession
    of narcotics.”). To the extent that these courts have relied upon Powell to reach this
    decision, they have erred in doing so. To the extent, however, that they discerned that
    Robinson had not been overturned, they were not wrong.
    In concurrence, our colleague would go beyond both Robinson and those portions
    of Justice White’s opinion in Powell that were necessary to the result, instead developing
    a new constitutional rule from those issues that Justice White explicitly deemed
    “unnecessary to pursue” in the case. Powell, 
    392 U.S. at 553
    . Under our colleague’s new
    rule, the Eighth Amendment would prevent the criminalization of conduct that is
    “proximate[ly]” caused by “[non]volitional acts.” Concurring Op. at 28. It has been
    almost 60 years since Robinson and 50 years since Powell were handed down. If the view
    of our concurring colleague had been adopted, there would presumably be some evidence
    during the long stretch of time since Robinson that some court had done so. Our
    colleague, however, is met with a dearth of authority, and she references no other circuit
    court that agrees with so far-reaching an Eighth Amendment view. The one circuit
    opinion she does reference was later vacated. Jones v. City of Los Angeles, 444. F3d 1118
    (9th Cir. 2006), vacated as moot following settlement, 
    505 F.3d 1006
     (9th Cir. 2007). See
    J.A. 78 (citing Lehr v. City of Sacramento, 
    624 F. Supp. 2d 1218
    , 1225 (2009) (“This
    11
    Court finds that, though the Jones opinion is informative, it is not binding, and the Court
    will limit the weight given the decision accordingly.”); Anderson v. City of Portland, No.
    08–1447–AA, 
    2009 WL 2386056
    , at *7 (D. Or. July 31, 2009) (“Ultimately, I part
    company with the reasoning employed by Jones.”)).
    The small smattering of other authority that the concurrence references are not
    only in a distinct minority, but also deal with a different question from the one presented
    here, namely the impossibility of controlling a bodily function. See Concurring Op. at 30
    (citing Pottinger v. City of Miami, 
    810 F. Supp. 1551
    , 1565 (S.D. Fla. 1992) (“For
    plaintiffs, resisting the need to eat, sleep or engage in other life-sustaining activities is
    impossible.”)). This is simply different from the concept of compelled behavior that our
    colleague espouses. So yet again, the question for us is whether we should permit a 4-1-4
    opinion that is at most ambiguous to overturn or greatly extend a longstanding and widely
    recognized Supreme Court opinion that the Court itself has never seen fit to repudiate or
    otherwise disavow. It is in the end a matter of respecting both the Supreme Court’s
    authority to overturn its own decisions, see Rodriguez de Quijas v. Shearson/Am.
    Express, Inc., 
    490 U.S. 477
    , 484 (1989) (“[T]he Court of Appeals should . . . leav[e] to
    this Court the prerogative of overruling its own decisions.”), and the limits of a circuit
    court’s authority to find circuitous routes around higher controlling precedent.
    III.
    A.
    12
    Consistent with the above discussion, it is the act of possessing alcohol—not the
    status of being an alcoholic—that gives rise to criminal sanctions. Virginia has been
    careful to draft a statutory scheme that falls on the constitutional side of the line drawn in
    Robinson. The interdiction provision set forth in § 4.1-333 is a civil enactment. An
    interdiction order is not accompanied by imprisonment or a punitive fine. The Eighth
    Amendment’s prohibition on “cruel and unusual punishment” has obvious criminal
    purposes. A provision that puts a person on notice that future acts may result in criminal
    sanctions does not criminalize status for the simple reason that it does not criminalize
    anything. It is the other Virginia provisions, not § 4.1-333, that impose criminal
    sanctions.
    While criminal prohibitions do come into play in §§ 4.1-322 and 4.1-305, those
    prohibitions apply only to affirmative acts: to “possess any alcoholic beverages” or to “be
    drunk in public,” and to “consume, purchase or possess, or attempt to consume, purchase
    or possess, any alcoholic beverage.” Appellants were arrested on the basis of committing
    these acts. That stands in stark contrast to the statute at issue in Robinson, under which a
    defendant could be charged even if he had never “used or possessed narcotics.” 
    370 U.S. at 666
    .
    We emphasize what we hope would be obvious: it would be unlawful for the state
    to simply round up “undesirable” persons based on their perceived status as addicts or
    drunkards. Cf. Papachristou v. City of Jacksonville, 
    405 U.S. 156
     (1972). It is inimical to
    personal liberty to bring criminal charges on the basis of who someone is. For that
    reason, there must be some behavioral link set forth in the law. But Virginia has been
    13
    careful to observe that line. It has prohibited individuals deemed at a higher risk of
    alcohol abuse from possessing or consuming alcohol. This includes not only habitual
    drunkards, but also people who have been convicted of drunk driving and those under
    twenty-one. See § 4.1-305.
    B.
    To accept appellants’ claim that there is no difference between alcohol addiction
    and the act of consuming alcohol would threaten to change the character of criminal law
    as we know it. Such a position has no plain limiting principle.
    We do not state this lightly. It is wise not to accept casually every “slippery slope”
    or “open-the-floodgates” argument that comes along. But in this case the potential
    breadth of the principle espoused by appellants is apparent. Every criminal act can be
    alleged to be the result of some compulsion. If human behavior is viewed as something
    over which human beings lack control, and for which they are not responsible, the
    implications are boundless. The examples extend beyond the discrete context of
    substance addiction. For instance, child molesters could challenge their convictions on
    the basis that their criminal acts were the product of uncontrollable pedophilic urges and
    therefore beyond the purview of criminal law. See Kansas v. Hendricks, 
    521 U.S. 346
    ,
    362 (1997) (upholding a sex offender statute where the law in question defined sex
    offenders as “suffering from a ‘mental abnormality’ or a ‘personality disorder’ that
    prevents them from exercising adequate control over their behavior”). The same could be
    said not only of sex offenders, but of stalkers, domestic abusers, and others driven by
    impulses they were allegedly powerless to check.
    14
    That is not to say that the criminal justice system is or should be unaware of the
    mitigating character of allegedly nonvolitional conduct. The criminal justice system
    already has in place numerous features designed to mitigate nonvolitional conduct,
    among them mens rea requirements (willfully, knowingly); affirmative defenses such as
    provocation, self-defense, and in extreme cases insanity; and of course sentencing
    proceedings where any nonvolitional characteristic or circumstance can be appraised by a
    sentencing judge. Those approaches to nonvolitional conduct often rely upon various
    combinations of legislative and judicial input, and they are more sensitive and balanced
    than the constitutional theory appellants propound in the instant case.
    C.
    Other features of the Virginia law likewise suffer no constitutional infirmity.
    Targeting alcohol abuse as Virginia has done is a prophylactic measure. It was
    permissible for the Commonwealth to regard the acts of purchasing or consuming alcohol
    as something that could lead persons with a history of heavy drinking to dangerous
    driving, domestic abuse, and sexual assault, among other criminal acts. The Virginia
    statutes affect rich and poor alike. They apply to a wide swath of society.
    The use of prophylactic measures to sanction relatively minor acts in order to
    forestall more serious criminal misconduct is hardly uncommon. Many statutory schemes
    adopt a two-step approach: first, a civil or criminal determination identifies certain people
    more likely to commit serial or grave offenses. Second, that determination imposes
    criminal sanctions on what might seem to be relatively minor infractions in order to head
    off more harmful behavior. For example, the Sex Offender Registration and Notification
    15
    Act (SORNA) requires federal sex offenders to notify the states where they live and work
    of their prior conviction. See 
    34 U.S.C. § 20913
    . Once the prior conviction has
    established that a person poses a social risk, his mere failure to register can give rise to
    criminal liability. 
    Id.
     In that way, SORNA uses criminal law to ensure that sexual
    offenders cannot fly under the radar. Similarly, federal criminal law prohibits otherwise
    routine firearms purchases by individuals who have been found by a court in a civil
    proceeding to be mentally incompetent. Such restrictions reduce the risk those people
    pose to themselves and to others. See 
    18 U.S.C. §§ 922
    (g)(4) and 924(a)(2). By the same
    token, a domestic abuser who violates a civil Temporary Restraining Order can be subject
    to criminal contempt proceedings. See, e.g., Va. Code 19.2-152.10, et seq. Once someone
    is found to pose a risk to his spouse or child, the simple act of coming within a certain
    distance of the protected persons or their home can give rise to criminal liability. Again,
    in this way, sanctioning a small act serves as a prophylactic measure designed to prevent
    the commission of a more serious crime.
    Virginia’s alcohol laws adopt precisely this approach. In fact, the very mechanism
    by which the state deters alcohol abuse by minors involves the criminalization of acts that
    are generally legal for the adult population. The same statute that prohibits interdicted
    people from possessing or consuming alcohol also applies to people who are under
    twenty-one. See Va. Code § 4.1-305. All of these laws have one thing in common: they
    apply milder sanctions to less serious infractions such as possession or failure to register
    in order to reduce the risk of grave misconduct involving sexual predation, gun violence,
    or fatal accidents on the road.
    16
    Appellants, however, criticize Virginia’s approach for its alleged selectivity. They
    argue first that Title 4.1 singles out homeless people. While this contention sounds more
    in the nature of a disparate impact equal protection claim than an Eighth Amendment
    one, see infra section V, it is also incorrect. The statutory scheme addresses the problem
    of drunkenness in its totality. The criminal prohibitions against possessing, purchasing, or
    consuming alcohol apply both outside and inside a person’s home. They apply whenever
    a non-homeless person leaves home to drive somewhere or attend a party or go to a sports
    bar.
    Our concurring colleague takes a different position, arguing that a statute is fatally
    selective if it criminalizes “otherwise legal behavior” for a subset of the population. On
    this view, the legislature can only prohibit acts when the law would “lead to criminal
    liability for everyone who commits them.” Concurring Op. at 34-35. Such a limitation is
    both wholly lacking in authority and ignores the valid reasons why prohibitions apply to
    some population cohorts and not to others. The reason is simply this: past actions have
    given rise to present and future risks. To say that a state acts impermissibly on this basis
    would be an astonishing proposition, and prohibit legislative bodies from making the
    altogether practical assessment of risky behaviors that is entirely within the legislative
    prerogative. Such risk assessment has commonly led to limits on the uses of automobiles,
    firearms, alcohol and the like in order to lessen recognized social harms. The fact that
    these legislative judgments result in additional burdens for some groups, such as sex
    offenders, felons, or minors, does not change the Eighth Amendment analysis. To find
    otherwise would be to do with the Eighth Amendment what the Equal Protection Clause
    17
    wisely does not, and that is to make suspect classes out of all groups who pose special
    and heightened risks to the community. See infra Part V.
    Appellants also allege police misconduct in the execution of this particular
    statutory scheme. However, this challenge seems more appropriately addressed through
    the Fourth Amendment. If there were arrests based on undesirable status and divorced
    from any behavioral link, such police behavior would run afoul of that amendment. In
    this sense, the Fourth and Eighth Amendments occupy distinct but supplementary
    domains. The Fourth Amendment requires probable cause to undertake an arrest or
    search, which means probable cause to believe a forbidden act, as required by the Eighth
    Amendment, has been committed. The concurrence maintains that homeless alcoholics
    have been arrested “simply because of their presence in a Walmart or near a discarded
    beer can.” Concurring Op. at 37. If that truly is all there is, there would be no probable
    cause for an arrest, but appellants decline to press their case under any Fourth
    Amendment theory. The appropriate tonic for police overreach is exclusion of evidence
    or a civil suit under 
    42 U.S.C. § 1983
     and not, as appellants urge, driving a stake through
    an entire statutory scheme.
    D.
    To say that Virginia’s approach, as described above, is unconstitutional thus not
    only misreads its purpose, but also engages in policy choices reserved largely for
    legislatures and substantially for the states. The reason for legislative responsibility for
    defining substantive criminal prohibitions is fundamental; the criminal law exists to
    protect the safety of citizens, and ensuring the safety of the people is one of those things
    18
    government exists to do. State legislatures thus have considerable latitude under their
    police power to address societal ills, and substantive criminal law has historically been
    reserved to them. What behavior to criminalize is not an exclusive state responsibility,
    but it is a core one. See Rachel E. Barkow, Our Federal System of Sentencing, 58 STAN.
    L. REV. 119, 119 (2005) (“The federal system of the United States is based on the
    bedrock premise that the states bear primary responsibility for criminal justice policy.”).
    States have a variety of tools with which to approach persistent social ills. The most
    thoughtful approaches are often the product of democratic input, expert opinion,
    cumulative experience, and simple trial and error. That is why the Eighth Amendment
    typically focuses on conditions of confinement, and inhumane forms and disproportionate
    lengths of punishment, rather than acting as a vehicle to reshape policy choices embedded
    within substantive criminal laws. See Sanford H. Kadish, Fifty Years of Criminal Law:
    An Opinionated Review, 87 CAL. L. REV. 943, 964-66 (1999).
    There is, when all is said and done, a balance to be struck. States cannot ignore the
    line between status and acts. The criminal law and the constitutional limitations within
    which it operates are founded on the premise that human dignity is universal, and arrests
    and punishments alike are indefensible when based on who people are rather than what
    they do. It is a basic transgression on American liberty to brand someone a criminal and
    then prosecute that person without any underlying criminal conduct. And it is the practice
    of totalitarian regimes, not our free society, to substitute a personal characteristic for a
    prohibited act.
    19
    But it is also important not to hamstring a state’s use of criminal prohibitions to
    protect its citizenry. Here, as noted, Virginia has opted to approach the problem of
    alcohol abuse prophylactically and prescriptively. The prophylactic prong is reflected in
    § 4.1-333. The interdiction order is a preventive tool. The state can use this sort of
    prophylactic device to identify those at the highest risk of alcohol problems and put them
    on notice that subsequent behavior may be subject to punishment. It is not
    constitutionally impermissible for the state to proceed in this manner so long as the line
    between status and act is scrupulously observed.
    IV.
    We next consider whether the interdiction provision, Virginia Code § 4.1-333,
    violates appellants’ Fourteenth Amendment right to Due Process. Appellants argue that
    despite their nominally civil character, interdiction proceedings must afford criminal
    protections such as appointed counsel and be governed by the reasonable doubt standard
    because criminal sanctions against an interdicted homeless alcoholic are “inevitable.”
    Opening Br. of Appellant at 38.
    Due Process guarantees an indigent defendant the right to appointed counsel when
    the nature of a civil or criminal proceeding is such that “if he loses, he may be deprived
    of his physical liberty.” Lassiter v. Dep’t of Soc. Servs. of Durham Cty., N.C., 
    452 U.S. 18
    , 27 (1981). Due Process also requires that every element of a crime be proved beyond
    a reasonable doubt. See In re Winship, 
    397 U.S. 358
    , 364 (1970).
    Neither of these requirements applies to Virginia’s interdiction provision.
    Interdiction alone carries no threat of imprisonment. The fact that it may “provide a basis
    20
    for . . . subsequent prosecution” does not “bring[] an immediate and automatic loss of
    liberty.” Ferguson v. Gathright, 
    485 F.2d 504
    , 506 (4th Cir. 1973). An interdicted person
    loses only the legal right to purchase, possess, or consume alcohol. There is no
    constitutionally protected liberty or property interest in such a right. See Collins v. Hall,
    
    991 F. Supp. 1065
    , 1071-72 (N.D. Ind. 1997) (rejecting a Due Process challenge to a
    habitual drunkard statute because the plaintiff did not “suffer[] a deprivation of a liberty
    interest protected by the federal constitution”). Appellants possess an understandable
    interest in not being labeled “habitual drunkards.” But the Supreme Court has been
    careful to leave redress of reputational injuries to state law. See Paul v. Davis, 
    424 U.S. 693
    , 701 (1976) (The Fourteenth Amendment is not “a font of tort law to be
    superimposed upon whatever systems may already be administered by the States.”). With
    no constitutionally protected interest at stake, the right to counsel cannot attach to an
    interdiction proceeding.
    As for proof beyond a reasonable doubt, it suffices to reiterate that interdiction is
    not a criminal proceeding. Appellants’ argument elides interdiction with subsequent
    prosecutions. But these are legally distinct proceedings rooted in separate statutory
    provisions. The notice and hearing provided in § 4.1-333 satisfies the process that is due
    in the civil context. See Plumer v. Maryland, 
    915 F.2d 927
    , 931 (4th Cir. 1990). And
    appellants do not point to any evidence that Virginia afforded them anything less than the
    full panoply of procedural protections in their subsequent criminal prosecutions.
    V.
    21
    Finally, we consider whether the interdiction provision violates appellants’
    Fourteenth Amendment right to Equal Protection under the law. Appellants argue that the
    statute violates this principle by “intentionally treating . . . homeless alcoholics
    differently from non-homeless alcoholics,” and that this discriminatory treatment
    mandates strict scrutiny. Opening Br. of Appellants at 45.
    When faced with an Equal Protection challenge, the great majority of legislative
    enactments are subject to rational basis review. That is, we ask whether the law is
    rationally related to some legitimate government interest. See, e.g., Star Sci. Inc. v.
    Beales, 
    278 F.3d 339
    , 351 (4th Cir. 2002). Only those laws that implicate a fundamental
    constitutional right or employ a suspect classification—typically some immutable
    characteristic such as race or sex—receive heightened scrutiny. See City of New Orleans
    v. Dukes, 
    427 U.S. 297
    , 303 (1976). (“Unless a classification trammels fundamental
    personal rights or is drawn upon inherently suspect distinctions such as race, religion, or
    alienage, our decisions presume the constitutionality of the statutory discriminations and
    require only that the classification challenged be rationally related to a legitimate state
    interest.”).
    There is no fundamental right or suspect class at issue here. The freedom to drink
    alcohol is not “implicit in the concept of ordered liberty such that neither liberty nor
    justice would exist if [it] were sacrificed.” See Washington v. Glucksberg, 
    521 U.S. 702
    ,
    720-21 (1997) (internal quotation marks omitted). And while their plight is worthy of
    both understanding and compassion, those afflicted with alcohol addiction and who lack
    permanent housing are not a suspect class for Equal Protection purposes. See Mitchell v.
    22
    Comm’r of the SSA, 
    182 F.3d 272
    , 274 (4th Cir. 1999) (“Alcoholics are neither a suspect
    nor a quasi-suspect class for purposes of equal protection analysis.”); Joel v. City of
    Orlando, 
    232 F.3d 1353
    , 1357 (11th Cir. 2000) (“Homeless persons are not a suspect
    class.”). Even more fundamentally, Virginia’s interdiction statute does not single out
    homeless alcoholics for different treatment. That it may disproportionately affect one
    group over another, as innumerable statutes do, does not make for unconstitutional
    discrimination.
    Having established that the interdiction statute need only satisfy rational basis
    review, we can promptly conclude the inquiry. Virginia has a legitimate interest in
    discouraging alcohol abuse and its attendant risks to public safety and wellbeing. We pass
    no judgment on the general wisdom of interdiction. But it cannot be said that identifying
    those at the greatest risk for alcohol abuse and restricting their ability to possess the
    object of that abuse lacks rationality.
    VI.
    It is clear that the Virginia interdiction statute meets with disfavor in the eyes of
    our fine concurring colleague. In her view, the legislature’s enactment of criminal
    sanctions is the wrong “policy decision[],” and the General Assembly would do well to
    consult studies “show[ing] that methods focused on treatment, rather than deterrence, are
    more effective. . . .” Concurring Op. at 36. The concurrence goes to great lengths to
    inform the legislature of the “many methods available to Virginia” in this endeavor. It
    suggests that the state pursue “civil” statutes,    “prioritize treatment and establish a
    program of compulsory treatment” for addicts, offer “public health education,” or simply
    23
    enact “laws to ameliorate the economic and social conditions” surrounding alcohol abuse.
    
    Id.
     Taken together, these suggestions do no less than tell the state how to calibrate
    deterrence and rehabilitation, manage budgetary resources, and structure their local
    economies. As such, it is appropriate that they are directed to the policymakers of the
    state rather than the litigants in this case. We need not dispute our colleague’s ideas, nor
    pass on their merits. What they represent in their totality is a commandeering and
    assumption of the legislative role. This conclusion is justified only by the statement that
    addictions are illnesses. See id. at 33. The Commonwealth does not, however, punish the
    illness. It instead targets what takes place when the illness manifests itself in conduct
    harming or potentially harming other persons.
    A parting recapitulation is in order. As the foregoing indicates, appellants’
    position suffers from multiple infirmities. As an initial matter, the desire to remove
    unspecified acts from the purview of criminal law flies in the face of the distinct and
    emphatic language of the Robinson opinion, which indicates that individual actions, as
    opposed to personal status, remain fair subjects for the legislative contemplation of
    criminal sanctions. Not only are the words of the Supreme Court disregarded, but the
    settled legal landscape that for more than half a century has reinforced their relevance.
    As noted, appellants’ position undermines the basic premise of the criminal law
    that individuals may indeed bear responsibility for their own actions, even as appellants
    overlook the considerable measures that our justice system has taken to soften the
    sanctions and mitigate the hardships of allegedly nonvolitional conduct.
    24
    Thirdly, appellants’ position is a simple affront to our federal system, as it seeks to
    displace with a single constitutional edict the latitude that the 50 states have long been
    given to address persistent social ills associated with drug and alcohol abuse.
    It is not often that a position operates to visit structural and institutional harms
    through the preemption of state and legislative authority, the disregard of higher
    precedent and the erosion of the most basic precepts of the criminal law. Any one of
    these flaws would be serious. Altogether, they are more than severe. The judgment of the
    district court is hereby affirmed.
    AFFIRMED
    25
    DIANA GRIBBON MOTZ, Circuit Judge, concurring in the judgment:
    More than fifty years ago, the Supreme Court held that the Eighth Amendment
    prohibits punishing a person for being addicted to narcotics. Robinson v. California, 
    370 U.S. 660
     (1962). This was so because “narcotics addiction is an illness,” and a state
    cannot punish a person for an illness. 
    Id. at 667
    . The Robinson Court also explained, as
    the government there recognized, that just as a “narcotics addict” is “in a state of mental
    and physical illness,” “[s]o is an alcoholic.” See 
    id.
     at 667 & n.8. In the case at hand,
    homeless alcoholics challenge a statutory scheme that criminalizes their illness — being
    addicted to alcohol. Absent binding circuit precedent, I would hold that they, like the
    defendant in Robinson, have alleged an Eighth Amendment violation.
    I.
    Although a state has the power to punish, the Eighth Amendment mandates that it
    exercise this power “within the limits of civilized standards.” Kennedy v. Louisiana, 
    554 U.S. 407
    , 436 (2008) (quoting Trop v. Dulles, 
    356 U.S. 86
    , 100 (1958) (plurality opinion)
    (internal quotation marks omitted)). Thus, the Eighth Amendment restricts the kinds of
    punishment that can be executed and “imposes substantive limits on what can be made
    criminal.” Ingraham v. Wright, 
    430 U.S. 651
    , 667 (1977) (emphasis added).
    In Robinson, the Court considered a statute making it a misdemeanor “to be
    addicted to the use of narcotics.” 
    370 U.S. at 662
    . Under that statute, the state could
    convict and imprison an addicted person for ninety days even if he had never “used or
    possessed any narcotics within the State.” 
    Id.
     at 666–67. Speaking for the Court, Justice
    26
    Stewart reasoned that “narcotic addiction is an illness,” which, like other illnesses, may
    be contracted “involuntarily,” and so held that “a state law which imprisons a person thus
    afflicted as a criminal” violates the Eighth Amendment. 
    Id. at 667
    .
    Six years later, the Court considered a challenge to a Texas statute that
    criminalized public intoxication. Powell v. Texas, 
    392 U.S. 514
     (1968). The defendant
    argued that this statute, like the statute in Robinson, punished an illness over which he
    had no control and so violated the Eighth Amendment. In a fractured opinion (4 – 1 – 4),
    the Supreme Court rejected that argument.
    In Powell, four Justices interpreted Robinson to prohibit only the criminalization
    of status. In their view, the Texas statute withstood constitutional challenge because it
    criminalized the act of being intoxicated in public rather than the status of alcohol
    addiction. These Justices did not suggest that alcoholism is not an illness. Nor did they
    contend that the Eighth Amendment allowed a state to prosecute an individual merely for
    being an alcoholic. Rather, they concluded that the Texas statute, unlike the law at issue
    in Robinson, did not criminalize “being an addict” or “being a chronic alcoholic.” 
    Id. at 532
     (Marshall, J.) (plurality opinion).
    Four other Justices in Powell concluded that the Texas statute did violate the
    Eighth Amendment. Justice Fortas explained that Robinson compelled this result because
    it stood for a principle at “the foundation of individual liberty and a cornerstone of the
    relations between a civilized state and its citizens.” 
    Id. at 567
    . (Fortas, J., dissenting,
    joined by Justices Douglas, Brennan, and Stewart). Namely, “[c]riminal penalties may
    not be inflicted upon a person for being in a condition he is powerless to change.” 
    Id.
    27
    Because Powell — an alcoholic — “was powerless to avoid drinking” and “once
    intoxicated, he could not prevent himself from appearing in public places,” these Justices
    would have found the challenged statute did violate the Eighth Amendment. 
    Id. at 568
    .
    Justice White provided the decisive fifth vote to uphold Powell’s conviction. In
    doing so, however, he expressly rejected the act-status distinction on which the other four
    Justices who voted to uphold the conviction had relied. See 
    id. at 548
    . As Justice White
    explained, “Unless Robinson is to be abandoned, the use of narcotics by an addict must
    be beyond the reach of the criminal law.         Similarly, the chronic alcoholic with an
    irresistible urge to consume alcohol should not be punishable for drinking or for being
    drunk.” 
    Id.
     at 548–49 (White, J., concurring in the judgment). Justice White agreed with
    the four dissenters that the critical question was not whether the Texas statute punished
    an “act” or a “status,” but rather “whether volitional acts brought about the ‘condition’”
    of public intoxication and “whether those [volitional] acts are sufficiently proximate to
    the ‘condition.’” 
    Id.
     at 550 n.2; see also 
    id.
     (“If it were necessary to distinguish between
    ‘acts’ and ‘conditions’ for purposes of the Eighth Amendment, I would adhere to the
    concept of ‘condition’ implicit in the opinion in Robinson.”).
    Crucially, in reaching this conclusion Justice White specifically contemplated a
    case, like the one at hand, in which an individual is an alcoholic and lacks a home. He
    explained that “chronic alcoholics must drink and hence must drink somewhere,” and
    while many chronic alcoholics “have homes, many others do not.” 
    Id. at 551
    . Thus, if
    individuals could show both that “resisting drunkenness is impossible and that avoiding
    public places when intoxicated is also impossible,” a statute banning public drunkenness
    28
    would be unconstitutional as applied to them.           
    Id.
     (emphasis added).      In those
    circumstances, the statute would, in effect, “ban[] a single act for which [homeless
    alcoholics] may not be convicted under the Eighth Amendment — the act of getting
    drunk.” 
    Id.
     (emphases added).
    Despite this, my colleagues elide the fact that Powell’s ability to “stay off or leave
    the streets” was a decisive factor in Justice White’s concurrence. 
    Id. at 553
    . But the
    closing words of his opinion make clear that these facts mattered:
    For the purposes of this case, it is necessary to say only that Powell showed
    nothing more than that he was to some degree compelled to drink and that
    he was drunk at the time of his arrest. He made no showing that he was
    unable to stay off the streets on the night in question. Because Powell did
    not show that his conviction offended the Constitution, I concur in the
    judgment affirming the Travis County court.
    
    Id.
     at 553–54 (footnote omitted). In other words, it was because Powell did not show
    “that he was unable to stay off the streets” that Justice White concurred in the judgment,
    rather than siding with the dissent. 
    Id.
     at 552–54.
    My colleagues’ assertion that I am creating a “new rule” disregards the Supreme
    Court’s instruction that “[w]hen a fragmented Court decides a case and no single
    rationale explaining the result enjoys the assent of five Justices, the holding of the Court
    may be viewed as that position taken by those Members who concurred in the judgments
    on the narrowest grounds.” Marks v. United States, 
    430 U.S. 188
    , 193 (1977) (citation
    and internal quotation marks omitted); see also Hughes v. United States, __ S. Ct. __
    (2018) (concluding it “unnecessary” to reconsider the reasoning of the Marks rule).
    Justice White’s concurrence clearly rested on “the narrowest grounds” for upholding the
    29
    defendant’s conviction in Powell. Accordingly, it should control our analysis in the case
    at hand.
    The Department of Justice has adopted this interpretation.         See Statement of
    Interest of the United States at 7–12, Bell v. City of Boise, 
    993 F. Supp. 2d 1237
    (D. Idaho 2014) (No. 1:09-cv-00540-REB). And so have some courts. See, e.g., Jones v.
    City of Los Angeles, 
    444 F.3d 1118
    , 1135–36 (9th Cir. 2006), vacated as moot due to a
    settlement, 
    505 F.3d 1006
     (9th Cir. 2007); Pottinger v. City of Miami, 
    810 F. Supp. 1551
    ,
    1561–1565 (S.D. Fla. 1992).
    But some courts have erroneously relied instead on the plurality opinion in Powell
    and, on this basis, upheld laws like the one challenged here. Unfortunately, our court is
    one of those to do so. See Fisher v. Coleman, 
    639 F.2d 191
     (4th Cir. 1981) (per curiam);
    see also Joel v. City of Orlando, 
    232 F.3d 1353
    , 1362 (11th Cir. 2000); United States v.
    Benefield, 
    889 F.2d 1061
     (11th. Cir. 1989). 1 As my colleagues themselves recognize,
    courts that “have relied upon the plurality opinion in Powell . . . have overextended
    themselves in doing so.”
    Justice White’s opinion should have controlled our holding in Fisher, just as it
    should control our analysis here. In Fisher, the district court had upheld Virginia’s
    1
    My colleagues’ suggestion that two other courts of appeals have joined in “a
    large chorus of circuit opinions” supporting their contrary approach rests on two short
    unpublished (and therefore non-precedential) opinions. Neither case involves a challenge
    to the constitutionality of a statute, nor provides any persuasive rationale in support of my
    colleagues’ position. See United States v. Stenson, 475 F. App’x 630 (7th Cir. 2012) (per
    curiam); Joshua v. Adams, 231 F. App’x 592 (9th Cir. 2007).
    30
    statutory scheme, reasoning that Powell “specifically rejected” the contention that
    “conduct symptomatic of alcoholism” was constitutionally protected and that “the case at
    bar falls squarely within the holding of Powell.” Fisher v. Coleman, 
    486 F. Supp. 311
    ,
    316 (W.D. Va. 1979). In a short per curiam opinion, we simply affirmed the district
    court “for reasons sufficiently stated by that court.”     
    639 F.2d at 192
    .       Thus, our
    affirmance relied entirely on the district court’s treatment of the plurality opinion in
    Powell as controlling — totally ignoring Justice White’s narrower approach, which
    Marks teaches is to be regarded as “the holding of the Court.” 430 U.S. at 193.
    II.
    Applying the narrower approach set forth by Justice White compels the conclusion
    that Plaintiffs have alleged an Eighth Amendment violation. Plaintiffs allege that they
    are homeless and suffer from an illness: alcoholism. They assert that, after Virginia
    labeled them “habitual drunkards” and interdicted them, the state criminally charged and
    then repeatedly prosecuted them for actions compelled by their status as homeless
    alcoholics.
    Plaintiffs allege that Virginia interdicted them — often in absentia — upon
    deeming them “habitual drunkards,” a vague statutory term that has historically served as
    a euphemism for the homeless. See Jayesh M. Rathod, Distilling Americans: The Legacy
    of Prohibition on U.S. Immigration Law, 
    51 Hous. L. Rev. 781
    , 792 (2014); see e.g.,
    Colin L. Anderson, Median Bans, Anti-Homeless Laws, and the Urban Growth Machine,
    8 DePaul J. for Soc. Just. 405, 412–18 (2015). Plaintiffs claim that, once interdicted, the
    31
    Commonwealth arrested and criminally prosecuted them — not once or twice, but dozens
    of times — for otherwise legal behavior.
    For example, they allege that police officers arrested Plaintiff Bryan Manning on
    one occasion “for smelling like alcohol” and on another for being “in a Walmart store
    where alcohol was sold.” They assert that officers arrested Plaintiff Ryan Williams for
    “sleeping in a park bathroom” where “a beer can was found in the trash,” and arrested
    Plaintiffs Richard Deckerhoff and Richard Eugene Walls for being “near” beer cans.
    Finally, Plaintiffs allege that the Commonwealth provides no clear procedure for
    removing the “habitual drunkard” label post-interdiction, such that interdicted persons are
    essentially branded for life. On the basis of these facts, Plaintiffs maintain that, as
    applied to them, Virginia’s statutory scheme violates the Eighth Amendment by
    subjecting them to incarceration because of their status as “homeless alcoholics.”
    In arguing to the contrary, the Commonwealth heavily relies on the fact that the
    Virginia statute operates in two steps. Va. Code § 4.1-333(A) permits a court to enter a
    civil interdiction order “prohibiting the sale of alcoholic beverages . . . until further
    ordered” to a person who “has shown himself to be an habitual drunkard.” Then Va.
    Code §§ 4.1-322 and 4.1-305 make it a Class 1 misdemeanor for an interdicted person to
    “possess any alcoholic beverages” or to “consume, purchase or possess, or attempt to
    consume, purchase or possess, any alcoholic beverage.” The punishment for this crime is
    “confinement in jail for not more than twelve months and a fine of not more than $2,500,
    either or both.” Va. Code § 18.2-11(a).
    32
    Virginia’s two-pronged statutory scheme may be more indirect than the statute at
    issue in Robinson, but it yields the same result. If the statute at issue in Robinson had
    allowed the state to “interdict” prescription drug addicts and then arrest interdicted
    addicts for filling those prescriptions, the statute effectively would also have criminalized
    “being addicted to narcotics” even if it nominally punished only filling prescriptions.
    Such a statute would surely be unconstitutional as well.
    A statute that would be unconstitutional if accomplished in one step cannot be
    rendered constitutional simply by bifurcating it. Thus, although Virginia may nominally
    penalize “possession” or “consumption,” the Commonwealth’s statutory scheme
    effectively targets and punishes homeless alcoholics based on their illness. That the
    Commonwealth brands homeless alcoholics as “habitual drunkards” before prosecuting
    them for involuntary manifestations of their illness does nothing to cure the
    unconstitutionality of the statutory scheme.
    III.
    Moreover, contrary to my colleagues’ suggestions, adopting Plaintiffs’ position
    would not shield individuals from prosecution for violating generally applicable laws,
    curtail a state’s ability to impose post-conviction restrictions, or infringe on a state’s
    ability to regulate alcohol. My colleagues warn against “accept[ing] casually every
    ‘slippery slope’ or ‘open-the-floodgates’ argument that comes along.” But in the same
    breath, they fall into this very trap. Plaintiffs challenge only the targeted criminalization
    of otherwise legal behavior that is an involuntary manifestation of their illness. Plaintiffs
    33
    do not assert that they are immune from prosecution for generally applicable criminal
    offenses.   They do not question the constitutionality of restrictions imposed after a
    criminal conviction. And they raise no objection to the Commonwealth’s general ability
    to regulate alcohol or other substances within its borders.
    The contention that Plaintiffs’ position leads to holding that any “uncontrollable”
    act absolves an individual of responsibility for generally applicable crimes is clearly
    incorrect. 2 A state undoubtedly has the power to prosecute individuals — even those
    suffering from an illness — for breaking laws that apply to the general population. Under
    the Eighth Amendment, an alcoholic may not, as a result of his addiction, escape
    prosecution for criminal behavior that is unlawful if committed by a non-alcoholic. But
    Plaintiffs do not seek a special exemption from generally applicable criminal laws. The
    constitutional challenge we confront today deals only with a law that targets a group of
    vulnerable, sick people for special punishment based on otherwise legal behavior
    (drinking alcohol) that is an involuntary manifestation of their illness.
    Accordingly, Plaintiffs’ position does not jeopardize laws generally criminalizing
    certain behavior. Those laws apply to all and reflect a state’s legitimate concern that
    2
    Any suggestion to the contrary is a straw man. Five Supreme Court Justices
    have rejected this very argument. See Powell, 
    392 U.S. at
    552 n.4 (White, J., concurring
    in the judgment) (“A holding that a person establishing the requisite facts could not,
    because of the Eighth Amendment, be criminally punished for appearing in public while
    drunk would . . . hardly have radical consequences.”); 
    id.
     at 59 n.2 (Fortas, J., dissenting,
    joined by Justices Douglas, Brennan, and Stewart) (“It is not foreseeable that findings
    such as those which are decisive here . . . would be made in the case of offenses such as
    driving a car while intoxicated, assault, theft, or robbery.”).
    34
    some actions are so dangerous or contrary to the public welfare that they should lead to
    criminal liability for everyone who commits them. That is not the case here. Generally,
    Virginians over the age of 21 can possess and consume alcohol, but if the state brands a
    person a “habitual drunkard” and interdicts him, behavior that is legal for all others over
    21 becomes criminal for the interdicted person. See Benno Weisberg, When Punishing
    Innocent Conduct Violates the Eighth Amendment: Applying the Robinson Doctrine to
    Homelessness and Other Contextual “Crimes,” 
    96 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 362
     (2005)
    (arguing that there is an important distinction for Eighth Amendment purposes between
    “laws that criminalize specific conduct” in all spatial and temporal contexts — such as
    theft, homicide, rape, assault, and buying or possessing drugs — and “laws that
    criminalize conduct only when performed in certain contexts”).
    Nor, contrary to my colleagues’ suggestion, does Plaintiffs’ position undermine a
    state’s use of prophylactic measures to thwart “serious criminal misconduct.” States
    certainly have a legitimate interest in using such measures to prevent and deter criminal
    offenders. But Plaintiffs’ challenge simply does not impact enhanced punishments or
    post-conviction restrictions imposed because of a prior criminal conviction. Those laws
    do empower courts, in some instances, to impose such punishments and restrictions on
    those who suffer from certain illnesses, but only where a defendant has already been
    convicted of a crime — a conviction imposed subject to due process and other
    constitutional safeguards.   See, e.g., 
    34 U.S.C. § 20913
     (establishing sex offender
    registry); 
    id.
     § 20911(1) (defining “sex offender” as “an individual who was convicted of
    a sex offense”).
    35
    Finally, holding Virginia’s statutory scheme unconstitutional would not affect
    “[t]he broad power of a State to regulate” alcohol or narcotics within its borders. See
    Robinson, 
    370 U.S. at 664
    . There are many methods available to Virginia to pursue these
    goals. The Commonwealth can enact civil, and generally applicable criminal statutes
    addressing alcohol and narcotics abuse. See 
    id. at 664
    . It can elect to prioritize treatment
    and “establish a program of compulsory treatment for those addicted to” alcohol. See 
    id.
    at 664–65. And it can “choose to attack” the combined “evils” of alcoholism and
    homelessness “through public health education,” or by enacting laws designed to
    “ameliorate the economic and social conditions under which those evils might be thought
    to flourish.” See 
    id. at 665
    .
    Policy decisions such as these are, of course, not ours to make; they rest within the
    sound province of the Virginia General Assembly. I note, however, that just as society’s
    understanding of alcoholism and addiction have evolved in the 56 years since Robinson,
    so too have methods of targeting these problems. Indeed, studies have repeatedly — and
    convincingly — shown that methods focused on treatment, rather than deterrence, are
    more effective at targeting the combined problems of alcoholism and homelessness. See,
    e.g., U.S. Interagency Council on Homelessness, Searching out Solutions: Constructive
    Alternatives to the Criminalization of Homelessness (June 2012). 3
    3
    Only Virginia and Utah continue to use criminal sanctions such as this. See Utah
    Code §§ 32B-4-413, 32B-4-304. That only two states still impose criminal penalties on
    alcoholics using interdiction schemes — schemes originating in the late 19th century, see,
    e.g., Va. Code. Ch. 83 § 5 (1873) — suggests yet another reason why such a scheme is
    unconstitutional. See Trop, 
    356 U.S. at
    100–01 (plurality opinion) (explaining that
    (Continued)
    36
    In   response   to   this   concurrence,   my   colleagues    offer   rhetoric   and
    misapprehensions. I will not attempt to match the rhetoric, but must correct a few of the
    misapprehensions. Faithfully following Justice White’s controlling opinion in Powell, as
    I would, does not “overturn or greatly extend” Supreme Court precedent. Rather, only
    this course properly follows the Court’s longstanding Marks rule. And the accusation
    that I have gone “to great lengths to inform the legislature” that it has made “the wrong
    ‘policy decision[]’” ignores the preceding paragraphs. In fact, I expressly recognize that
    policy decisions are the legislature’s province — provided those decisions do not violate
    the Constitution. Finally, of course a state may target conduct “harming or potentially
    harming other persons,” but the statute at issue here contains no such limitations. Indeed,
    the complaint alleges that the Commonwealth routinely uses this statute to arrest
    homeless alcoholics simply because of their presence in a Walmart or near a discarded
    beer can. (Given these allegations, Plaintiffs may also have a claim under the Fourth
    Amendment, as my colleagues suggest; of course, a plaintiff need not pursue every
    available claim.)
    Thus, although my colleagues’ opinion makes for dramatic reading, their analysis
    remains divorced from the law and the facts of this case. Plaintiffs’ challenge is a narrow
    one that will neither hinder nor even implicate a state’s ability to make legislative
    judgments concerning the safety and welfare of its citizens.
    because “the words of the [Eighth] Amendment are not precise” and “their scope is not
    static,” the Supreme Court has recognized that “[t]he Amendment must draw its meaning
    from the evolving standards of decency that mark the progress of a maturing society”).
    37
    IV.
    The statutory scheme challenged here criminalizes the otherwise legal behavior of
    individuals suffering from a serious illness. The specter of this unconstitutional law
    looms large over a number of the Commonwealth’s most vulnerable citizens. Plaintiffs
    allege that from 2007 to 2015, Virginia interdicted 1,220 individuals and recorded 4,743
    criminal convictions of interdicted persons for alcohol possession or consumption.
    Imprisonment for a short time — here, for not more than twelve months — does
    not, in the abstract, seem to be cruel or unusual punishment. But, as the Robinson Court
    recognized, “[e]ven one day in prison would be cruel and unusual punishment for the
    ‘crime’ of having a common cold.” 
    370 U.S. at 667
    . The targeted criminalization of
    otherwise legal behavior that is an involuntary manifestation of an illness is just as clearly
    cruel and unusual punishment here as it was in Robinson.
    Given our precedent, 4 I must concur in the judgment rejecting the challenge to
    Virginia’s statutory scheme. Because thousands of Virginians remain subject to a law
    that, in my view, is unconstitutional, I do so with reluctance and regret.
    4
    Plaintiffs recognize that Fisher constitutes circuit precedent, but suggest that we
    “take the opportunity to reconsider” Fisher. Appellants’ Br. at 37. This panel cannot do
    so. In the absence of an intervening change in the law, “[o]nly the full court, sitting en
    banc,” can do so. Demetres v. E. W. Const., Inc., 
    776 F.3d 271
    , 275 (4th Cir. 2015).
    38
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 17-1320

Citation Numbers: 900 F.3d 139

Filed Date: 8/9/2018

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 1/12/2023

Authorities (28)

James S. Joel v. City of Orlando , 232 F.3d 1353 ( 2000 )

United States v. Lorenza Benefield, Sr. , 889 F.2d 1061 ( 1989 )

Leonard W. Ferguson v. John S. Gathright, Superintendent ... , 485 F.2d 504 ( 1973 )

Terry M. Mitchell v. Commissioner of the Social Security ... , 182 F.3d 272 ( 1999 )

Charles P. Fisher v. J. Marshall Coleman and Richard H. ... , 639 F.2d 191 ( 1981 )

E.I. Du Pont De Nemours & Co. v. Kolon Industries, Inc. , 637 F.3d 435 ( 2011 )

Collins v. Hall , 991 F. Supp. 1065 ( 1997 )

Powell v. Texas , 88 S. Ct. 2145 ( 1968 )

edward-jones-patricia-vinson-george-vinson-thomas-cash-stanley-barger , 444 F.3d 1118 ( 2006 )

United States v. Raymond Moore , 486 F.2d 1139 ( 1973 )

tami-charles-plumer-v-state-of-maryland-motor-vehicle-administration-of , 915 F.2d 927 ( 1990 )

star-scientific-incorporated-a-delaware-corporation-v-randolph-a , 278 F.3d 339 ( 2002 )

Pottinger v. City of Miami , 810 F. Supp. 1551 ( 1992 )

Lehr v. City of Sacramento , 624 F. Supp. 2d 1218 ( 2009 )

Marks v. United States , 97 S. Ct. 990 ( 1977 )

Trop v. Dulles , 78 S. Ct. 590 ( 1958 )

Lassiter v. Department of Social Servs. of Durham Cty. , 101 S. Ct. 2153 ( 1981 )

Robinson v. California , 82 S. Ct. 1417 ( 1962 )

Paul v. Davis , 96 S. Ct. 1155 ( 1976 )

Washington v. Glucksberg , 117 S. Ct. 2258 ( 1997 )

View All Authorities »