Causeway Medical Suite v. Ieyoub , 109 F.3d 1096 ( 1997 )


Menu:
  •                                   United States Court of Appeals,
    Fifth Circuit.
    No. 95-31178.
    CAUSEWAY MEDICAL SUITE; Hope Medical Group for Women, on behalf of themselves
    and the patients they serve, Plaintiffs- Appellees,
    v.
    Richard P. IEYOUB, Attorney General of the State of Louisiana, Michael J. Foster, Jr.,
    Governor, State of Louisiana, Bobby P. Jindal, Secretary of the Louisiana Department of Health and
    Hospitals, and Madlyn B. Bagneris, Secretary of the Louisiana Department of Social Services,
    Defendants-Appellants.
    April 14, 1997.
    Appeal from the United States District Court for the Eastern District of Louisiana.
    Before POLITZ, Chief Judge, and EMILIO M. GARZA and STEWART, Circuit Judges.
    STEWART, Circuit Judge:
    We must decide whether certain provisions of Act 1254 (codified at La. R.S. 40:1299.35.5
    (West Supp.1996)), which changed Louisiana's judicial bypass procedure for minors seeking
    abortions, comports with the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. We hold that it
    does not and affirm the district court's summary judgment which permanently enjoined La. R.S.
    40:1299.35.5(B).
    LEGISLATIVE BACKGROUND
    In Louisiana, minors under the age of eighteen must obtain the consent of at least one parent
    or legal guardian before a physician has the legal authority to perform an abortion. La. R.S.
    40:1299.35.5(A) (West 1992). However, a physician may perform the abortion without the consent
    of a parent or legal guardian if t he minor exercises her rights under a judicial bypass procedure
    prescribed in La. R.S. 40:1299.35.5(B). Section 1299.35.5(B) has, since 1978, undergone changes.
    Because this appeal largely turns on the 1995 changes to § 1299.35.5(B), we bel ieve that a brief
    review of the legislative history of § 1299.35.5(B) sheds valuable light on the issues before us.
    A. The 1978 Version of La. R.S. 40:1299.35.5(B)
    We begin in 1978, when the Louisiana Legislature enacted La. R.S. 40:1299.35.5 (the 1978
    Act), which, among other things, regulated the circumstances under which minors could obtain
    abortions. Notably, the 1978 Act, while providing for a judicial bypass, gave little (if any) guidance
    to courts faced with minors seeking abortions. Subsection (A) of the 1978 Act, titled "Notice and
    consent," provided that the parents or legal guardian of a minor under eighteen must receive actual
    notice twenty-four hours before the minor had an abortion or, if the parent or legal guardian could
    not be reached, that parent or legal guardian must receive constructive notice seventy-two hours
    before the abortion. The sole exception to these parental notification requirements was a bare-bones
    judicial bypass provision, which stated simply "unless the abortion is ordered by a court having
    jurisdiction over such minor pregnant woman." Subsection (B) provided that if the minor was under
    the age of fifteen, she must obtain informed, written consent from a parent or legal guardian or
    "obtain[ ] an order from a court having jurisdiction over her that the abortion be performed or
    induced." Neither subsection (A) nor (B) provided any criteria that must be met before a judge could,
    without any notice to the parent(s) or legal guardian(s), order a minor to have an abortion.
    Then, in 1979, the Supreme Court handed down Bellotti v. Baird, 
    443 U.S. 622
    , 
    99 S.Ct. 3035
    , 
    61 L.Ed.2d 797
     (1979) (Bellotti II ), in which a plurality of the Court set forth the standards
    that should govern the judicial bypass procedure for minors seeking abortions. Recognizing the
    parent-child tension that may accompany a minor's wish to have an abortion, the Court held that a
    minor may seek an order from a court, without the consent or notification of a parent or legal
    guardian, that authorizes the procedure. 
    Id. at 646-48
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at 3049-51
    . In particular, the Court
    held:
    If she satisfies the court that she is mature and well enough informed to make intelligently the
    abortion decision on her own, the court must authorize her to act without parental
    consultation or consent. If she fails to satisfy the court that she is competent to make this
    decision independently, she must be permitted to show that an abortion nevertheless would
    be in her best interests. If the court is persuaded that it is, the court must authorize the
    abortion.
    
    Id. at 647-48
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at 3050
     (emphasis added). Approximately eight months after Bellotti II was
    decided, Louisiana's skeletal judicial bypass provision was struck down as inconsistent with Bellotti
    II. In Margaret S. v. Edwards, 
    488 F.Supp. 181
    , 203 (E.D.La.1980) (Margaret S.(I) ), the district
    court held: "This section [§ 1299.35.5(B) ] says nothing more than the pregnant minor may receive
    an order from a "court having jurisdiction over her that the abortion be performed or induced.' This
    is not enough.... La.Rev.Stat.Ann. § 40:1299.35.5(B) sets forth no standards or guidelines for the
    minor seeking judicial approval for abortion."
    B. The 1980 and 1981 Versions of La. R.S. 40:1299.35.5(B)
    In 1980, the Louisiana Legislature responded to Margaret S.(I) and, among other things,
    changed La. R.S. 40:1299.35.5(B) to comply with Bellotti II. Most importantly for purposes of this
    appeal, the new statute contained the mandatory language from the Bellotti II decision. La. R.S.
    40:1299.35.5(B) provided in part: "The court shall authorize the abortion only if the court finds that
    the woman is sufficiently mature and well-informed to make an intelligent decision on her own
    concerning the abortion, or, if the court finds that regardless of the capacity of the woman to make
    the decision, the abortion would be in her best interest." (Emphasis added). The 1980 version also
    included an expediency clause: "Such applications shall be heard summarily and expeditiously and
    shall take precedence over matters on the docket of the court." (Emphasis added).
    In 1981, Louisiana modified its abortion statute, beginning with a general statement of
    legislative intent. Section 1299.35.0 (West 1992) provided in part: "It is the intention of the
    Legislature of the State of Louisiana to regulate abortion to the extent permitted by decisions of the
    United States Supreme Court." In 1981, the legislature also refined and expanded § 1299.35.5(B),
    and the pertinent sections read as follows:
    (3) Each application shall be heard in chambers, confidentially, in a summary manner, and
    within forty-eight hours of the filing thereof.
    (4) If the court finds that the minor is sufficiently mature and well enough informed to make
    the decision concerning the abortion on her own, the court shall issue an order authorizing
    the minor to act on the matter without parental consultation or consent.
    (5) If the court finds that the minor is not competent to make the decision concerning the
    abortion on her own, but finds that the abortion nevertheless would be in the best interest of
    the minor, the court shall issue an order authorizing the abortion.
    (Emphasis added). Subsections (4) and (5) parsed out the "maturity and well-informed" provision
    and the "best-interests-of-the-minor" inquiry. As with the 1980 version, the 1981 version of §
    1299.35.5(B) retained the mandatory "shall" language. However, the word "expeditiously" was
    removed and a forty-eight hour time frame for hearing a minor's application was imposed. With these
    new changes in place, § 1299.35.5(B) survived a constitutional attack the next time around. See
    Margaret S. v. Treen, 
    597 F.Supp. 636
    , 650-52 (E.D.La.1984) (Margaret S. (II) ), aff'd on other
    grounds sub nom. Margaret S. v. Edwards, 
    794 F.2d 994
     (5th Cir.1986).1
    C. Act 1254—The 1995 Version of La. R.S. 40:1299.35.5(B)
    And so it was for fourteen years. In 1995, however, the Louisiana Legislature went back to
    the drawing board with Act 1254, which expanded and changed § 1299.35.5(B) to read in part:
    (3) Each application shall be heard in chambers, anonymously, in a summary manner, and
    within forty-eight hours of the filing thereof.
    (4) If the court finds, by clear and convincing evidence, that the minor is sufficiently mature
    and well enough informed to make the decision concerning the abortion on her own, the court
    may issue an order authorizing the minor to act on the matter. Prior to any such order, the
    court may require the minor to participate in an evaluation and counseling session with a
    mental health professional from the Department of Health and Hospitals, office of mental
    health, and a staff member from the Department of Social Services, office of community
    services. The court may refer the petitioner, if necessary, to the appropriate Department of
    Health and Hospitals, office of mental health regional office to arrange the evaluation and
    counseling session within forty-eight hours of the ex parte hearing, excluding legal holidays.
    (5) If the court finds that the minor is not sufficiently mature and well enough informed to
    make a decision intelligently among the alternatives, the court shall decide whether or not it
    would be in the best interest of the minor to notify her parents or guardian of the proceedings.
    If the court finds that it is in the minor's best interest to notify her parents or guardian, the
    court shall so notify and reconvene the proceedings within forty-eight hours with the parents
    or guardian present to advise and counsel the minor and aid the court in making its
    determination whether or not the abortion would be in the best interest of the minor.
    (6) If the court finds that the minor is not competent to make the decision concerning the
    abortion or that it would not be in the minor's best interest to notify her parents or guardian,
    the court may issue an order authorizing the abo rtion if the court finds, by clear and
    convincing evidence, that the abortion would be in the best interest of the minor.
    (Emphasis added). Three changes to Louisiana's bypass procedure are relevant for purposes of this
    appeal:2 (1) in subsections (4) and (6) (which correspond to subsections (4) and (5), respectively,
    1
    The district court in Margaret S. (II) stated that the 1981 judicial bypass procedure provided
    for an "expeditious hearing of the matter...." 597 F.Supp. at 652. As we have noted, however,
    the word "expeditious[ ]" was removed from the 1981 statute. The district court did not consider
    the meaning of "summary manner" as defined under Louisiana law to determine whether the new
    subsection (3) met the Bellotti II expedition requirement.
    2
    Although the plaintiffs challenged and the district court enjoined the expediency provision in
    subsection (3), that subpart largely remained unchanged in Act 1254. The legislature only
    changed "confidentially" to "anonymously." This particular change has not been challenged by the
    plaintiffs.
    in the 1981 statute), "shall" has been changed to "may," so that if the juvenile court finds that a minor
    is mature and well-informed or that an abortion would be in the minor's best interest, the court now
    "may" order an abortion; (2) subsection (4) permits judges to refer a minor to a state-sponsored
    counseling and evaluation session within forty-eight hours of the ex parte hearing; and (3) subsection
    (5) states that a juvenile court judge is compelled to notify the parents or guardian of an immature
    minor if doing so is in the best interest of the minor.
    PROCEDURAL HISTORY
    On July 6, 1995, Causeway Medical Suite and Hope Medical Group for Women (plaintiffs)
    filed suit challenging the constitutionality of Act 1254. The plaintiffs sought injunctive relief, claiming
    that Act 1254 violated the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment because Act 1254 (1)
    provided juvenile court judges discretion to deny a minor an abortion even though the minor
    demonstrated that she was mature and well-informed or that the abortion would be in her best
    interest; (2) failed to establish a time limit for an expeditious resolution of the minor's bypass
    application; (3) allowed the juvenile court to refer minors to state-sponsored evaluation and
    counseling without providing any time frame within which counselors are to report back to the court,
    thereby depriving minors of an effective opportunity to obtain an abortion and preventing the minor
    from remaining anonymous; and (4) breached the minor's confidentiality by permitting the juvenile
    court to notify the minor's parent that she is seeking an abortion if the court finds such notification
    would be in the minor's best interest.
    With one exception,3 the district court agreed with the plaintiffs on each of these points. 
    905 F.Supp. 360
    , 364-66 (E.D.La.1995). Acco rdingly, the district court entered summary judgment,
    permanently enjoining Act 1254 because it "constitute[d] an undue burden on the right of minors to
    have access to abortion services by way of a judicial bypass of the parental consent requirement and
    thus violates the Due Process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment." 
    Id. at 366
    . This appeal
    3
    The district court did not rule on the plaintiff's claim that the state-sponsored counseling
    provision impermissibly breached anonymity. On appeal, the plaintiffs resurrect this argument.
    We decline to address this claim, however, because it is unnecessary to the disposition of this
    case. The counseling and evaluation provision is facially unconstitutional for another reason
    discussed in Part IV.A.2, infra.
    followed.
    DISCUSSION
    The State makes three claims on appeal. First, it claims that the plaintiffs do not have standing
    to bring this lawsuit because there is no "case or controversy ." Second, the State argues that the
    proper standard of proof for facial challenges requires plaintiffs to demonstrate that Act 1254, under
    no set of circumstances, is constitutional. Third, and central to this appeal, the State contends that
    each of the challenged provisions is facially constitutional. We reject each of these contentions.
    I. STANDARD OF REVIEW
    We review the district court's decision to permanently enjoin Act 1254 for an abuse of
    discretion. North Alamo Water Supply Corp. v. City of San Juan, 
    90 F.3d 910
    , 916 (5th Cir.1996).
    "The district court abuses it s discretion if it (1) relies on clearly erroneous factual findings when
    deciding to grant or deny the permanent injunction, (2) relies on erroneous conclusions of law when
    deciding to grant or deny the permanent injunction, or (3) misapplies the factual or legal conclusions
    when fashioning its injunctive relief." 
    Id. at 916-17
    . " "The standard of review over the district
    court's grant of a permanent injunction must, of course, be segmented according to the component
    functions performed by the district court.' " Peaches Entertainment Corp. v. Entertainment
    Repertoire Assocs., Inc., 
    62 F.3d 690
    , 693 (5th Cir.1995) (quoting Multnomah Legal Serv. Workers
    Union v. Legal Serv. Corp., 
    936 F.2d 1547
    , 1552 (9th Cir.1991)).
    This case comes to us from a grant of summary judgment in favor of the plaintiffs. We review
    de novo the district court's entry of summary judgment. TLI, Inc. v. United States, 
    100 F.3d 424
    , 425
    (5th Cir.1996).
    II. JURISDICTION AND STANDING
    The State suggests that there is no "case or controversy" because the state officials named
    in this lawsuit do not have "the power to enforce private-action court procedures." As such, the State
    concludes, the injunction in this case is "hypothetical and meaningless." We reject these claims. The
    plaintiffs in this case have standing to assert the claims of those minors who seek abortions by way
    of a judicial bypass. See Planned Parenthood of Southeastern, Pa. v. Casey, 
    505 U.S. 833
    , 842-45,
    
    112 S.Ct. 2791
    , 2803, 
    120 L.Ed.2d 674
     (1992). And the district court had jurisdiction pursuant to
    
    28 U.S.C. § 1343
     because the plaintiffs seek redress for a deprivation of a constitutional right under
    color of state law.
    III. THE STANDARD OF PROOF FOR FACIAL CHALLENGES TO ABORTION STATUTES
    The plaintiffs in this case have brought a facial challenge, claiming that Act 1254 on its face
    violates the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. The Supreme Court has articulated
    two approaches to proving a statute is facially unconstitutional. In United States v. Salerno, 
    481 U.S. 739
    , 
    107 S.Ct. 2095
    , 
    95 L.Ed.2d 697
     (1987), the Court held that in a facial challenge, "the challenger
    must establish that no set of circumstances exists under which the Act would be valid." 
    Id. at 745
    ,
    
    107 S.Ct. at 2100
     (emphasis added). However, in Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey,
    
    505 U.S. 833
    , 
    112 S.Ct. 2791
    , 
    120 L.Ed.2d 674
     (1992), the Court appeared to temper the Salerno
    standard by suggesting that an abortion law is facially invalid if "in a large fraction of the cases in
    which [the law] is relevant, it will operate as a substantial obstacle to a woman's choice to undergo
    an abortion." 
    Id. at 895
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2830
     (emphasis added). Plainly, more statutes will survive a
    facial attack under Salerno than under Casey.
    Shortly after Casey was decided, we held in Barnes v. Moore, 
    970 F.2d 12
    , 14 n. 2 (5th Cir.),
    cert. denied, 
    506 U.S. 1021
    , 
    113 S.Ct. 656
    , 
    121 L.Ed.2d 582
     (1992), that Casey did not overrule
    Salerno. Since our decision in Barnes, however, no clear consensus among federal courts has
    emerged regarding the standard for facial challenges in a post-Casey world. Six Justices from the
    Supreme Court have expressed their views on this issue, but not in cases receiving a full hearing by
    the Court. Justices O'Connor, Souter, and Stevens have made it clear that the Casey standard
    controls in the abortion context. See Janklow v. Planned Parenthood, Sioux Falls Clinic, --- U.S.
    ----, ----, 
    116 S.Ct. 1582
    , 1583, 
    134 L.Ed.2d 679
     (1996) (Stevens, J., mem. respecting denial of
    certiorari) ("While a facial challenge may be more difficult to mount than an as-applied challenge, the
    dicta in Salerno "does not accurately characterize the standard for deciding facial challenges,' and
    "neither accurately reflects the Court's practice with respect to facial challenges, nor is it consistent
    with a wide array of legal principles.' ")(quoting Michael C. Dorf, Facial Challenges to State and
    Federal Statutes, 46 STAN. L. REV. 235, 236, 238 (1994)); Fargo Women's Health Organization
    v. Schafer, 
    507 U.S. 1013
    , 1014, 
    113 S.Ct. 1668
    , 1669, 
    123 L.Ed.2d 285
     (1993) (O'Connor, J.,
    joined by Souter, J., conc. in denial of stay pending appeal) (stating that lower courts' application of
    Salerno standard "is inconsistent with Casey "). On the other hand, Chief Justice Rehnquist and
    Justices Scalia and Thomas have stated that the Salerno standard applies in the abortion context. See
    Janklow, --- U.S. at ---- - ----, 116 S.Ct. at 1584-87 (Scalia, J., joined by Rehnquist, C.J. & Thomas,
    J., dissenting from denial of certiorari). There is also considerable disagreement among the lower
    federal courts on this issue.4 See generally Ruth Burdick, Note, The Casey Undue Burden Standard:
    Problems Predicted and Encountered, and the Split Over the Salerno Test, 23 HASTINGS CONST.
    L.Q. 825 (1996) (arguing that lower federal courts are likely to remain split over the Salerno-Casey
    choice).
    The district court avoided this thicket of disagreement, reasoning that under either approach,
    Act 1254 was unconstitutional. 
    905 F.Supp. at
    363 n. 2. As such, the district court applied the more
    rigorous Salerno standard. 
    Id. at 363
    . In this appeal, both parties urge us to confront head-on the
    question of the standard of proof that should govern facial challenges in abortion cases. Specifically,
    the plaintiffs claim that the statements made by Justices O'Connor and Souter in Fargo Women's
    Health Organization v. Schafer, 507 U.S. at 1014, 113 S.Ct. at 1669, and by Justice Stevens in
    Janklow call into doubt our prior holding in Barnes. On the other hand, the State asks us to follow
    our previous decision in Barnes because the Supreme Court has not conclusively resolved the
    confusion in this area.
    We are free to reconsider the correctness of a panel opinion, short of the full court sitting en
    banc, if the Supreme Court has handed down an intervening decision that implicitly or explicitly
    overrules one of our prior decisions. See Federal Deposit Ins. Corp. v. Dawson, 
    4 F.3d 1303
    , 1307
    4
    Compare Compassion in Dying v. Washington, 
    79 F.3d 790
    , 798 n. 9 (9th Cir.1996) (en
    banc) (holding that Casey displaced Salerno ), cert. granted sub nom. Washington v. Glucksberg,
    --- U.S. ----, 
    117 S.Ct. 37
    , 
    135 L.Ed.2d 1128
     (1996) and Planned Parenthood, Sioux Falls
    Clinic v. Miller, 
    63 F.3d 1452
    , 1456-58 (8th Cir.1995), cert. denied sub nom. Janklow v.
    Planned Parenthood, Sioux Falls Clinic, --- U.S. ----, 
    116 S.Ct. 1582
    , 
    134 L.Ed.2d 679
     (1996)
    (same) and Casey v. Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa., 
    14 F.3d 848
    , 863 n. 21 (3d
    Cir.1994) (on remand) (same) with Barnes v. Moore, 970 F.2d at 14 n. 2.
    (5th Cir.1993), cert. denied, 
    512 U.S. 1205
    , 
    114 S.Ct. 2673
    , 
    129 L.Ed.2d 809
     (1994); Campbell
    v. Sonat Offshore Drilling, Inc., 
    979 F.2d 1115
    , 1121 n. 8 (5th Cir.1992). However, we have not
    held that intermittent statements accompanying denials of certiorari or denials of stays pending appeal
    amount to an intervening change in the law. The Supreme Court it self has said that "all opinions
    dissenting from the denial of certiorari" are "totally unnecessary" and "examples of the purest form
    of dicta." Singleton v. Commissioner, 
    439 U.S. 940
    , 944-45, 
    99 S.Ct. 335
    , 338, 
    58 L.Ed.2d 335
    (1978) (Stevens, J., respecting the denial of certiorari). Accordingly, for a panel of this court to
    overrule a prior decision, we have required a Supreme Court decision that has been fully heard by the
    Court and establishes a rule of law inconsistent with our own. See United States v. Kirk, 
    528 F.2d 1057
    , 1063-64 (5th Cir.1976) (holding that two-member concurrence was insufficient as an indicator
    that the Court "expressly or implicitly" overruled one of our prior decisions). The wisdom of this
    policy is illustrated here. As far as we can tell, the Court appears to be divided 3-3 on the Salerno-
    Casey debate, and it would be ill-advised for us to assume that the Court will abandon Salerno
    because three members of the Court now desire that result.5
    More to the point, even assuming the statements in Fargo and Janklow amount to an
    intervening change in the law such that we may decline to follow Barnes, we nevertheless stay our
    hand on this contentious issue because its resolution is not necessary to the disposition of this case,
    for whether viewed under Casey or Salerno, Act 1254 is unconstitutional on its face.6 Thus, like the
    district court, we apply the more rigorous Salerno standard to Act 1254.
    IV. THE CONSTITUTIONALITY OF ACT 1254
    We now turn to the heart of this appeal—whether Act 1254 comports with the Due Process
    5
    The Eighth Circuit boldly declared that the Supreme Court in Casey has "effectively overruled
    Salerno for facial challenges to abortion statutes." Miller, 
    63 F.3d at 1458
    . As we have said, we
    decline to speculate about the outcome of this disagreement between the Justices of the Supreme
    Court.
    6
    We also respectfully decline, for the reasons stated above, Justice Stevens's invitation to
    reconsider the wisdom of our decision in Barnes. See Janklow, --- U.S. at ---- n. 2, 116 S.Ct. at
    1583 n. 2 (Stevens, J., mem. respecting the denial of certiorari) ("[I]t is not at all clear to me,
    given intervening statements by Members of this Court, [citation], that subsequent Fifth Circuit
    panels would follow Barnes ' application of the "no circumstance' test....").
    Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. We begin with a brief summary of the principles that have
    shaped this area and guide our decision today.
    After the Supreme Court declared in Roe v. Wade, 
    410 U.S. 113
    , 
    93 S.Ct. 705
    , 
    35 L.Ed.2d 147
     (1973) that women have a constitutional right to an abortion, the issue of where minors fit into
    the constitutional picture was soon addressed by the Court. Thus, in Planned Parenthood of Central
    Missouri v. Danforth, 
    428 U.S. 52
    , 
    96 S.Ct. 2831
    , 
    49 L.Ed.2d 788
     (1976), the Court held that a
    parental or legal guardian veto of a minor's choice to have an abortion was unconstitutional. 
    Id. at 74-75
    , 
    96 S.Ct. at 2843-44
    . "Constitutional rights," reasoned the Danforth Court, "do not mature
    and come into being magically only when one attains the state-defined age of majority. Minors, as
    well as adults, are protected by the Constitution and possess constitutional rights." 
    Id.
     The Court
    also noted, however, that "the State has somewhat broader authority to regulate the activities of
    children than adults." 
    Id. at 74
    , 
    96 S.Ct. at 2843
    .
    Just how far a State can go in restricting a minor's access to abortion was sketched three years
    later in the seminal decision of Bellotti v. Baird, 
    443 U.S. 622
    , 
    99 S.Ct. 3035
    , 
    61 L.Ed.2d 797
     (1979)
    (Bellotti II ) (plurality opinion). There, the Court was faced with a challenge to a Massachusetts
    statute which required a minor under the age of eighteen to obtain parental consent before an abortion
    could be performed, but if such consent was not given, " "consent may be obtained by order of a
    judge of the superior court for good cause shown.' " 
    Id. at 625
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at 3039
     (emphasis added).
    The Massachusetts Supreme Court had interpreted this judicial bypass provision to mean that a minor
    could not obtain a court order without any parental consent whatsoever. 
    Id. at 646
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at
    3049-
    50. Thus, in Bellotti II, the Court had to determine whether this bypass procedure satisfied the
    Constitution.
    The Court held that it did not. The Court first recognized that parental consent statutes must
    "provide an alternative procedure" in the event the minor is unable to secure one or both parents'
    consent. 
    Id. at 643
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at 3048
    . Turning next to the Massachusetts bypass provision, the Court
    concluded that Massachusetts's judicial bypass procedure "would impose an undue burden upon the
    exercise by minors of the right to seek an abortion." 
    Id. at 647
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at 3050
    . In reaching this
    conclusion, the Court presented the competing considerations underlying a minor's choice to
    terminate her pregnancy. The Court recognized that minors are vulnerable, less able than adults to
    make informed and mature decisions, and that parents play a central role in childrearing. 
    Id. at 634
    ,
    
    99 S.Ct. at 3043
    . Balanced against these concerns, the Court noted, are the battle lines that often
    develop in families in which one or both parents have strong views about abortion—battle lines that
    prevent minors from obtaining abortions. 
    Id. at 647
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at 3050
    . With these considerations in
    mind, the Court specified four constitutional requirements that must be built into parental consent
    statutes. The Court wrote:
    A pregnant minor is ent itled to such a proceeding to show either: (1) that she is mature
    enough and well enough informed to make her abortion decision, in consultation with her
    physician, independently of her parents' wishes; or (2) that even if she is not able to make this
    decision independently, the desired abortion would be in her best interests. The proceeding
    in which this showing is made must assure that a resolution of the issue, and any appeals that
    may follow, will be completed with [3] anonymity and [4] sufficient expedition to provide an
    effective opportunity for an abortion to be obtained.
    
    Id. at 643-44
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at 3048
     (footnote omitted); see also Ohio v. Akron Center for Reproductive
    Health, 
    497 U.S. 502
    , 511-14, 
    110 S.Ct. 2972
    , 2979-81, 
    111 L.Ed.2d 405
     (1990) (Akron II )
    (presenting the four Bellotti II requirements). If the minor demonstrates that she is mature,
    well-informed, or that the abortion would be in her best interest, the Bellotti II Court held that the
    bypass decisionmaker "must " authorize the abortion. Bellotti II, 
    443 U.S. at 647, 648
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at 3050, 3050-51
     (emphasis added). Because Massachusetts's bypass procedure did not comport with
    these requirements, the Court declared the statute unconstitutional. 
    Id. at 647-48
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at
    3050-
    51.
    Since Bellotti II, lower federal courts have come to the unanimous conclusion that once a
    minor satisfies the maturity criteria or the best-interest test, bypass decisionmakers must order an
    abortion. We took the lead in Scheinberg v. Smith, 
    659 F.2d 476
     (5th Cir. Unit B Oct.1981),
    overruled on other grounds in Casey, 
    505 U.S. 833
    , 
    112 S.Ct. 2791
    , 
    120 L.Ed.2d 674
    , where we
    held that abstention was inappropriate because a Florida bypass procedure presented federal
    constitutional issues. Id. at 481. The relevant statute provided that a court "may" order a minor to
    have an abo rtion if she demonstrates that she is sufficiently mature. Id. at 478 (quoting 
    Fla. Stat. Ann. § 390.001
    (4)(a) (West 1981)). In reaching the conclusion that we should not abstain, we
    reasoned:
    The language of Bellotti II is not permissive: "[i]f [the minor] satisfies the court that she is
    mature and well enough informed to make intelligently the abortion decision on her own, the
    court must authorize her to act ..." [Citation.] Thus, whether permissive or mandatory,
    subsection 4(a) vests Florida courts with constitutionally impermissible discretion to ignore
    a minor's maturity in determining whether to authorize her abortion.
    Id. at 481 (original emphasis). Other Circuits have read Bellotti II in the same way.7
    Bellotti II, of course, did not answer all of the questions surrounding minors' access to
    abortion. In fact, the fate of Bellotti II was at first unclear because it was decided by a plurality of
    the Court. Since then, however, the Court has held that Bellotti II is cont rolling precedent, see
    Lambert v. Wicklund, No. 96-858, 
    1997 WL 141488
    , at 2, --- U.S. ----, ---- - ----, --- S.Ct. ----, ---- -
    ----, --- L.Ed.2d ---- (U.S. Mar. 31, 1997); Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey, 
    505 U.S. 833
    , 898-900, 
    112 S.Ct. 2791
    , 2832, 
    120 L.Ed.2d 674
     (1992); City of Akron v. Akron Ctr. for
    Reproductive Health, 
    462 U.S. 416
    , 439-40, 
    103 S.Ct. 2481
    , 2497-98, 
    76 L.Ed.2d 687
     (1983)
    (Akron I ), and we have not thought otherwise, Barnes v. Mississippi, 
    992 F.2d 1335
    , 1338-39 (5th
    Cir.1993); Scheinberg v. Smith, 
    659 F.2d 476
    , 480-81 (5th Cir. Unit B Oct.1981).8 The Court has
    also suggested that absolute anonymity is not required in bypass proceedings. See Akron II, 
    497 U.S. at 513
    , 
    110 S.Ct. at 2980
    .
    With these background principles in mind, we turn next to the specific provisions of Act 1254
    to determine whether they comport with Bellotti II and its progeny.
    A. The Constitutionality of La. R.S. 40:1299.35.5(B)(4) & (6)
    7
    See Planned Parenthood, Sioux Falls Clinic v. Miller, 
    63 F.3d 1452
    , 1462 (8th Cir.1995) ("If
    a minor can demonstrate that she is mature, the State has no legitimate reason for imposing liberty
    restrictions upon her that it may not impose on an adult."), cert. denied sub nom. Janklow v.
    Planned Parenthood, Sioux Falls Clinic, --- U.S. ----, 
    116 S.Ct. 1582
    , 
    134 L.Ed.2d 679
     (1996);
    Indiana Planned Parenthood v. Pearson, 
    716 F.2d 1127
    , 1134 (7th Cir.1983) ("The statute does
    not—and constitutionally cannot—give the juvenile court the authority to refuse to waive
    notification despite a finding that the minor is mature.").
    8
    The State appears to suggest in their brief that Bellotti II has been modified by subsequent
    decisions of the Supreme Court. However, as our discussion suggests, the Court has never
    questioned the viability of the four Bellotti II requirements and we decline to do so in this case.
    More importantly, the State backed off this claim at oral argument, where it conceded that Act
    1254 must be evaluated under Bellotti II.
    Act 1254 changes Louisiana's judicial bypass procedure so that a minor who demonstrates
    that she is mature, well-informed, or that an abortion would be in her best interest, "may" receive
    judicial authorization for the abortion. La. R.S. 40:1299.35.5(B)(4), (6). In addition, Act 1254 sets
    up a state-sponsored "evaluation and counseling" scheme to which a minor may be referred within
    forty-eight hours of a hearing before the juvenile court. La. R.S. 40:1299.35.5(B)(4). The plaintiffs
    challenge (B)(4) and (6) on two grounds. First, the plaintiffs claim that (B)(4) and (6) violate the
    Bellotti II principle that mature and well-informed minors and those for whom an abortion is in their
    best interest must receive judicial authorization to have an abortion. Second, the plaintiffs claim that
    (B)(4)'s requirement that minors receive counseling from state health and social services agencies
    violates the Bellotti II principle that bypass proceedings are to proceed expeditiously. The district
    court agreed with the plaintiffs on both issues. We discuss each of these holdings in turn.
    1. "Shall" versus "May" in § 1299.35.5(B)(4) and (6)
    The 1981 version of § 1299.35.5(B) provided that if a minor demonstrates that she is either
    mature and well-informed or that the abortion would be in her best interest, the juvenile court "shall"
    order an abortion. La. R.S. 40:1299.35.5(B)(4), (5) (West 1992). As we noted above, this language
    appeared in Louisiana's judicial bypass statute because of the Supreme Court's decision in Bellotti II,
    which rendered the 1978 version of § 1299.35.5(B) unconstitutional. See Margaret S.(I), 488
    F.Supp. at 203. And with, among other things, the addition of the mandatory "shall" language, the
    1981 version of § 1299.35.5(B) survived a constitutional challenge. Margaret S.(II), 597 F.Supp.
    at 650-52.
    Against this legislative backdrop, the district court declared § 1299.35.5(B)(4) and (6)
    unconstitutional. The court looked to the common meaning of the terms "shall" and "may" and
    concluded that the Louisiana Legislature intended a change in the statutory framework governing the
    judicial bypass procedure. "[T]he clear intent of the statutory amendment," reasoned the district
    court, "was to grant the substantive power of discretion to the judges of this state that is directly
    contrary to the rulings of the Supreme Court in Casey, Akron II and Bellotti II." 
    905 F.Supp. at 364
    .
    The State in its briefs and at oral argument strenuously asserts that § 1299.35.5(B)(4) and (6)
    is constitutional because (1) the change from "shall" to "may" does not confer discretion on juvenile
    court judges to deny a minor an abortion if the minor is mature and well-informed or if the abortion
    is in the minor's best interest; and (2) subsections(B)(4) and (6) are procedural in nature and
    therefore do not contradict the substantive federal law in this area. Neither of these arguments is
    persuasive.
    We reject the State's co ntention that the change from "shall" to "may" does not confer
    discretion on juvenile court judges. We note by way of illustration that with one partial exception,9
    Louisiana stands alone on this front: As far as we are aware, every state with a parental consent or
    notification statute has used the mandatory "shall" language in their judicial bypass schemes.10 The
    State's argument that subsections (4) and (6) pass constitutional muster takes one of two forms.
    First, the word change does not on its face give juvenile courts the discretion to deny a minor an
    abortion if the minor shows that she is mature, well-informed, or that the abortion would be in her
    best interest; or, alternatively, even though the statute on its face states that a juvenile court judge
    9
    North Dakota appears to be the only other state in which a bypass decisionmaker "may" order
    an abortion if the Bellotti II requirements are met. N.D. CENT.CODE § 14-02.1-03.1(5)(a),
    (b)(1)-(3) (1995). To be sure, unlike Louisiana, part of North Dakota's statutory scheme tracks
    Bellotti II. For example, if a minor in North Dakota demonstrates that she is mature and well
    informed, § 14-02.1-03.1(5)(a) provides that "the court shall issue an order authorizing a
    competent physician to perform the abortion procedure on the minor." (Emphasis added.)
    However, if the minor fails to demonstrate she is mature and well informed, § 14-02.1-
    03.1(5)(b)(1), (3) provides that the court "may" order an abortion if the court determines that the
    abortion is nevertheless in the minor's best interests. On this point, the North Dakota statute is
    similar to La. R.S. 40:1299.35.5(B)(6).
    10
    See ALA.CODE § 26-21-4(f)(1), (2) (1996); ARIZ.REV.STAT. ANN. § 36-2152(B) (1996);
    ARK.CODE ANN. § 20-16-804(1)(A), (B) (1995); CAL. HEALTH & SAFETY CODE § 123450(c)(1),
    (2) (West 1996); 24 DEL.CODE ANN. § 1784(b) (1995); GA.CODE ANN. § 15-11-114(c)(1), (2)
    (1996); ILL. ANN. STAT. Ch. 750, para. 70/25(d)(1), (2) (Smith-Hurd 1996); IND.CODE ANN. §
    16-34-2-4(d) (West 1996); KAN. STAT. ANN. § 65-6705(e)(1), (2) (1995); KY.REV.STAT. ANN.
    § 311.732(4)(a), (b) (Baldwin 1996); 22 ME.REV.STAT. ANN. § 1597-A(6)(A)(5), (D)(1)-(2)
    (West 1995); MICH. COMP. LAWS ANN. § 722.904(3)(a), (b) (West 1996); MINN.STAT. ANN. §
    144.343(6)(c)(i) (West 1996); MISS.CODE ANN. § 41-41-55(4)(a), (b) (1995); MO. ANN. STAT.
    § 188.028(2), (3)(a)-(b) (Vernon 1996); MONT.CODE ANN. § 50-20-212(5)(a), (b) (1995); NEB.
    REV. STAT. § 71-6903(1) (1995); NEV. REV. STAT. § 442.2555(3)(a)-(d), (4) (1995); N.C. GEN.
    STAT. § 90-21.8(e)(1), (2) (1995); OHIO REV.CODE ANN. § 2151.85(C)(1), (2) (Baldwin 1996);
    18 PA. CONS.STAT. ANN. § 3206(c), (d) (1996); R.I. GEN. LAWS § 23-4.7-6 (1995); S.C.CODE
    ANN. § 44-41-32(5) (1995); TENN.CODE ANN. § 37-10-304(e)(1), (2) (1996); W. VA.CODE §
    16-2F-4(f)(1)(2) (1996); WIS. STAT. ANN. § 48.375(7)(c)(1), (2) (West 1996); WYO. STAT. §
    35-6-118(b)(v)(B), (C) (1996).
    "may" order an abortion if the Bellotti II requirements are met, we should not assume that juvenile
    court judges will not order an abortion in violation of Bellotti II.
    The State itself sows the seeds for rejecting the claim that "shall" ostensibly carries the same
    meaning as "may." In its briefs and at oral argument, the State claims that in determining the
    constitutionality of § 1299.35.5(B), we should follow Louisiana's rules of statutory construction.
    When we consider the constitutionality of state statutes, we look to the rules of statutory construction
    of the state, see, e.g., Leavitt v. Jane, --- U.S. ----, ---- - ----, 
    116 S.Ct. 2068
    , 2069-72, 
    135 L.Ed.2d 443
     (1996) (per curiam); Barnes v. Mississippi, 
    992 F.2d at 1341-42
    , mindful of the principle that
    we should avoid "federal-court nullification of state law," Leavitt, --- U.S. at ----, 
    116 S.Ct. at 2072
    ,
    and "[w]here fairly possible, ... construe a statute to avoid a danger of unconstitutionality," Ashcroft,
    
    462 U.S. at 493
    , 
    103 S.Ct. at 2526
    ; Akron II, 
    497 U.S. at 514
    , 
    110 S.Ct. at 2980-81
    .
    Under Louisiana law, "the paramount consideration for statutory interpretation is the
    ascertainment of the legislative intent and the reason or reasons which prompted the legislature to
    enact the law." Fontenot v. Chevron, U.S.A., Inc., 
    676 So.2d 557
    , 562 (La.1996). In searching for
    the legislative intent behind subsections (4) and (6), we begin with Article 9 of the Louisiana Civil
    Code, which provides:
    When a law is clear and unambiguous and its application does not lead to absurd
    consequences, the law shall be applied as written and no further interpretation may be made
    in search of the intent of the legislature.
    La. C.C. art. 9 (West 1996); Tucker v. Fowler, 
    668 So.2d 718
    , 719 (La.1996); Marine Marketing
    Servs., Inc. v. Louisiana Dep't of Ins., 
    673 So.2d 335
    , 338 (La.Ct.App. 1st Cir.1996) (holding that
    it was reversible error for trial court to look to statutory intent when the language of the statute was
    neither ambiguous nor produced absurd consequences). "When the wording of a Section is clear and
    free of ambiguity, the letter of it shall not be disregarded under the pretext of pursuing its spirit." La.
    R.S. 1:4 (West 1996); Sumrall v. Luhr Bros., 
    665 So.2d 796
    , 800 (La.Ct.App. 1st Cir.1995), writ
    denied, 
    669 So.2d 425
     (La.1996).
    Thus, when determining the Louisiana Legislature's intent behind subsections (4) and (6), we
    may only go beyond the plain terms of § 1299.35.5(B)(4) and (6) if the statute on its face is unclear
    or ambiguous or if application of the terms of subsections (4) and (6) produces "absurd
    consequences." We have found no decisions from the Louisiana courts interpreting the meaning of
    subsections (B)(4) and (6), no decisions interpreting the pertinent provisions of the 1981 version of
    § 1299.35.5(B), and no legislative history explaining the 1995 change from "shall" to "may." We
    therefore apply Louisiana's principles of statutory construction to § 1299.35.5(B)(4) and (6).
    We hold that § 1299.35.5(B)(4) and (6) plainly violates Bellotti II. As such, the statute is
    neither unclear nor ambiguous, nor does application of its plain terms produce absurd results. La.
    R.S. 1:3 (West 1996) provides:
    § 3. Words and phrases; how construed
    Words and phrases shall be read with their context and shall be construed according
    to the common and approved usage of the language. Technical words and phrases, and such
    others as may have acquired a peculiar and appropriate meaning in the law, shall be construed
    and understood according to such peculiar and appropriate meaning.
    The word "shall" is mandatory and the word "may" is permissive.
    (emphasis added); see also La. C.C. art. 11 (West 1996) ("The words of a law must be given their
    generally prevailing meaning."); Backhus v. Transit Cas. Co., 
    549 So.2d 283
    , 289 (La.1989) (same).
    We can imagine no more clear indication that § 1299.35.5(B)(4) and (6) on its face provides juvenile
    court judges discretion to deny an abortion to a minor who has met the Bellotti II requirements. The
    basic guide for interpreting Louisiana statutes states in unmistakably clear terms that "shall" means
    "mandatory" and that "may" means "permissive." Moreover, the common usage of the term
    "permissive" is "[a]llowed; allowable; that which may be done[;][l]enient; tolerant." BLACK'S LAW
    DICTIONARY at 1140 (6th ed.1990); Sumrall, 665 So.2d at 800 (looking to Black's Law Dictionary
    for common and approved usage). Thus, the plain language of § 1299.35.5(B)(4) and (6) states that
    juvenile court judges within Louisiana have the discretion to deny an abortion to a minor even though
    the minor demonstrates that she is mature, well-informed, or that the abortion would be in her best
    interest. This flies in the face of Bellotti II and its progeny.
    Our reading of the statute does not produce absurd consequences. We have done nothing
    more than apply the meaning of "may" and "shall" that exists in La. R.S. 1:3 to a statute that is neither
    unclear nor ambiguous on its face.          Louisiana courts have not declared that this sort of
    bread-and-butter interpretation of statutes produces "absurd consequences." Compare Breaux v.
    Hoffpauir, 
    674 So.2d 234
    , 236 (La.1996) (holding that interpretation of Louisiana statute would lead
    to absurd consequence because state definition of "actual wages" would be illegal under federal
    statute); Washington-St. Tammany Electrical Coop., Inc. v. Louisiana Pub. Serv. Comm'n, 
    671 So.2d 908
    , 914 (La.1996) (absurd consequence results when interpretation contravenes the purposes
    of the statute).
    The State would have us read § 1299.35.5(B) differently. They claim that § 1299.35.5(B)
    "provides only the procedural means needed for Louisiana state judges to apply the federal
    substantive principles in this area of law to individual cases in order to issue judgments in accordance
    with such substantive principles." Because, argues the State, § 1299.35.5(B) is a procedural statute,
    we must liberally construe the statute to effectuate its overall purposes. Second, the State points to
    the Louisiana Supreme Court's decision in Rathborne Lumber & Supply Co. v. Falgout, 
    218 La. 629
    ,
    
    50 So.2d 295
     (1950), in which the court stated in dictum: "[A]lthough words of a statute are
    permissive, ... sometimes they may require an interpretation giving them mandatory effect ... where
    the context or subject matter compels such construction or where it is necessary to carry out the clear
    policy and intention of the Legislature." 
    Id. at 635
    , 
    50 So.2d 295
    ; accord Romero v. Stephens, 
    359 So.2d 1061
    , 1065 (La.Ct.App.3d Cir.1978); Gurtler, Hebert & Co. v. Marquette Casualty Co., 
    145 So.2d 145
    , 147-48 (La.Ct.App. 4th Cir.1962). But see Hornsby v. Fidelity Nat'l Bank of Baton
    Rouge, 
    243 So.2d 96
    , 98 (La.Ct.App. 1st Cir.1971) (declining to follow Falgout, adhering to La.
    R.S. 1:3, and interpreting "may" and "shall" to mean "permissive" and "mandatory," respectively).
    Thus, concludes the State, we should follow Falgout in this case and effectuate the intent of the
    Louisiana Legislature as expressed in § 1299.35.0—"It is the intention of the Legislature of the State
    of Louisiana to regulate abortion to the extent permitted by decisions of the United States Supreme
    Court." We reject both arguments.
    For us to accept the State's claim that Act 1254 is a procedural statute that merely effectuates
    the substantive federal law in this area, we would have to conclude that the legislature did not in 1995
    intend to change § 1299.35.5(B). In other words, we would have to hold that the change from "shall"
    to "may" has no bearing on the constitutionality of Act 1254 because Act 1254 does not materially
    change the 1981 version of § 1299.35.5(B). We cannot accept the State's proposition that Act 1254
    does not change the law. First, we would in effect be interpreting the statute so that "may" means
    "shall," an interpretation that would be flatly inconsistent with the definition of those terms in La. R.S.
    1:3. Second, we would be ignoring the Louisiana Supreme Court's understanding of statutory
    changes. The court has said: "The legislature is presumed to have enacted a statute in light of the
    preceding statutes involving the same subject matter and court decisions construing those statutes,
    and where the new statute is worded differently from the preceding statute, the legislature is
    presumed to have intended to change the law." New Orleans Rosenbush Claims Serv., Inc. v. City
    of New Orleans, 
    653 So.2d 538
    , 544 (La.1995) (emphasis added). Nothing the State has said in their
    briefs or at oral argument persuades us that Act 1254 does not materially change the judicial bypass
    procedure in Louisiana.
    Perhaps the most basic flaw in the State's arguments is the assumption that we must go
    beyond the plain meaning of § 1299.35.5(B)(4) and (6). We decline to do so because, as we have
    said, the language of subsections (4) and (6) is clear, unambiguous, and does not produce absurd
    consequences. The State points us to no authority, and we perceive none, suggesting that procedural
    statutes are immune from Article 9's clear mandate. In addition, the State fails to provide any
    authority, and again we perceive none, for the proposition that Falgout is an exception to Article 9's
    statutory construction principle.
    Finally, the State argues that if we interpret § 1299.5.5(B)(4) and (6) to mean that juvenile
    court judges have the discretion to deny an abortion to a minor that meets the Bellotti II
    requirements, we would be indulging the inappropriate assumption that Louisiana judges will decline
    to follow the federal Constitution. We agree with the State that we should refrain from assuming that
    state actors will violate the law. "[T]he Fifth Circuit is not," as we have recognized, "a "roving
    commission[ ] assigned to pass judgment on the validity of the Nation's laws.' " Barnes v.
    Mississippi, 
    992 F.2d at 1342
     (quoting Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 
    413 U.S. 601
    , 610-11, 
    93 S.Ct. 2908
    , 2915, 
    37 L.Ed.2d 830
     (1973)).
    However, we make no such assumption here. We have held that § 1299.35.5(B)(4) and (6)
    on its face is inconsistent with Bellotti II and its progeny because it invests juvenile court judges with
    the discretion to deny a minor an abortion even though she satisfies the Bellotti II requirements. As
    such, this case is plainly distinguishable from our decision in Barnes v. Mississippi, 
    992 F.2d 1335
    .
    There, the plaintiffs brought a facial challenge against a rule promulgated by the Mississippi Supreme
    Court pursuant to a bypass statute that did not on its face conflict with Bellotti II. 
    Id. at 1337-41
    .
    The Mississippi statute notably provided that if a minor demonstrates that she is mature and
    well-informed or that the abortion would be in her best interest, the court must order the abortion.
    
    Id.
     at 1342 n. 4. The procedural rule challenged by the plaintiffs, although it was worded differently
    than the language in Bellotti II, did not on its face conflict with the statute. 
    Id. at 1341
     ("[T]he rule
    requires a minor to plead that notifying her parents of the abortion is not in her best interest.").
    Accordingly, we rejected the challenge to the Mississippi Supreme Court's procedural rule on the
    ground that "[i]f a Mississippi court does follow [the procedural rule] so as to conflict with Bellotti,
    a plaintiff will be free to launch an as-applied challenge to the bypass procedure." 
    Id. at 1342
    .
    Here, we face an entirely different situation. Juvenile court judges within Louisiana have a
    legislatively prescribed choice whether to order an abortion for a minor who is mature, well-informed,
    or for whom an abortion would be in her best interest. It is this discretion itself, and not the exercise
    of it, that we find inconsistent with Bellotti II.
    In short, § 1299.35.5(B)(4) and (6) is unconstitutional. We affirm the district court's decision
    to permanently enjoin these provisions of Act 1254.
    2. Expeditiousness in § 1299.35.5(B)(3) and (4)
    Section 1299.35.5(B)(3) provides that "[e]ach application shall be heard in chambers,
    anonymously, in a summary manner, and within forty-eight hours of the filing thereof." Except for
    the admonition that the hearing proceed in a "summary manner," subsection (B)(3) on its face does
    not pro vide a specific time frame for deciding the merits of a minor's application. Section
    1299.35.5(B)(4) provides that a juvenile court may require a minor to attend various state-sponsored
    evaluation and counseling sessions within forty-eight hours of the ex parte hearing with the juvenile
    court judge. Subsection (B)(4), like subsection (3), does not on its face provide a time frame within
    which that evaluation is to be completed and the results forwarded to the court. Nor does subsection
    (4) contain the "summary manner" language found in subsection (3).
    The plaintiffs claim that § 1299.35.5(B)(3) and (4) violates the Bellotti II requirement that
    bypass procedures proceed expeditiously because both subsections provide an indefinite time period
    for the juvenile court judge to decide the merits of the minor's application. The district court agreed
    with the plaintiffs that subsections (B)(3) and (4) did not meet the Bellotti II requirement for
    expeditious resolution of bypass applications. 
    905 F.Supp. at 365
    .11 On appeal, the State argues that
    the district court erred in reaching this conclusion because the statute requires juvenile court judges
    to conduct the proceedings in a "summary manner," and to hold that this provision violates Bellotti
    II, we "would have to assume that a state district judge would intentionally ignore the requirements
    of state law and the dictates of the United States Supreme Court."
    We agree with the district court that subsections (B)(3) and (4) are inconsistent with Bellotti
    II because they do not provide for an expeditious resolution of the minor's bypass application. We
    again frame our analysis in accord with Louisiana's rules of statutory construction and determine
    whether proceeding in a "summary manner" satisfies Bellotti II 's expedition requirement. Louisiana
    Civil Code article 2595 (West 1996) provides that in a summary proceeding, "[t]he court shall render
    its decision as soon as practicable after the conclusion of the trial of a summary proceeding and,
    whenever practicable, without taking the matter under advisement." (Emphasis added).
    Such an open-ended bypass procedure has never been approved. We should not, as the
    Supreme Court has suggest ed, "invalidate[ ] [a bypass] statute on a facial challenge based upon a
    worst-case analysis that may never occur." Akron II, 
    497 U.S. at 514
    , 
    110 S.Ct. at 2981
    . The
    11
    The district court stated that "the provisions of Act 1254 amend Section B(4) of the Act to
    require that the juvenile court hear the bypass application within 48 hours, without any
    requirement as to when the application must be ruled upon." 
    905 F.Supp. at 365
     (emphasis
    added). Our reading of the statute, however, reveals that subsection B(3) provides the forty-eight
    hour time frame and that the only change made by Act 1254 was to substitute the word
    "confidentially" with "anonymously." Act 1254 did not for the first time introduce the forty-eight
    hour and "summary manner" requirements; both appeared in the 1981 version of § 1299.35.5(B).
    Supreme Court has held that a seventeen- and twenty-two-day delay satisfies Bellotti II. Akron II,
    
    497 U.S. at 514
    , 
    110 S.Ct. at 2980-81
     (22 days); Ashcroft, 
    462 U.S. at
    479 n. 4, 491 n. 16, 
    103 S.Ct. at
    2519 n. 4, 2525 n. 16 (17 days). An indefinite period, however, has been rejected. In Glick
    v. McKay, 
    937 F.2d 434
     (9th Cir.1991),12 the Ninth Circuit determined the constitutionality of the
    bypass procedure in Nevada's parental notification statute. Like Louisiana's bypass procedure,
    Nevada's statute did not on its face provide a time frame within which a minor's bypass application
    was to be decided. Id. at 438. The Ninth Circuit struck down the statute as inconsistent with Bellotti
    II. "Under the statute," reasoned the court, "the district court could ... delay the bypass procedure
    indefinitely. The district court review procedure does not meet the Bellotti expediency criterion."
    Id. at 440-41; see also id. at 441 n. 4 (stating that "an indefinite period does not" satisfy Bellotti II
    ).
    Subsections (B)(3) and (4) plainly conflict with Bellotti II because the juvenile court is not
    required to rule on the minor's application within any specified time nor are state counselors required
    to report back to the juvenile court within any specified time. We hold that "whenever practicable"
    does not satisfy constitutional standards of expediency. There is no fall-back (or constructive
    authorization) provision within subsection (3) that deems a minor's application granted in the event
    the juvenile court does not act within a particular time frame. Thus, not only do subsections (3) and
    (4) fail to provide any specific time within which a minor's application will be decided, but they give
    no assurances (assurances required by Bellotti II ) that the proceedings will conclude expeditiously.
    The State attempts to rescue subsection (3) by pointing to Article 2591 (West 1961) of the
    Louisiana Civil Code, which provides: "Summary proceedings are those which are conducted with
    rapidity, within the delays allowed by the court, and without citation and the observance of all the
    formalities required in ordinary proceedings." (Emphasis added). Plainly, the "rapidity" language
    refers to the expeditiousness of the summary proceeding itself, not to the time a judge has to decide
    12
    The Supreme Court has disapproved the analysis in Glick, in which the Ninth Circuit held
    unconstitutional a bypass procedure which allowed a minor to have an abortion if parental
    notification, and not the abortion itself, was not in the minor's best interest. Lambert v. Wicklund,
    
    1997 WL 141488
    , at *2-*4, --- U.S. at ---- - ----, --- S.Ct. at ---- - ----. Nothing in Lambert
    affects Glick's holding regarding Bellotti II's expediency requirement.
    the merits of a case. We inevitably return to article 2595 which does, as we have said, prescribe the
    time frame within which a decision in a summary proceeding is to be rendered—"as soon as
    practicable." This is insufficient under Bellotti II.
    Finally, contrary to the State's contention, we do not portray Louisiana juvenile court judges
    or state-employed counselors as individuals who would intentionally violate Bellotti II, nor are we
    analyzing the constitutionality of subsections (B)(3) and (4) under a worst-case scenario. We have
    simply looked to the plain terms of § 1299.35.5(B)(3) and (4) to determine the rules juvenile court
    judges are required to follow when presented with a bypass application from a minor. The Louisiana
    Legislature has told them that they must rule on the application "as soon as" or "whenever
    practicable." This violates Bellotti II 's expedition requirement on its face. We therefore affirm the
    district court's decision to permanently enjoin subsections (3) and (4).
    B. The Constitutionality of La. R.S. 40:1299.35.5(B)(5)
    Section 1299.35.5(B)(5) provides, among other things, that the juvenile court "shall" notify
    the parent(s) or legal guardian if the court determines that such notification is in the minor's best
    interest. The plaintiffs contend, and the district court agreed, that § 1299.35.5(B)(5) does not satisfy
    Bellotti II 's anonymity requirement. The State, on the other hand, contends that § 1299.35.5(B)(5)
    comports with Bellotti II. The State relies on the following language in Bellotti II for this conclusion:
    [T]he court may deny the abortion request of an immature minor in the absence of parental
    consultation if it concludes that her best interests would be served thereby, or the court may
    in such a case defer decision until there is parental consultation in which the court may
    participate.
    Bellotti II, 
    443 U.S. at 648
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at 3050-51
     (emphasis added). From this statement, the State
    argues that the Bellotti II Court "seem[ed] to encourage [parental notification], if the courts believe
    to do so is in the minors [sic ] best interest." We agree with the district court and conclude that the
    State is mistaken.
    As the plaintiffs and the district court correctly note, this language from Bellotti II in no way
    permits the independent bypass decisionmaker to contact a minor's parents, inform them that their
    minor daughter is seeking an abortion without their consent, and then ask the parents to participate
    in the process of deciding whether the abortion would be in the minor's best interest. We read the
    statement from Bellotti II to mean that a Louisiana juvenile court can refuse to authorize a minor's
    abortion if parental notification is in the minor's best interest, or the court may wait until the minor
    herself seeks parental consultation, and then, with both the parents' and minor's input, determine
    whether an abortion is in the minor's best interest.
    Any other interpretation of this language—or shall we say, the State's interpretation—would
    cut the core out of Bellotti II. If Bellotti II means anything, it surely means that States seeking to
    regulate minors' access to abortion must offer a credible bypass procedure, independent of parents
    or legal guardians, in a parental consent statute like the one in Louisiana. Plainly, the State has
    attempted    to   enter   through    the   proverbial     back    door    by   suggesting     that   the
    "best-interest-of-the-minor" inquiry cannot arbitrarily exclude the input of parents or a legal guardian.
    Although the Supreme Court has recognized that bypass decisionmakers can consider whether
    parental notification would be in the best interest of the minor, Bellotti II, 
    443 U.S. at 640
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at 3046-47
    , and that complete anonymity is not required, Akron II, 
    497 U.S. at 513
    , 
    110 S.Ct. at 2980
    , the Court has not held that anonymity may give way to parental notification in bypass statutes.
    The Supreme Court's decision in H.L. v. Matheson, 
    450 U.S. 398
    , 
    101 S.Ct. 1164
    , 
    67 L.Ed.2d 388
     (1981) is not to the contrary. There, the Court upheld a parental notification provision,
    reasoning that "a statute setting out a "mere requirement of parental notice' does not violate the
    constitutional rights of an immature, dependent minor." 
    Id. at 409
    , 
    101 S.Ct. at 1171
    . Because the
    Court has yet to address the question of whether a bypass procedure is required for parental
    notification statutes, we do not read Matheson to hold that parental notification is an exception to
    the Bellotti II anonymity requirement. Indeed, if we were to agree with the State that Matheson
    modified the anonymity requirement in Bellotti II, we would create an exception that swallows the
    rule. The central thrust of Bellotti II was to ensure that minors who could not or would not seek the
    consent of a parent or legal guardian have access to a bypass procedure that would ensure anonymity
    from parents who may "obstruct both an abortion and their access to court." Bellotti II, 
    443 U.S. at 647
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at 3050
    . By requiring a juvenile court judge to notify a minor's parents if the judge
    finds that doing so would be in the minor's best interest, Louisiana has undermined the independent
    bypass procedure prescribed in Bellotti II.
    We affirm the district court's conclusion that subsection (5) of § 1299.35.5(B) is inconsistent
    with Bellotti II 's anonymity requirement.
    CONCLUSION
    We do not question Louisiana's interest in regulating the circumstances under which minors
    may obtain abortions or its interest in ensuring that minors make an informed choice to have an
    abortion. The Supreme Court has stressed, as have we, the need to balance parents' strong interest
    in participating in a minor's upbringing against a minor's constitutional right to an abortion. Beginning
    with Bellotti II, the Supreme Court has balanced these competing interests in a manner which
    mandates our decision today. Accordingly, if the Louisiana Legislature chooses to modify its judicial
    bypass procedure, it must do so consistent with the teachings of the Supreme Court and our
    Constitution. We hold that Act 1254 is facially unconstitutional under the Due Process Clause of the
    Fourteenth Amendment of the Constitution.
    The summary judgment of the district court permanently enjoining Act 1254 is AFFIRMED.
    AFFIRMED.
    EMILIO M. GARZA, Circuit Judge, concurring specially:
    For the second time in my judicial career, I am forced to follow a Supreme Court opinion I
    believe to be inimical to the Constitution. See Sojourner T. v. Edwards, 
    974 F.2d 27
    , 31 (5th
    Cir.1992) (Garza, J., concurring specially). Although I have misgivings about whether the Act's
    failure to require expedient decision can support a facial challenge under United States v. Salerno,
    
    481 U.S. 739
    , 745, 
    107 S.Ct. 2095
    , 2100, 
    95 L.Ed.2d 697
     (1987), I generally agree with the
    majority's opinion that certain provisions of Act 1254 are unconstitutional according to the Supreme
    Court's opinion in Bellotti v. Baird, 
    443 U.S. 622
    , 
    99 S.Ct. 3035
    , 
    61 L.Ed.2d 797
     (1979) (Bellotti
    II ). I respectfully disagree with the Bellotti II Court that the Constitution requires the result we
    reach today. I do not believe that the language of the Fourteenth Amendment speaks to the discretion
    judges may exercise in permitting minors to have an abortion. I think that the Bellotti II opinion
    crossed the line from judicial review to judicial legislation. Furthermore, in the absence of governing
    constitutional text, I believe that ontological issues such as abortion are more properly decided in the
    political and legislative arenas. Mindful, however, that the Constitution invests the Supreme Court
    with the final say, I defer to the Court's authority and concur in the majority opinion.
    I
    My disagreement with the holding of Bellotti II begins generally with substantive due process.
    Although the Supreme Court has assumed that the Fourteenth Amendment has a substantive
    component, see Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 
    505 U.S. 833
    , 846, 
    112 S.Ct. 2791
    , 2804, 
    120 L.Ed.2d 674
     (1992) (Due Process Clause "has been understood to contain a substantive
    component"), it has found the boundaries of such substantive rights to be elusive. Nonetheless,
    courts have extended such protections quite far, as evidenced by the Bellotti II opinion, which
    establishes ambitious and very specific minimum requirements for parental consent statutes in the
    abortion context.
    A
    The constitutional mandate of Bellotti II springs from a single word used by the drafters of
    the Civil War amendments: liberty. Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 846
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2804
    . The relevant portion
    of the Fourteenth Amendment provides that "[n]o state shall ... deprive any person of life, liberty, or
    property, without due process of law...." U.S. Const. amend. XIV. Drafted in the wake of the Civil
    War, this clause stands as a guarantee against arbitrary action against people by state governments.
    Daniels v. Williams, 
    474 U.S. 327
    , 331, 
    106 S.Ct. 662
    , 665, 
    88 L.Ed.2d 662
     (1986).
    "Substantive" due process, as the argument goes, is implicit in this notion. Proponents
    suggest (or assume) that some government action departs so far from the constitutional scheme that
    no amount of process will be sufficient to ratify its legitimacy. See, e.g., Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 846
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2804
    ; Daniels, 
    474 U.S. at 331
    , 
    106 S.Ct. at 665
    . The Court has "understood" the
    Fourteenth Amendment to include such guarantees at least as far back as 1887, see Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 846
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at
    2804 (citing Mugler v. Kansas, 
    123 U.S. 623
    , 660-61, 
    8 S.Ct. 273
    , 291, 
    31 L.Ed. 205
     (1887)) (holding that the Fourteenth Amendment protected brewer from arbitrary
    deprivation of property), although the Court has probably understood the notion of due process to
    include a substantive component at least as early as Dred Scott v. Sanford, 60 U.S. (How.) 393, 450,
    
    15 L.Ed. 691
     (1856) (interpreting the Fifth Amendment to say that "an act of Congress which
    deprives a citizen of the United States of his liberty or property, merely because he came himself or
    brought his property into a particular Territory of the United States, and who had committed no
    offence against the laws, could hardly be dignified with the name of due process of law.").
    Employing this theory of substantive guarantees, the Supreme Court has read the word
    "liberty" to create extensive, "fundamental" rights that the state may burden only under the most
    compelling of circumstances and only in the narrowest of ways. The Court has used the Fourteenth
    Amendment to constitutionalize such issues as contraception, Carey v. Population Services Int'l 
    431 U.S. 678
    , 684-85, 
    97 S.Ct. 2010
    , 2015-16, 
    52 L.Ed.2d 675
     (1977); Griswold v. Connecticut, 
    381 U.S. 479
    , 483-86, 
    85 S.Ct. 1678
    , 1681-82, 
    14 L.Ed.2d 510
     (1965); municipal housing regulations,
    Moore v. East Cleveland, 
    431 U.S. 494
    , 499, 
    97 S.Ct. 1932
    , 1935, 
    52 L.Ed.2d 531
     (1977) (plurality
    opinion); child rearing, Santosky v. Kramer, 
    455 U.S. 745
    , 753, 
    102 S.Ct. 1388
    , 1394, 
    71 L.Ed.2d 599
     (1982); marriage, Loving v. Virginia, 
    388 U.S. 1
    , 12, 
    87 S.Ct. 1817
    , 1823, 
    18 L.Ed.2d 1010
    (1967); school curricula, Pierce v. Society of Sisters, 
    268 U.S. 510
    , 535, 
    45 S.Ct. 571
    , 573, 
    69 L.Ed. 1070
     (1925); and, of course, abortion, Roe v. Wade 
    410 U.S. 113
    , 152-53, 
    93 S.Ct. 705
    , 726-27,
    
    35 L.Ed.2d 147
     (1973). This list is only a partial catalogue of issues, not mentioned anywhere in the
    Constitution generally or the Fourteenth Amendment specifically, that the Supreme Court has
    removed from the political arena. The Court's good intentions, expressed in these cases, have slowly
    eroded the scope of public debate.
    I do not believe that we should narrow the scope of procedural protection afforded by the
    Fifth or Fourteenth Amendments. Nor do I dispute that the Fourteenth Amendment incorporates
    most of the Bill of Rights. See, e.g., Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 847
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2804
    ; Duncan v.
    Louisiana, 
    391 U.S. 145
    , 147-148, 
    88 S.Ct. 1444
    , 1446, 
    20 L.Ed.2d 491
     (1968). However, I think
    it is a mistake to create new substantive rights, of whole cloth, for every state and for all time, under
    implicit "penumbras" of a written Constitution; see, e.g., Griswold v. Connecticut, 
    381 U.S. 479
    ,
    484, 
    85 S.Ct. 1678
    , 1681, 
    14 L.Ed.2d 510
     (1965) ("[S]pecific guarantees in the Bill of Rights have
    penumbras, formed by emanations from those guarantees that help give them life and substance.");
    through constitutional extrapolation, see 
    id. at 484
    , 
    85 S.Ct. at 1682
     (holding that contraception,
    although not mentioned in the Bill of Rights, "concerns a relationship lying within the zone of privacy
    created by several fundamental constitutional guarantees"); or by mere assumptions, see Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 982
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2875
     (Scalia, J., dissenting in part) (" "[R]easoned judgment' does not begin
    by begging the question, as Roe and subsequent cases unquestionably did by assuming that what the
    State is protecting is the mere "potentiality of human life.' ").
    Perhaps many of the most important substantive due process cases could have been decided
    under other constitutional provisions, such as the First Amendment. See, e.g., Meyer v. Nebraska,
    
    262 U.S. 390
    , 399-403, 
    43 S.Ct. 625
    , 627, 
    67 L.Ed. 1042
     (1923) (striking down statute that forbade
    teaching of German in grammar school). Alternatively, some of these issues could have been dealt
    with by the states—if no extant constitutional provision stood in conflict with these laws, the Court
    need not have stretched the Fourteenth Amendment to create conflict. State legislatures could have
    changed laws as public attitudes changed. See, e.g., Conn. Gen.Stat. § 53-32 (1969) (repealing
    Connecticut laws at issue in Griswold prohibiting use of contraceptives). It is a feature of a healthy
    democracy that evolving public norms find voice in new laws supported by the people.
    Some of these judicial decisions, such as invalidating statutes that discriminate based on race,
    reflect our nation's highest aspirations as an individualist, pluralist society. Nonetheless, judicial
    officers should not force the pace of change nor bind the nation to wise po licy using loose
    interpretations of our written Constitution. Neither our aspirations about privacy, nor our concerns
    about the consequences of leaving certain matters for states to decide, invests us with the authority
    to nullify state law. Article III courts should not cloak political choices with claims that those choices
    are required by the Due Process Clause. See Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 983
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2875
     (Scalia, J.,
    dissenting in part).
    Currently, the boundaries of subst antive due process are less than pellucid. As these
    unenumerated substantive rights are by their natures not explicit, the Court has understandably had
    difficulty in fixing their outer perimeter. We have been told by the Court that the limits of due
    process cannot be reduced to a formula, Poe v. Ullman, 
    367 U.S. 497
    , 542, 
    81 S.Ct. 1752
    , 1776, 
    6 L.Ed.2d 989
     (1961) (Harlan, J., dissenting), and that the doctrine's "boundaries are not susceptible
    of expression as a simple rule." Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 849
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2806
    . The Court has suggested
    that substantive rights must be so "implicit in the concept of ordered liberty," that "neither liberty nor
    justice would exist if [they were] sacrificed," Palko v. Connecticut, 
    302 U.S. 319
    , 325, 326, 
    58 S.Ct. 149
    , 151, 152, 
    82 L.Ed. 288
     (1937). It has also said that "at the heart of liberty is the right to define
    one's own concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life."
    Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 851
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2807
    . As illustrated by the catalogue of substantive due process
    rights discussed earlier, the Fourteenth Amendment (thus interpreted) puts quite a bit of public policy
    within the "heart" of liberty. This is how the Supreme Court has dealt with the admittedly difficult
    issue of circumscribing which rights and liberties the Fourteenth Amendment comprises.
    I do not believe that such open-ended inquiry can be helpful to judges interpreting the
    Fourteenth Amendment. We must return to those principles embedded in the Constitution. First, as
    Chief Justice Marshall said in Marbury v. Madison, "it is emphatically the province and duty of the
    judicial department to say what the law is." 5 U.S. (Cranch) 137, 177, 
    2 L.Ed. 60
     (1803).
    Importantly, "to say what the law is" presupposes that there is law to interpret. The Constitution
    does not charge courts with legislation, merely interpretation.
    Second, the powers of legislatures are limited, but not by the inherent power of the courts.
    They are circumscribed by a written constitution: "The powers of the legislature are defined and
    limited; and that those limits may not be mistaken and forgotten, the constitution is written." 
    Id.
     
    5 U.S. at 176
     (emphasis added). Indeed, the Framers specifically protected against the combination
    of legislative and judicial powers in one branch. "The judges can exercise no executive prerogative,
    though they are shoots from the executive stock; nor any legislative function, though they may be
    advised by legislative councils.... "Were the power of judging joined with the legislative, the life and
    liberty of the subject would be exposed to arbitrary control, for the judge would then be the
    legislator.' " The Federalist No. 47, at 303 (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1961) (quoting
    Charles Montesquieu, The Spirit of Laws, Vol. I, Book IX (1748)).
    Third, the people, not the courts, established the Constitution;          it is a document of
    self-determination, not judicial determination. "That the people have an original right to establish,
    for their future government, such principles as, in their opinion, shall most conduce to their own
    happiness, is the basis on which the whole American fabric has been erected." Marbury, 
    5 U.S. at 176
     (emphasis added). In the context of unenumerated constitutional rights, the Supreme Court has
    constructed a new constitutional amendment out of the single word "liberty." Instead of interpreting
    liberty in the context of the Constitution, the Court would have us interpret the Constitution in the
    context of its broad interpretation of liberty. Viewed expansively, this word can turn the entire
    Constitution on its head and nullify any restraints on the Court's authority, judicial self-restraint
    notwithstanding, which the Constitution itself rejects.
    Fourth and finally, the Constitution is a flexible and dynamic document, designed to have as
    much vitality today as it did the day it was written. "This provision is made in a constitution, intended
    to endure for ages to come, and consequently, to be adapted to the various crises of human affairs."
    M'Culloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. (Wheat.) 316, 415, 
    4 L.Ed. 579
     (1819). Al though historical
    circumstances change, the principles that undergird the Constitution do not.
    With these principles in mind, we should consider the proper way to interpret the Fourteenth
    Amendment, and accordingly, the proper scope of substantive due process. As a starting point, an
    understanding of what constitutional amendments were supposed to mean should guide any attempt
    to interpret them. The power to amend the Constitution is one of the greatest powers bestowed by
    the Framers. The power to amend the Constitution gives the people the authority to constrain
    majorities present and future. Because amendments are so powerful, the Constitution provides a
    rigorous proposal and ratification procedure for constitutional amendments in Article V, giving
    special constitutional ratifying authority to the pronouncements of three-fourths of the states. This
    great authority to bind future generations is seated in the American people. Because only the drafters
    and the states have the power to amend, their understanding of the words they choose should govern
    the courts' interpretations where those words are ambiguous. Courts that stray beyond that meaning
    are acting beyond their authority. In Casey, however, the courts employed no textual analysis or
    legislative history, only judicial "understandings." Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 846
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2804
    .
    That is not to say that the Constitution or the Bill of Rights must be frozen in time. As
    Marshall said in M'Culloch, the Constitution is meant to endure, and its application must be flexible.
    No one would dispute that the First Amendment protects television or the internet, or that the Fourth
    Amendment protects cellular phones, even though none of these technologies existed in the late
    eighteenth century. The understanding of the drafters and ratifiers that Congress should not abridge
    the freedom of the media must guide the courts' application of timeless principles to changed
    circumstances. In this way, the understandings that undergird the Constitution and its amendments
    continue to have vitality in areas unforeseen at the drafting.
    To say that these understandings are flexible, however, is emphatically not to say that changed
    values gain constitutional precedence to govern changed circumstances. That is a different
    proposition altogether. It is unwise to read t he Constitution by reference to a telephone poll, see
    Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 962
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2865
     (Rehnquist, C.J., dissenting in part); even if it were
    possible, we have no authority to do so. Article V does not give amendment power to contemporary,
    majority viewpoints. It explicitly sets forth a procedure to be followed for amendment.
    To date, judicial attempts at understanding the meaning of the Fourteenth Amendment have
    proven unsatisfactory. Although the Court has held that the Due Process Clause incorporates most
    of the Bill of Rights against the states, Duncan v. Louisiana, 391, U.S. 145, 147-48, 
    88 S.Ct. 1444
    ,
    1446, 
    20 L.Ed.2d 491
     (1968), it has repudiated the notion that the Bill of Rights limits the
    interpretation of that clause. See Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 847
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at
    2804-05 (citing disagreement
    with Adamson v. California, 
    332 U.S. 46
    , 68-92, 
    67 S.Ct. 1672
    , 1683-97, 
    91 L.Ed. 1903
     (1947)
    (Black, J., dissenting)). The Court has also rejected the i dea that the drafters of the Due Process
    Clause only meant to protect citizens from state actions that were unconstitutional under the Due
    Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment or proscribed by other law when the Fourteenth Amendment
    was ratified. 
    Id.
     (citing disagreement with Michael H. v. Gerald D., 
    491 U.S. 110
    , 127-28 n. 6, 
    109 S.Ct. 2333
    , 2344-45 n. 6, 
    105 L.Ed.2d 91
     (1989)).
    In his seminal dissent in Poe v. Ullman (later adopted by the plurality in Casey), Justice Harlan
    provided a different view of how to interpret the Fourteenth Amendment. Justice Harlan suggested
    that we consult what "history teaches are the traditions from which [liberty] developed as well as the
    traditions from which it broke." Justice Harlan does not suggest that we look at the history of the
    Fourteenth Amendment, but rather to American history and traditions generally to determine what
    liberties have been protected. At first blush, American history might seem t o be a good point of
    reference—a fixed, knowable tradition from which we might draw understanding. There are two
    major problems with this approach. First, the traditions from which liberty developed may suggest
    a different role for government than was actually inscribed into the Fourteenth Amendment. Should
    the liberty of freed slaves under the Fourteenth Amendment truly be defined by reference to American
    history leading up to the Civil War?
    The second major difficulty of Justice Harlan's approach is that one can find whatever one
    seeks in history, if one is so determined. It is certainly true that Justice Harlan's look into the
    American history will produce a richer record from which to draw conclusions. However, to canvas
    all of American history will likely produce conflicting traditions, allowing those who look to find
    whatever answers they prefer. See Michael D., 
    491 U.S. at 137
    , 
    109 S.Ct. at 2349
     (Brennan, J.,
    dissenting) (Tradition "can be as malleable and as elusive as "liberty' itself...."); Moore v. East
    Cleveland, 
    431 U.S. 494
    , 549, 
    97 S.Ct. 1932
    , 1961, 
    52 L.Ed.2d 531
     (1977) (White, J., dissenting)
    ("What the deeply rooted traditions of the country are is arguable; which of them deserve the
    protection of the Due Process Clause is even more debatable.").
    The historical approach thus breaks down into the following conundrum: who decides which
    liberties were recognized in our history? How do we decide which history or tradition is relevant?
    The task, however, is not to interpret American history, but to interpret the words of the Fourteenth
    Amendment. The federal judiciary is not composed of historians, merely lawyers whose expertise is
    neither "history" nor "tradition." As used in Casey, concepts such as history and tradition have
    become ersatz constitutional provisions that courts substitute for the actual words.
    Understanding the meaning of the word "liberty" in the context of the legislative history of
    the Fourteenth Amendment avoids many of these judicial struggles to determine who gets to define
    history. Interpreting the Fourteenth Amendment by reference to the understanding of the drafters and
    ratifiers is an approach more closely targeted to the task of interpreting a written constitution. In fact,
    that is what the Supreme Court does in almost all other provisions of the Constitution.
    I realize that sometimes legislative history is less clear than the Amendment or statute it is
    supposed to illuminate, see, e.g., United States v. Public Utilities Commission, 
    345 U.S. 295
    , 320,
    
    73 S.Ct. 706
    , 720, 
    97 L.Ed. 1020
     (1953) (Jackson, J., concurring), and Congress often speaks with
    more than one voice as to why it chose particular language in a statute. Compare, e.g., TVA v. Hill,
    
    437 U.S. 153
    , 173-93, 
    98 S.Ct. 2279
    , 2291-2301, 
    57 L.Ed.2d 117
     (1978) (legislative history of
    Endangered Species Act expresses Congressional intent that Court should enjoin completion of
    federal dam that would threaten endangered species) with 
    id. at 207-10
    , 
    98 S.Ct. at 2308-09
     (Powell,
    J., dissenting) (legislative history of statute supports opposite view) (cited in Stephen Breyer, On the
    Uses of Legislative History in Interpreting Statutes, 65 S. Cal. L.Rev. 845, 862 n. 39 (1991)).
    Indeed, some Amendments and statutes have scarce history to consider. Such difficulties, however,
    are confronted by courts every day. Perfection in legislative history is not to be expected: I do not
    pretend that this judicial task will be easy, only necessary. Fortunately the drafters of the Fourteenth
    Amendment explained in some det ail what they meant to accomplish, the legislative history is
    particularly useful in interpreting the words of the Amendment. See, e.g., Adamson v. California,
    
    332 U.S. 46
    , 92-123, 
    67 S.Ct. 1672
    , 1696-1711, 
    91 L.Ed. 1903
     (1947) (appendix to dissent of Black,
    J., citing extensive legislative history of Fourteenth Amendment in Congress).
    The drafters of the Fourteenth Amendment certainly had more modest goals in mind by using
    the term "liberty" than the modern Supreme Court has. Liberty for the drafters came in the context
    of dealing with restrictive racial laws in the South. In the floor debates surrounding the drafting of
    the Fourteenth Amendment, the bill sponsor in the Senate, Senator Trumbull, suggested that the
    liberty interests involved were intended to deal with these statutes:
    "[S]tatutes of Mississippi ... provide that if any person of African descent residing in that
    State travels from one county to the another without having a pass or a certificate of his
    freedom, he is liable to be committed to jail and to be dealt with as a person who i s in the
    State without authority. Other provisions of the statute prohibit any negro or mulatto from
    having fire-arms; and one provision of the statute declares that for "exercising the functions
    of a minister of the Gospel free negroes ... on conviction, may be punished by ... lashes....'
    [ ... ] The statutes of South Carolina make it a highly penal offense for any person, white or
    colored, to teach slaves; and similar provisions are to be found running through all the
    statutes of the late slaveholding States.... The purpose of the bill ... is to destroy all these
    discriminations...."
    Adamson, 
    332 U.S. at 99-100
    , 
    67 S.Ct. at 1700
     (quoting Cong. Globe, 39th Cong. 1st Sess. 474
    (1865)). This does not suggest that the term "liberty" as used in the Fourteenth Amendment applies
    only to race-conscious statutes, indeed the plain language of the Fourteenth Amendment admits a
    broader interpretation. However, it does suggest a context in which to decide how to interpret the
    Amendment consistent with the drafters' intent, a context that was not intended to include abortion.
    I recognize that the Supreme Court has not accepted this approach. Indeed, the Court has
    recently held that such a fixed interpretive guideline is unhelpful in interpreting the Fourteenth
    Amendment. In Casey, the plurality stated that the Court should examine each case as it comes, ad
    hoc, to determine what substantive rights the Fourteenth Amendment guarantees, using "reasoned
    judgment." Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 849
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2806
    . The power of Article III courts to invalidate
    state laws under the Constitution is not so expansive—even the reasoned judgment of our wisest
    jurists cannot replace the written constitution as authority.
    Casey best illustrates the approach taken by the Supreme Court. Near the end of the plurality
    opinion, the Court says that "[e]ach generation must learn anew that the Constitution's written terms
    embody ideas and aspirations that survive more ages than one." Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 901
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2833
    . This is in line with my earlier suggestion that old understandings apply to new situations and
    that the Constitution is limited by its words. But that is not what the Casey court actually did in the
    opinion. In deciding whether the abortion regulations at stake fell within the ambit of the Fourteenth
    Amendment, the court cited Justice Harlan's dissent in Poe v. Ullman. Specifically the Court quoted
    two extensive passages of that opinion. First, the Court asserted that neither the Bill of Rights nor
    the specific practices of states at the time of the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment marks the
    outer limits of substantive due process:
    "[T]he full scope of the liberty guaranteed by the Due Process Clause cannot be found in or
    limited by the precise terms of the specific guarantees elsewhere provided in the Constitution.
    This "liberty' is not a series of isolated points pricked out in terms of the taking of property;
    the freedom of speech, press, and religion; the right to keep and bear arms; the freedom from
    unreasonable searches and seizures; and so on. It is a rational continuum which, broadly
    speaking, includes a freedom from all substantial arbitrary impositions and purposeless
    restraints, ... and which also recognizes, what a reasonable and sensitive judgment must, that
    certain interests require particularly careful scrutiny of the state needs asserted to justify their
    abridgement."
    Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 848-49
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2805
     (quoting Poe, 
    367 U.S. at 543
    , 
    81 S.Ct. at 1777
    (Harlan, J., dissenting on jurisdictional grounds)). The Casey Court continued, quoting from Poe,
    that the adjudication of substantive due process claims has traditionally been, and will continue to be,
    a matter of "reasoned judgment":
    "Due process has not been reduced to any formula; its content cannot be determined by
    reference to any code. The best that can be said is that through the course of this Court's
    decisions it has represented the balance which our Nation, built upon postulates of respect for
    the liberty of the individual, has struck between that liberty and the demands of organized
    society. If the supplying of content to this Constitutional concept has of necessity been a
    rational process, it certainly has not been one where judges have felt free to roam where
    unguided speculation might take them. The balance of which I speak is the balance struck by
    this country, having regard to what history teaches are the traditions from which it developed
    as well as the traditions from which it broke. That tradition is a living thing. A decision of
    this Court which radically departs from it could not long survive, while a decision which
    builds on what has survived is likely to be sound. No formula could serve as a substitute, in
    this area, for judgment and restraint."
    Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 849-50
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2806
    , (quoting Poe, 
    367 U.S. at 542
    , 
    81 S.Ct. at 1776
    (Harlan, J., dissenting on jurisdictional grounds)). The two block quotes selected by the Court from
    Poe are perhaps more telling for what they omitted, however. For between these two long, lofty (and
    transposed) quotes in Poe, lie two telling sentences. After the above-quoted sentence, "No formula
    could serve as a substitute, in this area, for judgment and restraint[,]" Justice Harlan continued:
    It is this outlook which has led the Court continuingly to perceive distinctions in the
    imperative character of Constitutional provisions, since that character must be discerned from
    a particular provision's larger context. And inasmuch as this context is not one of words, but
    of history and purposes, the full scope of the liberty guaranteed by the Due Process Clause
    cannot be found in or limited by the precise terms of the specific guarantees elsewhere
    provided in the Constitution.
    Poe, 
    367 U.S. at 543
    , 
    81 S.Ct. at 1777
     (Harlan, J., dissenting on jurisdictional grounds) (emphasis
    added). This omitted quote highlights Justice Harlan's approach, employed by the Casey Court, of
    using history and tradition in general, not the written Consti tution, to delimit the Fourteenth
    Amendment. See also Griswold, 
    381 U.S. at 501
    , 
    85 S.Ct. at 1691
     (Harlan, J., concurring) (rejecting
    Justice Douglas's restriction of substantive due process to the Bill of Rights and suggesting that
    judicial restraint may be achieved in the Fourteenth Amendment context "only by continual insistence
    upon respect for the teachings of history, solid reco gnition of the basic values that underlie our
    society, and wise appreciation of the great roles that the doctrines of federalism and separation of
    powers have played in establishing and preserving American freedoms.").
    The Court is no longer interpreting the words of the Constitution; after Casey it is
    interpreting history. Words such as "rational continuum," "substantial arbitrary impositions,"
    "purposeless restraints," and "balance ... which our Nation has struck" are code words intended to
    evoke emotional and rhetorical fealty, yet they have no meaning independent of that given them by
    five Justices. The people's Constitution—at least as to unenumerated constitutional rights—has
    become the Court's Constitution. Those principles most conducive to the people's happiness now
    come not from the people, but from Platonic guardians. Justice Black has been proven right, arguing
    in his dissent in Griswold against such an ambitious use of the Due Process Clause: "For myself it
    would be most irksome to be ruled by a bevy of Platonic Guardians, even if I knew how to choose
    them, which I assuredly do not." Griswold, 
    381 U.S. at 526-27
    , 
    85 S.Ct. at 1705
     (Black, J.,
    dissenting) (quoting Learned Hand, The Bill of Rights 70 (1958)).
    As the Supreme Court said in Bowers v. Hardwick, "The Court is most vulnerable and comes
    nearest to illegitimacy when it deals with judge-made constitutional law having little or no cognizable
    roots in the language or design of the Constitution." 
    478 U.S. 186
    , 194, 
    106 S.Ct. 2841
    , 2846, 
    92 L.Ed.2d 140
     (1986). Interestingly, the Court does not even conduct such a historical review in Casey
    to bolster Roe 's "doct rinal footing," nor does it accept or refer to the history cited in Roe as
    compelling. See Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 849-50
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2806
    .
    B
    In part because of the Supreme Court's ambiguity about the scope of substantive due process,
    it is unclear to me that the Court itself still believes that abortion is a "fundamental right" under the
    Fourteenth Amendment. In the narrow context of this concurrence, I will not canvas the Supreme
    Court's entire line of abortion cases. For the purposes of this opinion, it is necessary only to point
    out that the Court's more recent decisions indicate tepid support for Roe v. Wade. If Roe is no longer
    the best interpretation of the Constitution, then our authority to strike the Louisiana statute is very
    tenuous.
    In Planned Parenthood v. Casey, the Court in a fractured joint opinion upheld Roe 's "central
    holding," but did not defend Roe as a sound reading of the Constitution. 
    505 U.S. at 860-61
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2812
    . Instead, it upheld Roe out of concerns for the abstract, nonconstitutional value of
    stare decisis, for the institutional credibility of the Court, and because of the primacy of settled
    expectations about constitutional law. 
    Id.
     ("Within the bounds of normal stare decisis analysis, then,
    and subject to the considerations on which it customarily turns, the stronger argument is for affirming
    Roe 's central holding, with whatever degree of personal reluctance any of us may have....").
    The joint opinion in Casey was correct to consider the force of precedent and the value of
    settled expectations. However, I think that the Court would have been mo re in line with the
    Constitution had it given effect to its conclusion that Roe is wrong. Where the Constitution is the
    source of a court's power, it must interpret the Constitution first and consider institutional credibility
    second. Where, for example, the Court finds that it does not have the constitutional authority to
    strike a state law, its own prior opinions (especially erroneous ones) do not grant that authority, stare
    decisis notwithstanding.
    The Casey Court asserted that it should not overrule cases, especially cases such as Roe,
    lightly. It explained: "a decision to overrule should rest on some special reason over and above the
    belief that a prior case was wrongly decided." Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 864
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2813
    , (citing
    Mitchell v. W.T. Grant Co., 
    416 U.S. 600
    , 636, 
    94 S.Ct. 1895
    , 1914, 
    40 L.Ed.2d 406
     (1974)
    (Stewart, J., dissenting)); Mapp v. Ohio, 
    367 U.S. 643
    , 677, 
    81 S.Ct. 1684
    , 1703, 
    6 L.Ed.2d 1081
    (1961) (Harlan, J., dissenting). But these dissents do not impress upon me why the Supreme Court
    (or any Article III court) should derive the authority to evaluate state laws under its own precedents
    and not under the best reading of the Constitution. What more should the Court need in order to
    overrule a prior case than its studied conclusion, based on the words of the Constitution, that the case
    had been wrongly decided?
    Roe and its progeny, including Bellotti II, have always stood on precarious constitutional
    footing for the reasons I indicated in the last section. After Casey, these cases may not even be
    constitutional law. They might best be considered vestigial precedents propped up only by the judicial
    creation of stare decisis.
    II
    Perhaps because of the difficulties of restricting substantive due process, the Supreme Court
    assumed what can only be called legislative duties in Bellotti v. Baird, 
    443 U.S. 622
    , 
    99 S.Ct. 3035
    ,
    
    61 L.Ed.2d 797
     (1979) ("Bellotti II ").            In Bellotti II, the Supreme Court addressed the
    constitutionality of a Massachusetts statute restricting minors' access to abortion. The Bellotti II
    Court held that minors have the same abortion rights as women who have reached the age of
    majority, and that the Massachusetts's parental consent law unduly burdened minors' exercise of that
    right. Bellotti II, 
    443 U.S. at 647
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at 3050
    . But the Court did not stop there. It continued,
    stating that the Court's interpretation of the word "liberty" in the Fourteenth Amendment required
    that, when states seek to regulate minors' access to abortions,
    every minor must have the opportunity—if she so desires—to go directly to a court without
    first consulting or notifying her parents. If she satisfies the court that she is mature and well
    enough informed to make intelligently the abortion decision on her own, the court must
    authorize her to act without parental consultation or consent. If she fails to satisfy the court
    that she is competent to make this decision independently, she must be permitted to show that
    an abortion nevertheless would be in her best interests. If the court is persuaded that it is, the
    court must authorize the abortion.
    
    Id. at 647-48
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at 3050
    . The Court thus decided that a minor seeking an abortion without
    parental consent must be afforded a prompt hearing in court; must be allowed to have an abortion
    if the court decides she is mature enough to make the decision herself; and must be allowed to
    proceed if the court determines an abortion is in her best interests. 
    Id.
     Regardless of whether that is
    good policy, I am not confident that there is a principled way to reach that conclusion from the word
    "liberty" in the Fourteenth Amendment. By promulgating specific, minimum requirements for state
    parental consent statutes despite a complete vacuum of Constitutional authority, the Court's opinion
    in Bellotti II has the distinct flavor of judicial legislation.
    Bellotti II addresses policy concerns with parental consent statutes, elevates those concerns
    to constitutional heights, then declares Massachusetts's nonconforming po licy decisions to be
    unconstitutional. This line of reasoning amounts to little more than a tautology. By positing a
    fundamental right to abortion and by classifying regulations that jurists deem unwise as an "undue
    burden" on that right, federal judges risk constitutionalizing their policy preferences regarding any
    of the catalogue of substantive Fourteenth Amendment rights.
    As one might expect, such backward induction yields conflicting and seemingly arbitrary
    results. For example, we are instructed in Bellotti II that parental consent requirements are
    unconstitutional, 
    443 U.S. at 649-50
    , 
    99 S.Ct. at 3051
    , yet in Casey we are told that the Constitution
    does not invalidate informed consent requirements, 
    505 U.S. at 887
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2826
    . In Akron I,
    we learn that women have a fundamental right to an abortion that prohibits states from imposing a
    twenty-four hour waiting period, Akron v. Akron Center for Reprod. Health, 
    462 U.S. 416
    , 450, 
    103 S.Ct. 2481
    , 2503, 
    76 L.Ed.2d 687
     (1983), while in Casey we learn that "liberty" does not prohibit
    such a twenty-four hour waiting period, 
    505 U.S. at 885
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2824
     (overruling Akron I ).
    The Court's different opinions about the best way to administer a "fundamental right" to abortion may
    be sensible; on the other hand they may not. But in any event they are not driven by the Constitution.
    As illustrated by Bellotti II, the due process clause has become a blank check, redeemable for
    whatever rights the courts fashion. This is no rule of law, and it is certainly not constitutionalism.
    The Supreme Court's abortion jurisprudence assures us that our panel has authority under the
    Constitution to strike portions of Louisiana's parental consent statute. But because this jurisprudence
    no longer derives its force from the written Constitution, I hesitate to invoke Bellotti II to strike this
    law.
    III
    Aside from serious concerns about substantive due process, I have a pragmatic objection to
    courts substituting their judgments about this type of policy question for the decisions of legislatures.
    As I have asserted before, I think that the modern abortion cases are less about policy than about
    power. Sojourner T. v. Edwards, 
    974 F.2d 27
    , 31 (Garza, J., concurring specially) (quoting Casey,
    
    505 U.S. at 981
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2874
     (Scalia, J., dissenting in part)). The last two sections have
    outlined my belief that the Constitution has vested the power to decide these hotly contested,
    nonconstitutional issues in the state legislatures. See U.S. Const. amend. IX and X. In addition to
    my beliefs about the constitutional authority of Article III courts, I also think that these issues are
    better decided over time by democratic, political institutions. See generally Cass R. Sunstein,
    Foreword: Leaving Things Undecided, 110 Harv. L.Rev. 4 (1996) (arguing for narrow judicial
    decisions in cases involving constitutional and moral uncertainty).
    The Supreme Court's abortion jurisprudence epitomizes a trend toward centralizing and
    constitutionalizing the most controversial issues of public policy. I believe that expanding the
    jurisdiction and power of the courts in order to speed the pace of change is unjustified. Where the
    Constitution does not dictate otherwise, the proper mode of political reform is through enlightened
    debate, political experimentation, and change. We are a pluralistic nation with strong individualist
    ideals. One large component of American civic virtue is public debate over issues. To be sure, this
    requires patience, because self-determination is not a guarantee of correctness the first time or every
    time. State legislatures will occasionally pass "silly" laws. See, e.g., Griswold, 
    381 U.S. at 527
    , 
    85 S.Ct. at 1705
     (Stewart, J., dissenting). Some states may be slower than others in coming to what may
    eventually be a national consensus on an issue. But the ideal is that, through public discourse and
    experimentation, states will reconsider anachronistic laws, adapt, change, and find the public policies
    that work best. Where these issues are not constitutional, it demeans the ideal of democracy for the
    courts to decide these issues for the people, especially under a strained interpretation of the
    Constitution.
    Some have justified an ambitious judicial role in abortion cases by suggesting that the
    Supreme Court has a special calling to unite the nation in high-stakes cases in which people
    passionately disagree. In Casey, the Court stated that such cases carry a special "dimension" that
    places those opinions in a class by themselves:
    Where, in the performance of its judicial duties, the Court decides a case in such a way as to
    resolve the sort of intensely divisive controversy reflected in Roe and those rare, comparable
    cases, its decision has a dimension that the resolution of the normal case does not carry. It
    is the dimension present whenever the Court's interpretation of the Constitution calls the
    contending sides of a nat ional controversy to end their national division by accepting a
    common mandate rooted in the Constitution.
    Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 866-67
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2815
    . The Court suggested that the two cases exemplifying
    this call to a common mandate were Roe v. Wade and Brown v. Board of Education. But as Justice
    Scalia pointed out in his Casey dissent, Roe did not settle the political issue of legalized abortion. No
    one accepted a common mandate in that case. In retrospect, it is clear that the Suprem e Court's
    intervention in the debate clouded the issues, inflaming those who believe that there is no
    constitutional right to abortion and forcing advocates of legalized abortion to defend abortion "rights"
    under Roe. Today we see that even many of those who believe that abortion should be legal do not
    support Roe v. Wade as faithful interpretation of the Constitution. See Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 860-61
    ,
    
    112 S.Ct. at 2812
     (joint opinion reluctantly upholding Roe on stare decisis grounds); see also Ruth
    Bader Ginsburg, Some Thoughts on Autonomy and Equality in Relation to Roe v. Wade, 63 N.C.
    L.Rev. 375, 385-86 (1985) (criticizing the "[h]eavy handed judicial intervention" of the Roe court and
    suggesting an alternative starting point for analysis in abortion cases).
    Roe did not mark the end of t he debate or the acceptance of a common mandate, but the
    beginning of a bitter national exegesis. In this respect, Roe is more like Plessy v. Ferguson, 
    163 U.S. 537
    , 
    16 S.Ct. 1138
    , 
    41 L.Ed. 256
     (1896), than Brown v. Board of Education, 
    347 U.S. 483
    , 
    74 S.Ct. 686
    , 
    98 L.Ed. 873
     (1954) (Brown I ). Plessy, like Roe, represented an attempt to read into the
    Constitution one view of history and social policy neither explicit nor fairly implied from the
    Constitutional text. "Separate but equal" may have been an attempt to solve a contentious issue of
    the 1890s, but it was not constitutional interpretation. Plessy did not unite the nation behind the idea
    that segregation was consistent with the Civil War Amendments. As in its abortion cases, the Court
    occasionally upheld the "central holding" of Plessy on stare decisis grounds, before finally overruling
    it in Brown I, 
    347 U.S. at 494-95
    , 
    74 S.Ct. at 691-92
    . I suggest this comparison not necessarily to
    draw any moral parallel between slavery and abortion, but rather to point out that the Court's
    insertion of itself as the final arbiter of the abortion debate is unlikely to prove more successful than
    its attempt in Plessy.
    Plessy is not the only time our nation has faced a conflict between faithful interpretation and
    stare decisis. We learned the same lesson about ambitious judicial intervention again in the early
    twentieth century, even in the same substantive due process context, in the line of cases following
    Lochner v. New York, 
    198 U.S. 45
    , 
    25 S.Ct. 539
    , 
    49 L.Ed. 937
     (1905). In Lochner and its progeny,
    the Court established and upheld on stare decisis grounds the laissez-faire notion that state regulation
    of worker health and welfare violated the substantive due process rights of employers in liberty of
    contract. See, e.g., Adkins v. Children's Hospital of District of Columbia, 
    261 U.S. 525
    , 
    43 S.Ct. 394
    , 
    67 L.Ed. 785
     (1923). The Court later overruled Adkins and signaled the end of the Lochner era
    in West Coast Hotel Co. v. Parrish, 
    300 U.S. 379
    , 
    57 S.Ct. 578
    , 
    81 L.Ed. 703
     (1937), holding that
    the Due Process Clause did not contain implicit protections of absolute liberty of contract.
    In fact, the very first substantive due process case tel ls the same story. In Dred Scott v.
    Sanford, 60 U.S. (How.) 393, 450, 
    15 L.Ed. 691
     (1856), the Court held, among other things, that
    a slave owner did not lose his property interest in the slave when he traveled with the slave to a free
    state. In what could be described as the beginning of substantive due process, the Court held that a
    section of the Missouri Compromise, which would have recognized such slaves as free, was
    unconstitutional. The Court held that such governmental intrusion on private property rights,
    regardless of procedural safeguards, "could hardly be dignified with the name of due process of law."
    
    Id.
     This was the first time since Marbury v. Madison that the Court used the power of judicial review,
    and the first time ever t hat the Court invalidated a statute under judicial review. That a notion as
    controversial as substantive due process sprang from such a cataclysmic opinion is revealing.
    Dred Scott was fashioned as an opinion to put an end to a bitter dispute in America. It took
    one of the most contentious and personal of political issues out of the national debate. But instead
    of resolving controversies, Dred Scott tore the nation apart. Although Roe and its progeny have not
    resulted in a civil war, the peace over abortion since 1973 has been anything but civil. The last twenty
    years have seen political protest over the Court's abortion jurisprudence unmatched by any other
    political issue of our day. Protest marches, clinic bombings, and fatal shootings have punctuated the
    debate. Putting the lid on this pot has caused it to boil over. Regular debate, lobbying, and
    legislation at the state level, as contemplated by the Constitution, may diffuse political pressure,
    relieve tensions, and provide for nuanced answers to hard questions about abortion. Removing such
    issues from the people prevents their vetting at the local level and requires the political pressure to
    be released outside the bounds of civil debate.
    In Dred Scott, Plessy, and Lochner, the Court made things worse by inserting itself into, and
    preempting, the national debate. Although at one time these cases were also defensible on stare
    decisis grounds, they are not celebrated cases in our history. By contrast, the cases in which the
    Court overruled such precedents, such as Brown I and West Coast Hotel, are celebrated as
    constitutional moments. It is of course easier to discern between the two types of cases in retrospect.
    I think that enough history has passed for us confidently to conclude that Roe belongs in the former
    category, cases in which the Court intervened to settle a national debate by way of expansive
    constitutional interpretation. It remains for our Supreme Court to write the analog to West Coast
    Hotel extricating itself from the substantive due process morass of abortion cases and returning the
    debate to the people.
    Deliberation about this subject, although heated, is healthy. As a nation, we have not reached
    a consensus about when life begins; we have not finally determined the proper interplay between a
    mother's liberty, the interests of an unborn child, and the state's interests in protecting life. At an
    ontological level, we the people have yet to decide whether person defines life or life defines person.
    As technology allows fetal independence at an earlier and earlier age, our understanding of these
    questions will not remain static. The Constitution, in all its prescience, does not answer these
    questions. Such ontic questions are quintessentially the right of the people to decide. In abortion
    cases, law presupposes a theory of ethics and morality, which in turn presupposes deeply personal
    ideas about being and existence. Our answers to such questions as when life begins define our ethical
    beliefs, and these ethical beliefs should determine how we govern ourselves. It is a serious mistake
    to try to reverse this order, to make our law determine how we decide these fundamental, personal,
    ontic issues. Abortion in this context is less a question about constitutional law, and more about who
    we are as a people. I submit that this is a decision the Supreme Court cannot make. Liberty is not
    coextensive with license; it therefore must have limits. Those limits may be imposed only by the
    people, either in their Constitution or through their laws, not legislated by the courts. Taking these
    issues out of the public discourse threatens to foment hostility, stifle the search for answers, distance
    people from their Constitution, and undermine the credibility of that document.
    IV
    Bellotti II represents a type of legislating that is better left to Congress or the states. In many
    cases, the courts must fill in gaps in statutes, account for unforeseen circumstances, or decide difficult
    issues that legislators avoid. However, in this instance, Louisiana actually did exercise its legislative
    powers; it debated and struggled and made tough choices. Now we are nullifying Louisiana's choice,
    not under the Constitution, but under Roe 's continuing authority based on stare decisis.
    Therefore it is not impertinence that makes me question the Supreme Court's abortion
    jurisprudence, but institutional modesty.        I am uncomfortable invoking the authority of the
    Constitution to invalidate this statute, especially under such an ambiguous mandate from the
    Constitution. Although the Court said in Bellotti II that Roe and the Fourteenth Amendment set
    minimum standards for parental consent statutes, it is unclear that the post-Casey Supreme Court still
    believes that the Constitution demands this outcome. Overturning Louisiana's legislature on such thin
    authority runs dangerously close to anticonstitutional hubris. As Abraham Lincoln said of Dred
    Scott:
    The candid citizen must confess that if the policy of the government, upon vital questions
    affecting the whole people, is to be irrevocably fixed by decisions of the Supreme Court, the
    instant they are made, in ordinary litigation between parties in personal actions, the people
    will have ceased to be their own rulers, having, to that extent, practically resigned the
    government into the hands of that eminent tribunal.
    Abraham Lincoln, First Inaugural Address—Final Text (Mar. 4, 1861), in 4 The Collected Works
    of Abraham Lincoln 262, 268 (Roy P. Basler ed., 1953) (cited in Casey, 
    505 U.S. at 996
    , 
    112 S.Ct. at 2882
     (Scalia, J., dissenting in part)).
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 95-31178

Citation Numbers: 109 F.3d 1096

Judges: Emilio, Garza, Politz, Stewart

Filed Date: 4/14/1997

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 8/1/2023

Authorities (47)

robert-p-casey-allan-s-noonan-ernest-d-preate-jr-v-planned-parenthood , 14 F.3d 848 ( 1994 )

TLI, Inc. v. United States , 100 F.3d 424 ( 1996 )

Peaches Entertainment Corp. v. Entertainment Repertoire ... , 62 F.3d 690 ( 1995 )

Federal Deposit Insurance Corporation, Receiver of Texas ... , 4 F.3d 1303 ( 1993 )

Helen B. Barnes, M.D. v. The State of Mississippi , 992 F.2d 1335 ( 1993 )

North Alamo Water Supply Corporation v. City of San Juan, ... , 90 F.3d 910 ( 1996 )

Lochner v. New York , 25 S. Ct. 539 ( 1905 )

Singleton Et Ux. v. Commissioner of Internal Revenue , 439 U.S. 940 ( 1978 )

United States v. Salerno , 107 S. Ct. 2095 ( 1987 )

compassion-in-dying-a-washington-nonprofit-corporation-jane-roe-john-doe , 79 F.3d 790 ( 1996 )

Meyer v. Nebraska , 43 S. Ct. 625 ( 1923 )

Rathborne Lumber & Supply Co. v. Falgout , 218 La. 629 ( 1950 )

planned-parenthood-sioux-falls-clinic-buck-j-williams-md-and-womens , 63 F.3d 1452 ( 1995 )

Causeway Medical Suite v. Ieyoub , 905 F. Supp. 360 ( 1995 )

Adkins v. Children's Hospital of Columbia , 43 S. Ct. 394 ( 1923 )

Mugler v. Kansas , 8 S. Ct. 273 ( 1887 )

Carey v. Population Services International , 97 S. Ct. 2010 ( 1977 )

Daniels v. Williams , 106 S. Ct. 662 ( 1986 )

Michael H. v. Gerald D. , 109 S. Ct. 2333 ( 1989 )

City of Akron v. Akron Center for Reproductive Health, Inc. , 103 S. Ct. 2481 ( 1983 )

View All Authorities »