Robert Winter, Jr. v. Steven Wolnitzek , 834 F.3d 681 ( 2016 )


Menu:
  •                          RECOMMENDED FOR FULL-TEXT PUBLICATION
    Pursuant to Sixth Circuit I.O.P. 32.1(b)
    File Name: 16a0206p.06
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
    _________________
    ROBERT A. WINTER, JR.,                              ┐
    Plaintiff-Appellee/Cross-Appellant, │
    │
    │
    CAMERON A. BLAU; ALLISON JONES,                     │
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841
    Intervening Plaintiffs-Appellees/Cross-Appellants, │>
    │
    v.                                             │
    │
    │
    STEVEN D. WOLNITZEK; JANET L. STUMBO; EDDY            │
    COLEMAN; DAVID PAUL BOWLES; DIANE E.                  │
    LOGSDON; JOYCE KING JENNINGS; JIMMY SHAFFER,          │
    Defendants-Appellants/Cross-Appellees.      │
    ┘
    Appeal from the United States District Court
    for the Eastern District of Kentucky at Covington.
    No. 2:14-cv-00119—Amul R. Thapar, District Judge.
    Argued: August 4, 2016
    Decided and Filed: August 24, 2016
    Before: COLE, Chief Judge; SUTTON and COOK, Circuit Judges.
    _________________
    COUNSEL
    ARGUED: Jeffrey C. Mando, ADAMS, STEPNER, WOLTERMANN & DUSING, PLLC,
    Covington, Kentucky, for Appellants/Cross-Appellees. Mark R. Overstreet, STITES &
    HARBISON, PLLC, Frankfort, Kentucky, for Appellants/Cross-Appellees as to all claims except
    those asserted by Judge Jones. Christopher Wiest, CHRIS WIEST, AAL, PLLC, Crestview
    Hills, Kentucky, for Appellees/Cross-Appellants. ON BRIEF: Jeffrey C. Mando, ADAMS,
    STEPNER, WOLTERMANN & DUSING, PLLC, Covington, Kentucky, for Appellants/Cross-
    Appellees. Mark R. Overstreet, STITES & HARBISON, PLLC, Frankfort, Kentucky, Bethany
    A. Breetz, STITES & HARBISON, PLLC, Louisville, Kentucky, for Appellants/Cross-
    Appellees as to all claims except those asserted by Judge Jones. Christopher Wiest, CHRIS
    1
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841             Winter, et al. v. Wolnitzek, et al.               Page 2
    WIEST, AAL, PLLC, Crestview Hills, Kentucky, Jack S. Gatlin, GATLIN VOELKER, PLLC,
    Ft. Mitchell, Kentucky, for Appellees/Cross-Appellants.
    _________________
    OPINION
    _________________
    SUTTON, Circuit Judge. One sitting judge and two aspiring judges from Kentucky wish
    to exercise their free-speech rights during this and future judicial elections. They claim that the
    Commonwealth’s Code of Judicial Conduct stands in the way. They are not the first judges to
    bring this kind of complaint. A growing line of cases grapples with the States’ authority to
    create a system of judicial elections on the one hand and regulate judicial campaign speech on
    the other. See Williams-Yulee v. Fla. Bar, 
    135 S. Ct. 1656
     (2015); Republican Party of Minn. v.
    White, 
    536 U.S. 765
     (2002); Carey v. Wolnitzek, 
    614 F.3d 189
     (6th Cir. 2010). At issue today
    are several clauses in Kentucky’s judicial canons—from prohibitions on “campaign[ing] as a
    member of a political organization,” to “endors[ing] . . . a candidate for public office,” to
    “mak[ing] a contribution to a political organization,” to making any “commitments” with respect
    to “cases, controversies, or issues” likely to come before the court, to making “false” or
    “misleading” statements. The district court issued a thorough and thoughtful opinion, making
    our job easier. It struck some of these provisions and upheld others. We agree with almost all of
    its reasoning and affirm almost all of its judgment.
    I.
    Robert Winter’s campaign literature identified him as a “lifelong Republican” and
    informed voters that his opponents were registered Democrats. R. 29-1 at 2. The Judicial
    Conduct Commission, which enforces the Code, sent him a “probable cause” letter, stating that
    his mailers may have violated the canon prohibiting “campaign[ing] as a member of a political
    organization.” Rules of Supreme Court of Kentucky 4.300, Canon 5(A)(1)(a); id. at 4.170(1)
    (pre-2016 version); see R. 1-9 at 1.
    Incumbent Allison Jones asked voters to “re-elect” her, even though she was initially
    appointed to her seat, and she promised to “work with the legislative and executive branches to
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841             Winter, et al. v. Wolnitzek, et al.                Page 3
    ensure that the law provides stiff penalties for heroin dealers and that the judiciary has the tools
    necessary to reduce recidivism among heroin addicts that are arrested and sentenced.” R. 80 at
    4, 8. Her “re-elect” statement, the Commission wrote in its probable cause letter, potentially
    violated the canon prohibiting “false and misleading statements.” Canon 5(B)(1)(c). And her
    “stiff penalties” comment potentially constituted an impermissible “commitment” on an issue
    likely to come before her court. Canon 5(B)(1)(c).
    Cameron Blau, an aspiring judge, wants to give speeches supporting the Republican
    Party, to hold Republican fundraisers, to seek and receive endorsements from Republican
    candidates, and to donate to candidates and to the party. The Code bans all of that, which left
    Blau “fear[ful] [to] engag[e]” in any of it due to the risk of public reprimand, disbarment from
    the practice of law, or eventual suspension without pay and removal from office. R. 50 at 6; see
    Rules of Supreme Court of Kentucky 4.020(1)(b).
    Winter filed this lawsuit, after which Jones and Blau intervened, all three to the end of
    stopping the Commission (in truth, its members) from enforcing these canons against them.
    Both sides moved for summary judgment. Before ruling on the motions, the district court
    certified questions about the meaning of three of the canons to the Kentucky Supreme Court.
    The Court answered in February 2016. Winter v. Wolnitzek, 
    482 S.W.3d 768
     (Ky. 2016). The
    district court issued a 45-page opinion granting in part the plaintiffs’ request to enjoin the
    challenged canons and issuing a final judgment to that effect. Each side appealed and each side
    sought expedited resolution of the case.
    II.
    Is there an Article III case or controversy? Yes, as a general matter. All three plaintiffs
    plan to run in the next elections for which they are eligible, either 2016 or 2018. See Carey,
    
    614 F.3d at 197
    . All three intend to engage in speech arguably proscribed by the canons. And
    the Commission plans to enforce the canons against them.
    Even so, the Commonwealth contests Jones’ standing on the ground that she lacks a
    credible threat of enforcement for her “stiff penalties for heroin dealers” comment. The question
    is whether Jones faces a “credible threat of enforcement” for engaging in that speech. Susan B.
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841              Winter, et al. v. Wolnitzek, et al.                Page 4
    Anthony List v. Driehaus, 
    134 S. Ct. 2334
    , 2342, 2346 (2014). The answer turns on whether the
    Commission’s letter carried with it a valid threat of enforcement. It did. The letter informed her
    that “a complaint ha[d] been filed against [her]” and requested that she respond to the allegations
    in writing. R. 72-2 at 7. The Commission issued the letter only after deciding “there is probable
    cause for action.” Rules of Supreme Court of Kentucky 4.170(1) (pre-2016 version). A state
    agency’s probable cause finding provides a sufficient threat of enforcement to confer First
    Amendment preenforcement standing. See, e.g., Driehaus, 
    134 S. Ct. at 2345
    ; Platt v. Bd. of
    Comm’rs on Grievances & Discipline, 
    769 F.3d 447
    , 452 (6th Cir. 2014).
    The State would have us hold that Jones’ as-applied challenge is not ripe, even though
    her facial challenge is ripe. But if there is any difference between the standing requirements for
    as-applied and facial challenges, it is because raising a narrow as-applied challenge is easier, not
    harder, than raising a facial challenge.       Nor can there be standing without ripeness in
    preenforcement challenges.        The line between Article III standing and ripeness in
    preenforcement First Amendment challenges has evaporated. Driehaus, 
    134 S. Ct. at
    2346–47.
    “The doctrines of standing and ripeness ‘originate’ from the same Article III limitation” and thus
    are analyzed together in challenges of this sort. 
    Id.
     at 2341 n.5; see, e.g., Platt, 769 F.3d at 451;
    Kiser v. Reitz, 
    765 F.3d 601
    , 606–07 (6th Cir. 2014). Whether the plaintiffs have standing and
    whether their claims are ripe come to the same question: Have they established a credible threat
    of enforcement? The answer is yes. And the answer does not differ in this instance for as-
    applied and facial challenges.
    Nor do any practical obstacles keep us from considering the plaintiffs’ as-applied
    challenges. The parties have described their conduct with plenty of detail. The Kentucky
    Supreme Court has told us that the canons proscribe their speech. And the Commission has said
    that it plans to enforce the canons against the plaintiffs. That means the plaintiffs have “laid the
    foundation” for their as-applied challenges, Ctr. for Individual Freedom v. Madigan, 
    697 F.3d 464
    , 475–76 (7th Cir. 2012), permitting us to decide them now, see, e.g., Holder v.
    Humanitarian Law Project, 
    561 U.S. 1
    , 12, 15 (2010); Russell v. Lundergan-Grimes, 
    784 F.3d 1037
    , 1049–50 (6th Cir. 2015).
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841             Winter, et al. v. Wolnitzek, et al.                 Page 5
    If the plaintiffs have standing to raise these challenges and if they are ripe for resolution,
    the Commission maintains, that must be because the Commission has initiated formal
    proceedings against them. And if that is true, it adds, Younger abstention bars us from hearing
    the case. Younger v. Harris, 
    401 U.S. 37
     (1971). But a finding of probable cause does not
    necessarily mean a formal proceeding exists. In the absence of an ongoing enforcement action,
    Younger has no role to play, leaving us with authority, indeed an obligation, to resolve the case.
    See Sprint Commc’ns, Inc. v. Jacobs, 
    134 S. Ct. 584
    , 590–91 (2013).
    III.
    The Kentucky Constitution gives the citizens of the Commonwealth the right to vote for
    their judges in nonpartisan elections. Ky. Const. § 117. The First (and Fourteenth) Amendment
    to the United States Constitution gives candidates for elective office, whether executive,
    legislative, or judicial, freedom on the campaign trail to explain why they are the superior
    candidate for the job. White, 
    536 U.S. at
    781–82, 787–88. Strict scrutiny as a result applies to
    any State’s efforts to regulate the campaign speech of sitting or aspiring judges. Williams-Yulee,
    
    135 S. Ct. at 1665
    .
    The plaintiffs challenge eight features of the Commonwealth’s Code of Judicial Conduct.
    (1) Campaigning clause. “Except as permitted by law,” Canon 5(A)(1)(a) says, “a judge
    or a candidate for election to judicial office shall not[] campaign as a member of a political
    organization.” The Kentucky Supreme Court in its certification decision held that this clause
    prohibits candidates from “portray[ing] themselves, either directly or by implication, as the
    official nominee of a political party.” Winter, 482 S.W.3d at 777. Interpreted that way, the
    district court held, the canon is vague and unconstitutionally overbroad. We agree.
    The problem with this canon is that it’s unclear when candidates go from permissibly
    affiliating with a party to illegally implying that they are the nominee of a party. On the one
    hand, the First Amendment establishes that a State may not prevent judicial candidates from
    publicly taking a stance on “matters of current public importance.” White, 
    536 U.S. at
    781–82
    (quoting Wood v. Georgia, 
    370 U.S. 375
    , 395 (1962)). Saying “I am a Republican” is shorthand
    for just that, which means candidates have a constitutional right to portray themselves as a
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841             Winter, et al. v. Wolnitzek, et al.               Page 6
    member of a political party. Carey, 
    614 F.3d at
    201–02. On the other hand, Kentucky has a
    right to prevent candidates from identifying themselves as the nominee of a political party for a
    judicial seat. That’s because Kentucky runs its judicial elections on a nonpartisan basis. There is
    no Democratic or Republican nominee for each seat because political parties don’t officially
    endorse Kentucky judicial candidates, and indeed the two candidates vying in a general election
    for the same seat could each support the same party.
    In its certification decision, the Kentucky Supreme Court construed the canon to prohibit
    “suggesting to the voters that the candidate is the endorsed nominee of a political party.” Winter,
    482 S.W.3d at 776 (emphasis in original). A candidate for judicial office, it explained, may say
    that he is “a Republican” or “a Democrat,” or “the only Republican” or “the only Democrat,”
    because those phrases don’t imply an endorsement. Id. Those claims merely portray a candidate
    as a member of a party. So far so good. But claiming to be “the Liberal Democrat” or “the
    Conservative Republican,” it added, implies an endorsement—due to the definite article—and
    therefore violates the canon. Id. at 776–77.
    This last point makes the canon, as construed by Kentucky’s highest court, too vague to
    tightly regulate the problem and too vague to avoid scaring off permissible electoral speech. It’s
    unclear when a candidate crosses the line from exercising his constitutional right to portray
    himself as a member of a political party, Carey, 
    614 F.3d at
    201–02, to impermissibly implying
    the endorsement of that party. A few examples illustrate the uncertainty. Could a candidate
    truthfully claim to have “the endorsement of leaders of the Republican Party?” What if a
    candidate says, quite accurately, that “the Republicans support my campaign?” We are not sure
    whether this would violate Kentucky law, making us doubt whether judicial candidates would
    know either.    The Kentucky Supreme Court said that claiming to be “the Conservative
    Republican” would violate the canon by implying an endorsement; it thought the use of “the”
    was the key, while the word “conservative” was mere “surplusage.” See Winter, 482 S.W.3d at
    776.   But how about claiming to be “the moderate Republican candidate” or “the most
    experienced conservative Republican candidate?” After reading those phrases, some might infer
    an endorsement, but others might infer that there are other Republicans in the race. It’s hard to
    know when a candidate has portrayed himself as an official nominee “by implication.” Id. at
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841                 Winter, et al. v. Wolnitzek, et al.           Page 7
    777.    Because the canon (as interpreted by the Kentucky Supreme Court) gives judicial
    candidates little confidence about when they exercise their right to affiliate with a party or when
    they violate the law, the campaigning clause is vague and unconstitutionally overbroad. The
    district court rightly struck it in its entirety.
    (2) Speeches clause.        Suffering from a related problem is the infelicitously named
    speeches clause, which bans judicial candidates from “mak[ing] speeches for or against a
    political organization or candidate.” Canon 5A(1)(c). A candidate has a free-speech right to say
    in a campaign speech that she is “a Republican,” Carey, 
    614 F.3d at 202
    , and yet this clause by
    its terms bars a speech in which she says she is “for the Republican party.” Because this clause
    does too much in one sense and too little in another, it does not narrowly address the problem at
    hand and thus is facially invalid.
    In one sense, the speeches clause “does too little to advance the State’s interest in
    impartiality and the avoidance of partisan influence.” Carey, 
    614 F.3d at 202
    . Kentucky allows
    “a judicial candidate [to] identify himself to the public as a member of a political party” in many
    ways. Winter, 482 S.W.3d at 775–76. The candidate may tell any audience, no matter how big,
    that he is a Republican or a Democrat. See Canon 5A(1)(c), Cmt. He may give a speech for any
    political interest group, from the National Rifle Association to Planned Parenthood. And he may
    email, tweet, write, or say in an interview that he is for a political party. Banning him from
    giving a speech to the same effect creates serious under-inclusivity problems.
    In another sense, the clause “suppresses too much speech to advance the government’s
    interest.” Carey, 
    614 F.3d at 201
    . By banning speech functionally identical to the speech
    permitted by Carey—that he supports a particular party, 
    id.
     at 201–02—the clause suffers from
    debilitating over-inclusivity problems. Both problems establish a fit defect and preclude the
    canon from running the gauntlet of strict scrutiny.
    True, other circuits have upheld speeches clauses in other States’ judicial codes. But they
    did so while reviewing more narrowly written canons. See Wolfson v. Concannon, 
    811 F.3d 1176
    , 1179 n.2 (9th Cir. 2016) (en banc) (prohibiting candidates from making “speeches on
    behalf of a political organization” (emphasis added)); Bauer v. Shepard, 
    620 F.3d 704
    , 711 (7th
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841               Winter, et al. v. Wolnitzek, et al.              Page 8
    Cir. 2010) (same).      The prohibitions at issue did not “prevent judicial candidates from
    announcing their views on disputed legal and political subjects.” Wolfson, 811 F.3d at 1185.
    This one does. It is unconstitutional.
    (3) Contributions clause. This clause prohibits judicial candidates from “mak[ing] a
    contribution to a political organization or candidate.” Canon 5(A)(1)(d). As the plaintiffs see it,
    the provision suffers from a patent defect: If a candidate may declare “the party [he] support[s],”
    Carey, 
    614 F.3d at 201
    , it also must be the case that he can “put his money where his mouth is”
    by contributing to that party, R. 124 at 30. It is not that easy.
    There is a distinction between speech-limiting regulations that limit all judges (elected or
    not) and those that hamstring judges in their efforts to run for election. For some time now,
    courts have recognized that a state “cannot have it both ways. If it wants to elect its judges, it
    cannot deprive its citizens of a full and robust election debate.” Geary v. Renne, 
    911 F.2d 280
    ,
    294 (9th Cir. 1990) (en banc) (Reinhardt, J., concurring), vacated on other grounds, 
    501 U.S. 312
     (1991). Kentucky, like any State, is free to staff its judiciary with elected judges. But as
    Justice Scalia pointed out in White, “the First Amendment does not permit it to achieve its goal
    by leaving the principle of elections in place while preventing candidates from discussing what
    the elections are about.” 
    536 U.S. at 788
    . The campaigning and speeches clauses, invalidated
    above, restrict what judicial candidates may say in their own campaigns and thus violate the First
    Amendment. The lesson is straightforward: A State may not hold judicial elections, then
    prevent candidates from explaining what makes them qualified for that office.
    But there is no having-it-both-ways problem with a contributions limit like this one.
    A contribution to a political organization or a candidate in a different campaign “is less a judge’s
    communication about his qualifications and beliefs than an effort to affect a separate political
    campaign, or even more problematically, assume a role as political powerbroker.” Siefert v.
    Alexander, 
    608 F.3d 974
    , 984 (7th Cir. 2010).            While “[j]udicial candidates have a First
    Amendment right to speak in support of their campaigns,” Williams-Yulee, 
    135 S. Ct. at 1673
    ,
    they do not have an unlimited right to contribute money to someone else’s campaign. Otherwise,
    the Code of Conduct for United States Judges—which bans judges from “mak[ing] a
    contribution to a political organization or candidate,” see Canon 5(A)(3)—is unconstitutional.
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841              Winter, et al. v. Wolnitzek, et al.                 Page 9
    That would come as a surprise. The “distance between” a contribution to someone else’s
    campaign “and speech about a judge’s own campaign justifies a more deferential approach to
    government prohibition” of contributions. Siefert, 
    608 F.3d at 984
    .
    Financial contributions, we realize, amount to speech. See Buckley v. Valeo, 
    424 U.S. 1
    ,
    17–18 (1976). But the alignment between speech and money makes a difference only with
    respect to Janus-faced regulations that tell judicial candidates to run for office but deny them the
    tools for doing so. That is not what this regulation does. A contribution of time, money, or
    reputation to a political organization or a candidate in a separate election, whether judicial or not,
    differs in kind and degree from a judicial candidate contributing the same to his own campaign.
    There is “a dividing line between” the speeches clause, “which impermissibly bars protected
    speech about the judge’s own campaign,” and the contributions clause, “which addresses a
    judge’s entry into the political arena on behalf of his partisan comrades.” Siefert, 
    608 F.3d at 984
    .   Kentucky, for this reason, allows judicial candidates to purchase tickets to political
    gatherings only if “he or she doesn’t create the impression that the purchase is not for the
    advancement of the judge or candidate but is solely a contribution to another candidate or
    political organization, which is prohibited.” Canon 5(A)(2), Cmt. The contributions clause
    narrowly serves the Commonwealth’s compelling interest in preventing the appearance that
    judicial candidates are no different from other elected officials when it comes to quid pro quo
    politics. It is constitutional.
    (4) Endorsements clause. The endorsements clause is of a piece. It prohibits judicial
    candidates from “publicly endors[ing] or oppos[ing] a candidate for public office.” Canon
    5(A)(1)(c). And it too has nothing to do with the push-me-pull-me problem—being forced to run
    for office while being denied the means of doing so—that infects most unconstitutional
    regulations of speech in this area. By focusing on another candidate for office, a third party
    other than the judicial candidate himself, this clause narrowly addresses Kentucky’s compelling
    interest in keeping its judges above the partisan fray of trading political favors.
    Endorsements differ from a candidate’s own expressions of agreement with a political
    party’s platform or another candidate’s views. When a judicial candidate endorses a particular
    candidate, he “support[s] or aid[s]” the other candidate, rather than supporting himself, “by or as
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841              Winter, et al. v. Wolnitzek, et al.                  Page 10
    if by signed statement.” Webster’s Third New International Dictionary 749 (3d. ed. 2002).
    Voters understand the difference between a speech expressing, say, the judicial candidate’s
    progressive vision for the Commonwealth and one, say, formally endorsing the Democratic
    nominee for Attorney General of Kentucky or President of the United States. The former helps
    the candidate; the latter helps the candidates for Attorney General and President. A ban on the
    former “impermissibly bars protected speech about the judge’s own campaign.”                   Siefert,
    
    608 F.3d at 984
    . But a ban on the latter permissibly “addresses a judge’s entry into the political
    arena on behalf of his partisan comrades.” 
    Id.
    Because endorsements often are “exchanged between political actors on a quid pro quo
    basis,” 
    id.,
     the endorsements clause is narrowly tailored to Kentucky’s compelling interest in
    preventing judges from becoming (or being perceived as becoming) part of partisan political
    machines. As long as Kentucky “does not regulate speech with regard to any underlying issues,”
    it may target “the act of endorsement itself, which . . . is a direct expression of bias in favor of or
    against potential parties to a case, or at the very least, damages the appearance of impartiality.”
    Wersal v. Sexton, 
    674 F.3d 1010
    , 1026 (8th Cir. 2012). A ban on such endorsements also guards
    against the risk that, once a judge is elected, he will not be able to (and he will not be perceived
    as being able to) referee disputes involving elected officials he did or did not endorse.
    The clause does not suffer from the too-much and too-little coverage problems that the
    speeches and contributions clauses do. The plaintiffs have not identified any protected speech
    banned by the endorsements clause that makes it over-inclusive. It does not prohibit speech in
    opposition to one’s own opponent any more than it prohibits “endorsing” oneself. Yet it does
    ban the endorsement of a candidate in a different race, an act that, like the personal solicitations
    in Williams-Yulee, signals the judicial candidate’s “active[] engage[ment] in political
    campaigns.” Wolfson, 811 F.3d at 1184 (upholding Arizona’s endorsement clause).
    While the clause is narrowly drawn, it is not perfectly drawn. It has a modest under-
    inclusivity problem because, as the plaintiffs point out, and the Commentary to Canon 5
    confirms, a judicial candidate may “privately express[] his or her views on judicial candidates or
    other candidates for public office.” True enough. But private expressions of approval or
    disapproval create far fewer quid pro quo appearance problems than the candidate formally
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841              Winter, et al. v. Wolnitzek, et al.               Page 11
    putting his name and reputation behind another. The endorsements clause “aims squarely at the
    conduct most likely to undermine” non-partisanship in judicial elections and is thus narrowly
    tailored to that interest. Williams-Yulee, 
    135 S. Ct. at 1668
    .
    (5) Acting as a leader clause. Kentucky prohibits a judge from “act[ing] as a leader or
    hold[ing] any office in a political organization.” Canon 5(A)(1)(b). This clause does all that the
    First Amendment asks of it when it comes to Blau’s facial challenge. The Commonwealth
    targets an admirable goal (preserving public confidence in its judges, Williams-Yulee, 
    135 S. Ct. at 1666
    ) and uses permissible means in doing so (“diminishing reliance on political parties in
    judicial selection,” Carey, 
    614 F.3d at 201
    ). A judge who heads up a political party entrenches,
    rather than diminishes, political parties in judicial selection. Whether the candidate wishes to act
    as a leader of a political organization or hold office in a political organization, she cannot do so
    without directly undermining Kentucky’s legitimate policy choice to hold nonpartisan elections
    for judges.
    The difficulty comes in resolving Blau’s as-applied challenge to the clause.             The
    Kentucky Supreme Court read this clause broadly, interpreting it to include not just leading a
    political party or holding a formal office but also “hosting a political event.” Winter, 482 S.W.3d
    at 778. And that, it turns out, is one of the things Blau wants to do. R. 50 at 5, 12–13. There are
    many types of political events, and it’s not clear how many this canon covers.
    Happily for us, Blau identifies the one he wants to host: a “fundraiser[].” Second Br. 52.
    And the State, it seems to us, can comfortably ban that kind of event. Williams-Yulee tells us the
    rule when it comes to fundraising for oneself. Judicial candidates do not have a constitutional
    right to “supplicate campaign donors.” 
    135 S. Ct. at 1666
    . And fundraising for others is
    controlled by our reasoning on the endorsements clause. As with endorsements, fundraisers
    “may be exchanged between political actors on a quid pro quo basis” and are thus less about a
    judge’s “qualifications and beliefs than [they are] an effort to affect a separate political
    campaign, or even more problematically, assume a role as political powerbroker.” Seifert,
    
    608 F.3d at 984
    . Both types of fundraisers bring “a judge’s impartiality . . . into question” and
    can cause “the public [to] lose faith” in the promise of neutral and apolitical judging. Wolfson,
    811 F.3d at 1184; see also Bauer, 
    620 F.3d at
    712–13. Kentucky’s ban on judges and judicial
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841              Winter, et al. v. Wolnitzek, et al.                 Page 12
    candidates hosting political fundraisers, together with its ban on their holding a political office or
    leading a political party, does not impermissibly infringe Blau’s free-speech rights.
    (6) False statements clause. This clause prohibits a judge or judicial candidate from
    “knowingly” or “with reckless disregard for the truth” making any “false [] statements” during a
    campaign. Canon 5(B)(1)(c). The Kentucky Supreme Court interpreted it to prohibit “untrue
    utterance[s]” that are “material[]” to a campaign, and to apply to Jones’ request for voters to “re-
    elect” her even though she was initially appointed to her post. See Winter, 482 S.W.3d at 776,
    778–79.
    The clause is constitutional on its face. The narrowest way to keep judges honest during
    their campaigns is to prohibit them from consciously making false statements about matters
    material to the campaign. This canon does that, and does it clearly. In the words of the district
    court: “Don’t want to violate the Canon? Don’t tell a lie on purpose or recklessly.” R. 124 at
    38. Given the mens rea requirement, a judicial candidate will necessarily be conscious of
    violating this canon. Cf. Weaver v. Bonner, 
    309 F.3d 1312
    , 1319–20 (11th Cir. 2002).
    This court, it is true, recently invalidated a false-statement ban that covered all non-
    judicial candidates for political office in Ohio. See Susan B. Anthony List v. Driehaus, 
    814 F.3d 466
    , 473–76 (6th Cir. 2016). But the Ohio law swept more broadly than Kentucky’s: It applied
    to all false statements, not just material ones, compare id. at 475, with Winter, 482 S.W.3d at
    776, and it imposed liability on publishers of false statements, not just speakers, Susan B.
    Anthony List, 814 F.3d at 475. Kentucky’s narrower interest in preserving public confidence in
    the honesty and integrity of its judiciary also is more compelling than Ohio’s purported interest
    in protecting voters in other elected races from misinformation. See id. at 475. However much
    or however little truth-bending the public has come to expect from candidates for political jobs,
    “[j]udges are not politicians,” and a “State’s decision to elect its judiciary does not compel it to
    treat judicial candidates like campaigners for political office.” Williams-Yulee, 
    135 S. Ct. at 1662
    . Kentucky has a “vital state interest” in safeguarding the public’s confidence in the honesty
    of its judiciary, see 
    id. at 1666
     (quoting Caperton v. A.T. Massey Coal Co., 
    556 U.S. 868
    , 889
    (2009)), and the State’s ban on materially false statements by judicial candidates survives strict
    scrutiny—at least facially.
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841             Winter, et al. v. Wolnitzek, et al.               Page 13
    As applied to Jones, however, the State’s ban does not. The headwater of this problem is
    the Kentucky Supreme Court’s ruling that Jones’ “re-elect” statement qualified as a “materially
    false statement . . . calculated to mislead and deceive the voters.” Winter, 482 S.W.3d at 779.
    Yes, “re-elect” could mean what the court thought it meant: elect someone to the same position
    to which she was previously elected. See id. And that was not true for Jones. The Governor had
    appointed her to the position; she had not been elected to it. But the term fairly could also mean
    “to elect for another term in office,” precisely what Jones was seeking. Webster’s Third New
    International Dictionary 1907. Applied to a statement such as “re-elect,” readily capable of a
    true interpretation here, the ban outstrips the Commonwealth’s interest in ensuring candidates
    don’t tell knowing lies and thus fails to give candidates the “breathing space” necessary to free
    debate. Brown v. Hartlage, 
    456 U.S. 45
    , 60–61 (1982); see Weaver, 
    309 F.3d at
    1319–20.
    (7) Misleading statements clause. Canon 5(B)(1)(c)’s ban on misleading statements fails
    across the board. If “misleading” adds anything to “false,” it is to include statements that, while
    technically true or ambiguous, create false implications or give rise to false inferences. But only
    a ban on conscious falsehoods satisfies strict scrutiny.         See Weaver, 
    309 F.3d at 1319
    .
    “[E]rroneous statement is inevitable in free debate,” and “[t]he chilling effect of . . . absolute
    accountability for factual misstatements in the course of political debate is incompatible with
    [an] atmosphere of free discussion.” Brown, 
    456 U.S. at
    60–61 (quotation omitted). “Negligent
    misstatements,” in contrast to knowing misstatements, “must be protected in order to give
    protected speech the ‘breathing space’ it requires,” even in judicial elections. Weaver, 
    309 F.3d at 1320
    . Unknowing lies do not undermine the integrity of the judiciary in the same way that
    knowing lies do, and the ability of an opponent to correct a misstatement “more than offsets the
    danger of a misinformed electorate.” 
    Id.
     This clause adds little to the permissible ban on false
    statements, and what it adds cannot be squared with the First Amendment.
    (8) Commits clause.        Judicial candidates may not, “in connection with cases,
    controversies, or issues that are likely to come before the court, make pledges, promises or
    commitments that are inconsistent with the impartial performance of the adjudicative duties of
    judicial office.” Canon 5(B)(1)(c). We have seen a version of this canon before, and Kentucky
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841             Winter, et al. v. Wolnitzek, et al.                Page 14
    has (commendably) tried to focus its coverage since the last visit. See Carey, 
    614 F.3d at
    207–
    09.
    Then and now, no one questions that Kentucky may prohibit judges from making
    commitments to decide specific cases in a certain way. “The First Amendment,” after all,
    “permits a State to limit speech when the Due Process Clause demands nothing less.” 
    Id. at 207
    .
    Then and now, however, the canon does more than that by forbidding a judge from making “a
    promise with respect to ‘issues’ as well.” R. 124 at 35. “At the broadest level of meaning,” we
    noted in Carey, the clause “would seem to cover issue-related promises” on a number of
    impermissible bases: promises to, say, follow stare decisis, adhere to the rule of law, or interpret
    the law as a textualist. 
    614 F.3d at 208
    . But “[i]n a narrower sense,” we went on, the clause
    might be permissibly tailored to cover commitments “exhibit[ing] a bias against parties,” which
    would narrowly advance a compelling interest under White. 
    Id.
     Unable to tell which thing the
    canon did, yet unwilling to encroach on a “co-equal sovereign,” we remanded to “give the
    Commonwealth a first shot” at focusing the clause on its compelling interest in maintaining the
    impartiality—as to parties—of its judiciary. 
    Id. at 209
    .
    Kentucky has tried to do that.      It narrowed the commits clause to cover only a
    commitment “that [is] inconsistent with the impartial performance of the adjudicative duties of
    judicial office.” Canon 5(B)(1)(c). That language, missing from the version we reviewed in
    Carey, does much to fix the clause’s “serious level-of-generality problem.” 
    614 F.3d at 208
    . A
    commitment on many of the issues we worried about—on stare decisis, on the rule of law, on
    textualism, and so on—is not inconsistent with the “impartial performance” of a judge and thus
    is not prohibited by the clause. The revised commentary says as much. “[S]tatements or
    announcements of personal views on legal, political, or other issues,” it provides, “are not
    prohibited.” Canon 5(B)(1)(c), Cmt. And the Seventh Circuit, reviewing a canon with identical
    language, agreed that the revised version “differ[s] considerably from the rule at issue in Carey,”
    where “all commitments on [all] ‘issues’” were prohibited. Bauer, 
    620 F.3d at 716
    ; cf. Kans.
    Judicial Review v. Stout, 
    562 F.3d 1240
    , 1246–47 (10th Cir. 2009).
    What appears to narrow the clause, the plaintiffs respond, makes it unconstitutionally
    vague.    It is impossible to know, they contend, what is (and what is not) an issue-based
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841              Winter, et al. v. Wolnitzek, et al.                 Page 15
    commitment that is “inconsistent with the impartial performance of the adjudicative duties of
    judicial office.”
    There is something to the point, and we can understand why the district court agreed with
    it. While the “root meaning” of the word “impartiality” is avoiding “bias for or against either
    party to the proceeding,” White, 
    536 U.S. at 775
    , “[n]either the commits clauses nor the
    [Canon’s] definitions pin th[at] meaning down,” Bauer, 
    620 F.3d at 716
    . And while we might
    read this clause narrowly to toe the constitutional line, it’s not clear that this would respect the
    Commission and state judiciary’s approach to the language. See 
    id.
     We doubt, for example, that
    Jones’ promise to “continue to work with the legislative and executive branches to ensure that
    the law provides stiff penalties for heroin dealers,” R. 80 at 8 (quotation omitted), is
    “inconsistent with [] impartiality” and thus anticipate that it could not be constitutionally
    proscribed. But we don’t know if that’s how the Commonwealth will construe the provision.
    Our inability to know how much protected speech the canon sweeps in means we could hold, as
    the district court did, that the clause is vague and unconstitutionally overbroad.
    But again, “discretion, to say nothing of respect for a co-equal sovereign, is the better part
    of valor.”   Carey, 
    614 F.3d at 209
    .       If Kentucky interprets “impartiality” to mean solely
    “impartiality as to parties,” the clause may well advance a compelling interest and do so
    narrowly. See White, 
    536 U.S. at
    775–77. Just as we did in Carey, we think it wise to “remand
    this aspect of the case to the district court,” which will allow the defendants to “obtain authority
    to remove the ‘issues’ language”; to adopt “an acceptable narrowing construction of the ‘issues’
    language along with a modification to the commentary”; or to “suggest certification to the
    Kentucky Supreme Court.” 
    614 F.3d at 209
    . For now, we will “assume that [Kentucky] will act
    sensibly and resolve the open questions in a way that honors candidates’ rights under the first
    amendment” rather than “deem the law vague by identifying situations in which state officials
    might take an untenably broad reading of the commits clause[].” Bauer, 
    620 F.3d at 716
    . We
    thus reinstate this clause and will “wait and see” if the Commonwealth’s “process [] yields
    greater certainty”—and firmer constitutionality. 
    Id.
     at 716–17. For the last time, one hopes.
    Nos. 16-5836/5839/5841             Winter, et al. v. Wolnitzek, et al.                Page 16
    * * *
    Regulating campaign speech is not easy. It’s not supposed to be. But treating elections
    for the courts just like elections for the political branches does not make sense either. Candidates
    for judicial office, if elected, are supposed to follow the rule of law—no matter current public
    opinion, no matter the views of the political branches, no matter the views of the parties that
    support them. But candidates for the other offices are permitted to, indeed often expected to,
    listen to the views of their constituents and parties. Navigating these cross-currents is no simple
    task—and for that we have considerable sympathy for the efforts of the Commission. At the
    same time Kentucky has the right to elect its judges on a nonpartisan basis, however, it has no
    right to suspend the First Amendment in the process. If the Commission wishes to impose
    mandatory sanctions on the speech of judicial candidates for office, as opposed to non-
    enforceable guidelines or best practices, it must satisfy the rigors of the First Amendment in
    doing so.
    IV.
    We affirm the district court’s judgment as to the campaigning, speeches, endorsements,
    acting as a leader, and misleading statements clauses, and as to the facial challenge to the false
    statements clause. We reverse the court’s judgment on the contributions clause and the as-
    applied challenge to the false statements clause. And we vacate the court’s judgment on the
    commits clause and remand for further consideration of that clause’s meaning and validity.