Patrick Atkinson v. Merrick B. Garland ( 2023 )


Menu:
  •                                In the
    United States Court of Appeals
    For the Seventh Circuit
    ____________________
    No. 22-1557
    PATRICK ATKINSON,
    Plaintiff-Appellant,
    v.
    MERRICK GARLAND, Attorney General of the United States,
    and STEVEN DETTELBACH, Director of the Bureau of Alcohol,
    Tobacco, Firearms and Explosives,
    Defendants-Appellees.
    ____________________
    Appeal from the United States District Court for the
    Northern District of Illinois, Eastern Division.
    No. 1:21-cv-291 — John Robert Blakey, Judge.
    ____________________
    ARGUED NOVEMBER 8, 2022 — DECIDED JUNE 20, 2023
    ____________________
    Before SYKES, Chief Judge, and WOOD and SCUDDER, Circuit
    Judges.
    SCUDDER, Circuit Judge. Before us is a Second Amendment
    challenge to the federal felon-in-possession statute, 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1). The appeal reaches us in the wake of the Supreme
    Court’s decision in New York State Rifle & Pistol Association v.
    Bruen, 
    142 S. Ct. 2111 (2022)
    . That development is significant
    2                                                  No. 22-1557
    because Bruen announced a new framework for analyzing re-
    strictions on the possession of firearms. No longer, the Su-
    preme Court made clear, can lower courts balance interests—
    of an individual’s right to possess a firearm and the state’s
    commitment to promoting personal or public safety—to re-
    solve the constitutionality of the challenged restriction. The
    new approach anchors itself exclusively in the Second
    Amendment’s text and the pertinent history of firearms regu-
    lation, with the government bearing the burden of “affirma-
    tively prov[ing] that its firearms regulation is part of the his-
    torical tradition that delimits the outer bounds of the right to
    keep and bear arms.” 
    Id. at 2127
    .
    The Supreme Court decided Bruen after the district court
    faithfully applied our precedent and rejected Patrick Atkin-
    son’s Second Amendment challenge to § 922(g)(1). The par-
    ties’ briefing on appeal only scratches the surface of the his-
    torical analysis now required by Bruen. In these circum-
    stances, we think the best course is to remand to allow the
    district court to undertake the Bruen analysis in the first in-
    stance.
    I
    A
    Before Bruen, the Supreme Court’s decisions in District of
    Columbia v. Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
     (2008), and McDonald v. City of
    Chicago, 
    561 U.S. 742
     (2010), defined our approach to resolving
    Second Amendment challenges to firearms restrictions. Those
    cases established that the Second Amendment “protects a per-
    sonal right to keep and bear arms for lawful purposes, most
    notably for self-defense within the home.” McDonald, 
    561 U.S. at 780
     (plurality). The right was not, however, “unlimited.”
    No. 22-1557                                                       3
    Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 626
    . Nodding to commentators from “Black-
    stone through the 19th-century cases,” the Court acknowl-
    edged that some firearms restrictions could pass constitu-
    tional muster. 
    Id.
    Every circuit court responded to Heller by developing the
    same two-step test. See Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2126–27. At the first
    step, the government could defend the challenged restriction
    by showing that the regulated activity fell outside the scope
    of the Second Amendment as originally understood. See, e.g.,
    Ezell v. City of Chicago, 
    846 F.3d 888
    , 892 (7th Cir. 2017). If his-
    tory proved inconclusive or suggested the regulated activity
    was not “categorically unprotected,” we then conducted a
    means-end analysis, weighing the severity of the regulation
    against the ends the government sought to achieve. See 
    id.
    (quoting Ezell v. City of Chicago, 
    651 F.3d 684
    , 703 (7th Cir.
    2011)).
    Bruen leaves no room for doubt: text and history, not a
    means-end analysis, now define the controlling Second
    Amendment inquiry. See 142 S. Ct. at 2131 (emphasizing that,
    although “judicial deference to legislative interest balancing
    is understandable—and elsewhere, appropriate—it is not def-
    erence that the Constitution demands here [under the Second
    Amendment]”). Accordingly, when the Second Amend-
    ment’s “plain text” covers the regulated conduct, the govern-
    ment has only one way to defend the regulation—by proving
    that it is “consistent with this Nation’s historical tradition of
    firearm regulation.” Id. at 2126.
    Alongside announcing this standard, the Court offered
    guidance on what is certain to prove most challenging for the
    lower courts—how to interpret and define the relevant body
    of regulatory history. The pertinent question, the Court
    4                                                    No. 22-1557
    explained, is what the Founders understood the Second
    Amendment to mean. See id. at 2136. The Court therefore cau-
    tioned against giving too much weight to laws passed before
    or after the Founding, although a “long, unbroken line of
    common-law precedent stretching from Bracton to Blackstone
    is far more likely to be part of our law than a short-lived, 14th-
    century English practice.” Id. Post-Founding history may also
    play a role in guiding “our interpretation of an ambiguous
    constitutional provision.” Id. at 2137 (quoting NLRB v. Noel
    Canning, 
    573 U.S. 513
    , 572 (2014) (Scalia, J., concurring in judg-
    ment)).
    Bruen directs us to canvass these historical periods for sim-
    ilar regulations. When “a challenged regulation addresses a
    general societal problem that has persisted since the 18th cen-
    tury, the lack of a distinctly similar historical regulation ad-
    dressing that problem is relevant evidence that the challenged
    regulation is inconsistent with the Second Amendment.” 
    Id. at 2131
    . So too if the Founders used “materially different
    means” to address the same problem. 
    Id.
     “And if some juris-
    dictions actually attempted to enact analogous regulations
    during this timeframe, but those proposals were rejected on
    constitutional grounds, that rejection surely would provide
    some probative evidence of unconstitutionality.” 
    Id.
    To defend “modern regulations that were unimaginable at
    the founding,” the government may reason by analogy. 
    Id. at 2132
    . That does not require pinpointing a “dead ringer”—a
    “well-established and representative historical analogue” will
    do. 
    Id. at 2133
     (emphasis in original). The proper inquiry, in
    short, turns on whether the “modern and historical regula-
    tions impose a comparable burden on the right of armed self-
    defense and whether that burden is comparably justified.” 
    Id.
    No. 22-1557                                                     5
    In Bruen itself, the Court applied this inquiry to a New
    York law that required an applicant to demonstrate “proper
    cause” to receive a permit for public carry of a firearm. The
    state’s proper-cause requirement did not survive the Court’s
    exacting textual and historical analysis. See 
    id. at 2138
     (con-
    cluding that the state neither “demonstrate[d] a tradition of
    broadly prohibiting the public carry of commonly used fire-
    arms for self-defense” nor identified “any such historical tra-
    dition limiting public carry only to those law-abiding citizens
    who demonstrate a special need for self-defense”).
    The Court devoted most of its attention to Founding-era
    laws, while also paying some regard to historical analogues
    dating as far back as 1328 and as recent as the late 1800s. Many
    of the laws drawn from this full historical range proved to be
    poor analogues because they were significantly less restrictive
    than New York’s licensing scheme. A pre-Founding English
    law, providing that Englishmen could not “go nor ride armed
    by night nor by day,” banned public carry of weapons only
    when intended to cause terror. See 
    id. at 2139
     (quoting Statute
    of Northampton 1328, 
    2 Edw. 3
     c. 3 (Eng.)). Early colonial laws
    were not only few and far between but also carried the same
    intent requirement. See 
    id.
     at 2142–43. The New York law, by
    contrast, banned public carry across the board for citizens
    who could not convince authorities that they had a special
    need to carry their weapons publicly.
    Some mid-19th-century statutes banned concealed carry,
    but they typically left the right to open carry intact. See 
    id.
     at
    2146–47. Surety statutes—which forced some individuals to
    post bond before carrying weapons publicly—applied only to
    individuals likely to pose a threat, yet even those individuals
    6                                                    No. 22-1557
    could carry weapons publicly after posting bond. See 
    id.
     at
    2148–50.
    At other points, the government’s analogues were not
    enough to show a tradition of similar regulation. Some laws
    were comparable to the New York statute in severity but were
    outliers in their time. See 
    id. at 2153
    . Other laws were not en-
    forced often or effectively enough to establish a historical tra-
    dition of comparable firearms regulation. See 
    id.
     at 2149–50.
    Still others impacted a limited swath of the total population,
    faced little judicial scrutiny, and came too late after the
    Founding to shed much light on the original understanding
    of the Second Amendment. See 
    id.
     at 2154–55.
    B
    Patrick Atkinson filed this lawsuit before Bruen. His crim-
    inal history included a 1998 guilty plea to felony mail fraud.
    After maintaining an otherwise clean record for 24 years, he
    decided he wanted a gun. But 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1) bars gun
    possession for anyone who, like Atkinson, has a conviction for
    “a crime punishable by imprisonment for a term exceeding
    one year.” So he brought this suit under 18 U.S.C. § 925A to
    challenge the constitutionality of § 922(g)(1) as the law ap-
    plied to him.
    Relying on our pre-Bruen framework, the district court
    granted a motion from the government and dismissed the
    case. Our precedent, the district court explained, compelled
    that outcome, as we had previously rejected challenges to
    § 922(g)(1) mirroring the one that Atkinson lodged. See, e.g.,
    Kanter v. Barr, 
    919 F.3d 437
     (7th Cir. 2019); Hatfield v. Barr, 
    925 F.3d 950
     (7th Cir. 2019). But we did so under the means-end
    inquiry after determining that the historical record on felons
    No. 22-1557                                                   7
    possessing firearms was “inconclusive.” Kanter, 
    919 F.3d at
    445–47. Because our precedent moved straight to the means-
    end analysis, the district court did not conduct the historical
    analysis that Bruen now requires.
    II
    The parties’ briefing does not grapple with Bruen. The best
    way forward, as we see it, is to return the case to the district
    court for a proper, fulsome analysis of the historical tradition
    supporting § 922(g)(1).
    A
    For its part, the government would have us avoid a Bruen
    analysis altogether. Invoking Heller and McDonald, it urges us
    to uphold § 922(g)(1) based on oft-quoted dicta describing
    felon-in-possession laws as “presumptively lawful.” Heller,
    
    554 U.S. at
    626–27 & n.26; see also McDonald, 
    561 U.S. at 786
    (plurality) (“We repeat [Heller’s] assurances here.”). The gov-
    ernment sees further support for its view in Bruen itself. See
    142 S. Ct. at 2138 n.9 (explaining that “nothing in our analysis
    should be interpreted to suggest the unconstitutionality” of
    public carry licensing schemes requiring applicants to pass a
    criminal background check).
    Nothing allows us to sidestep Bruen in the way the gov-
    ernment invites. Yes, the Court seemed to find no constitu-
    tional fault with a state requiring a criminal background
    check before issuing a public carry permit. But in no way did
    the Court suggest that its observation resolved cases like the
    one Atkinson brought challenging § 922(g)(1). We must un-
    dertake the text-and-history inquiry the Court so plainly an-
    nounced and expounded upon at great length.
    8                                                   No. 22-1557
    The government’s brief before us includes some historical
    analysis, but nothing close to what would satisfy the demand-
    ing standard set forth in Bruen. In addition to some Founding-
    era commentary, the government mentions that felons like At-
    kinson were historically subject to execution and estate forfei-
    ture, as well as the loss of other civic rights.
    No doubt these historical details may prove relevant on
    remand. But the government’s analysis as a whole falls well
    short of Bruen’s demands. Remember what the Court itself
    did in Bruen after rejecting a means-end approach and an-
    nouncing the text-and-history standard—it rolled up its
    sleeves and examined a wealth of laws and commentary span-
    ning several centuries, paying close attention to the enforce-
    ment and impact of various regulations. The government
    points us to only a couple of isolated historical facts and inci-
    dents, offering no detail about their application and import.
    This does not suffice under Bruen.
    Since oral argument, the government has also urged us to
    conclude, without any historical analysis, that the plain text
    of the Second Amendment does not cover felons. See, e.g.,
    United States v. Sitladeen, No. 22-1010, 
    2023 WL 2765015
    , at *2–
    5 (8th Cir. Apr. 4, 2023) (relying on circuit precedent and con-
    cluding that unauthorized aliens are not part of “the people”
    protected by the Second Amendment). Bruen left this compli-
    cated issue unresolved. Although we analyzed the scope of
    the Second Amendment right before Bruen, we have not re-
    turned to the issue since then. See United States v. Meza-Rodri-
    guez, 
    798 F.3d 664
    , 669–72 (7th Cir. 2015) (defining “the peo-
    ple” for purposes of the Second Amendment as members of
    the national community with substantial connections to the
    No. 22-1557                                                  9
    country). We cannot resolve the issue without the benefit of
    more substantial briefing on remand.
    Atkinson’s historical analysis falls short, too. He now ar-
    gues that § 922(g)(1) is facially unconstitutional because his-
    tory supports disarming only “dangerous” persons with con-
    victions for “violent” felonies. Alternatively, he urges us to
    conclude that history requires an individualized assessment
    of the danger that he poses. To support these contentions, At-
    kinson leans on Founding-era commentary and various laws
    disarming politically dangerous groups.
    But although Atkinson has shown some support for the
    idea that a group’s “dangerousness” is what mattered to the
    Founders, he does not provide much historical basis for indi-
    vidualized assessments or for delineating between individu-
    als who committed violent versus non-violent crimes. The
    distinction is not an obvious consequence of many of the laws
    that Atkinson, and his amicus especially, discuss. Nor does
    Atkinson tell us what the Founders would have viewed as a
    “violent” crime and what evidence they would consider in
    making that determination.
    Aided by the parties’ briefing and the benefits of the ad-
    versarial process, the district court is best suited to conduct
    the required analysis in the first instance. As our dissenting
    colleague underscores, the constitutional issues at stake are
    weighty. Before we resolve the question before us, the parties
    should have a full and fair opportunity to develop their posi-
    tions before the district court in accordance with the princi-
    ples of party presentation. Our review, which all agree is in-
    evitable, will be better for what transpires on remand in the
    district court.
    10                                                 No. 22-1557
    B
    Several interrelated and non-exhaustive questions may
    help focus the proper analysis on remand:
    1. Does § 922(g)(1) address a “general societal
    problem that has persisted since the 18th cen-
    tury?” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2131. If this problem
    existed during a relevant historical period, did
    earlier generations address it with similar or
    “materially different means?” Id.
    2. What does history tell us about disarming those
    convicted of crimes generally and of felonies in
    particular? Among other sources, the parties
    could look to commentary from the Founders,
    proposals emerging from the states’ constitu-
    tional ratifying conventions, any actual prac-
    tices of disarming felons or criminals more gen-
    erally around the time of the Founding, and
    treatment of felons outside of the gun context
    (to the extent this treatment is probative of the
    Founders’ views of the Second Amendment).
    When considering historical regulations and
    practices, the key question is whether those reg-
    ulations and practices are comparable in sub-
    stance to the restriction imposed by § 922(g)(1).
    To answer the question, the district court and
    the parties should consider how the breadth, se-
    verity, and the underlying rationale of the his-
    torical examples stack up against § 922(g)(1).
    3. Are there broader historical analogues to
    § 922(g)(1) during the periods that Bruen
    No. 22-1557                                                  11
    emphasized, including, but not limited to, laws
    disarming “dangerous” groups other than fel-
    ons? The parties should not stop at compiling
    lists of historical firearms regulations and prac-
    tices. The proper inquiry, as we have explained,
    should focus on how the substance of the histor-
    ical examples compares to § 922(g)(1).
    4. If the district court’s historical inquiry identifies
    analogous laws, do those laws supply enough
    of a historical tradition (as opposed to isolated
    instances of regulation) to support § 922(g)(1)?
    On this front, the parties should provide details
    about the enforcement, impact, or judicial scru-
    tiny of these laws, to the extent possible.
    5. If history supports Atkinson’s call for individu-
    alized assessments or for a distinction between
    violent and non-violent felonies, how do we de-
    fine a non-violent or a non-dangerous felony?
    And what evidence can a court consider in as-
    sessing whether a particular felony conviction
    was violent? For instance, can a court consider
    the felony conviction itself, the facts of the un-
    derlying crime, or sentencing enhancements?
    Bruen shows that these distinctions should also
    have firm historical support. See 142 S. Ct. at
    2132–33 (explaining that the court must assess
    whether modern and historical regulations are
    “relevantly similar,” including in terms of how
    and why the regulations burden gun rights).
    Both sides should cast a wider net and provide more detail
    about whatever history they rely on. For its part, the district
    12                                                  No. 22-1557
    court may accept amicus briefs to assist with its inquiry and,
    of course, may benefit from recent decisions from other courts
    and indeed the analysis embodied in our dissenting col-
    league’s opinion. See, e.g., post, at 24–36; Range v. Att’y Gen.,
    No. 21-2835, 
    2023 WL 3833404
     (3d Cir. June 6, 2023) (conclud-
    ing that § 922(g)(1) is unconstitutional as applied to an appel-
    lant convicted of a welfare fraud offense); United States v. Jack-
    son, No. 22-2870, 
    2023 WL 3769242
     (8th Cir. June 2, 2023) (re-
    jecting an as-applied challenge).
    Although the government must conduct a more substan-
    tial historical analysis on remand, it may also develop its con-
    tention that the plain text of the Second Amendment does not
    protect felons and other offenders impacted by § 922(g)(1).
    III
    We recognize that asking these questions is easier than an-
    swering them. As our dissenting colleague likewise empha-
    sizes, the historical analysis required by Bruen will be difficult
    and no doubt yield some measure of indeterminacy. The par-
    ties may be unable altogether to find answers to certain ques-
    tions, may find incomplete information in response to others,
    and perhaps in some instances may identify substantial his-
    torical information pertinent to one or another dimension of
    the required inquiry. In the end, the district court (and surely
    us too, when this case or another one like it returns) will have
    to give the best answer available to whether the government
    has carried its burden of “affirmatively prov[ing] that its fire-
    arms regulation is part of the historical tradition that delimits
    the outer bounds of the right to keep and bear arms.” Bruen,
    142 S. Ct. at 2127.
    No. 22-1557                                        13
    For these reasons, we VACATE and REMAND for further
    proceedings.
    14                                                  No. 22-1557
    WOOD, Circuit Judge, dissenting. The question before us in
    this case could not be more important: may individual rights
    under the Second Amendment be curtailed or denied only on
    the basis of a granular, case-by-case analysis, or does Con-
    gress have the power to enact categorical restrictions? And if
    some categorical limits are possible and others are not, what
    sorting principle may or must we use to separate the permis-
    sible from the impermissible?
    My colleagues have taken the position that we need fur-
    ther input from the district court before we can tackle the pre-
    sent case. With respect, I do not agree with them. The issue
    before us is whether 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1) is compatible with
    the Second Amendment. That statute prohibits those con-
    victed of a crime for which the punishment exceeds one year
    in prison (usually felonies) from possessing a firearm or am-
    munition. This is a pure question of law, and our considera-
    tion is therefore de novo. If we think that we would benefit
    from further exploration of the issue, in light of the interven-
    ing decision in New York State Rifle & Pistol Association, Inc. v.
    Bruen, 
    142 S. Ct. 2111 (2022)
    , nothing prevents us from asking
    the parties to submit supplemental briefs. Exactly that process
    occurs when we are confronted with an unfamiliar question
    of foreign law—another setting in which we have the author-
    ity to conduct our own research. See Fed. R. Civ. P. 44.1. Just
    so here: we must decide whether, in light of the textual and
    historical materials to which Bruen directs us, section
    922(g)(1) is constitutional. Remanding this case to the district
    court will not reduce our responsibility to evaluate that ques-
    tion independently when the case inevitably returns to us.
    My own assessment of the materials that now govern Sec-
    ond Amendment questions per Bruen convinces me that the
    No. 22-1557                                                       15
    categorical prohibition created by section 922(g)(1) passes
    muster under the Constitution. I would therefore affirm the
    district court now, without saddling it with a Ph.D.-level his-
    torical inquiry that necessarily will be inconclusive.
    I
    Section 922(g)(1) makes it unlawful “for any person who
    has been convicted in any court of [] a crime punishable by
    imprisonment for a term exceeding one year … to ship or
    transport … or possess … any firearm or ammunition.” Sev-
    eral questions come immediately to mind, including whether
    the weapon (or ammunition) being shipped, transported, or
    possessed falls within the scope of the Second Amendment,
    and whether the accused has committed the type of predicate
    offense to which the statute refers. I will say only a few words
    about those antecedent questions, because they do not play a
    significant role in the present case. I will then move on to the
    heart of the matter: whether the individual right to bear arms
    recognized in the Second Amendment can be regulated by
    Congress in the manner we see in section 922(g)(1).
    At a high level of generality, few would disagree with the
    proposition that not all weapons qualify as the “arms” to
    which the Second Amendment refers—that is, weapons that
    ordinary people are entitled to use for purposes of self-de-
    fense or sport. Contrary to the textualist position, it is also
    plain that this is not an amendment whose meaning was fro-
    zen in time upon its addition to the Constitution. In District of
    Columbia v. Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
     (2008), the Court made the lat-
    ter point clear when it said that “the Second Amendment ex-
    tends, prima facie, to all instruments that constitute bearable
    arms, even those that were not in existence at the time of the found-
    ing.” 
    554 U.S. at 582
     (emphasis added). But that did not extend
    16                                                  No. 22-1557
    Second Amendment protections to everything that could be
    described as a weapon. Courts are compelled to draw lines,
    and argument is always possible near the boundaries. But
    some things are relatively clear. No one doubts that handguns
    are “bearable arms” and thus the type of weapon covered by
    the Amendment. Well beyond the other side of this imaginary
    line are devices such as rocket-launchers or nuclear warheads,
    both of which are reserved for the exclusive use of the mili-
    tary. Because Atkinson wants the right to have and to use
    weapons that, as far as this record shows, fit comfortably
    within the Amendment, I will assume for purposes of this dis-
    sent that the issue before us has nothing to do with the type of
    weapon involved here.
    The nature of the offense that has swept Atkinson under
    the prohibition in section 922(g)(1) is another matter. As I
    noted a moment ago, the statute disqualifies all persons who
    have been convicted in any court of “a” crime punishable by
    more than a year’s imprisonment. (Interestingly, the term
    “any court” does not include courts of foreign countries. See
    Small v. United States, 
    544 U.S. 385
     (2005).) The relevant of-
    fenses do not include “any Federal or State offenses pertaining
    to antitrust violations, unfair trade practices, restraints of
    trade, or other similar offenses relating to the regulation of
    business practices”; nor do they include “any State offense
    classified by the laws of the State as a misdemeanor and pun-
    ishable by a term of imprisonment of two years or less,” or
    convictions that have been expunged or pardoned. 
    18 U.S.C. § 921
    (a)(20). Convictions for which civil rights have been re-
    stored also do not count, unless there is an express provision
    exempting firearms from the restoration. Id.; see generally
    Buchmeier v. United States, 
    581 F.3d 561
     (7th Cir. 2009) (en
    banc). But those limitations do not help Atkinson. His
    No. 22-1557                                                 17
    predicate offense was a serious federal crime: felony mail
    fraud in violation of 
    18 U.S.C. § 1341
    , which is punishable by
    up to 20 years’ imprisonment. He pleaded guilty in 1998 to
    defrauding one of his clients by paying $6,000 to an insider
    involved in a hiring transaction. His sentence was a light
    one—six months’ home confinement, two years’ supervised
    release, and a $15,000 fine.
    In his briefing before this court, Atkinson urges us to re-
    gard this as a trivial offense, not worthy of permanent loss of
    Second Amendment rights. He also suggests that his own par-
    ticipation in the fraudulent scheme was “unwitting” and that
    we should account for his relative lack of culpability. At the
    same time, he claims that he fully accepts responsibility for
    his actions and his status as someone convicted of a felony.
    Even so, he urges, the Second Amendment does not support
    the categorical exclusion of all felons from gun possession,
    ownership, or use.
    Atkinson’s invitation for us to conduct an independent
    evaluation of the gravity of his own crime for purposes of sec-
    tion 922(g)(1) is out of bounds, in my view. The Judiciary can-
    not be in the position of looking at prior offenses identified by
    Congress and second-guessing Congress’s decisions both
    with respect to criminalization and to sentencing exposure.
    Should a judge who believes that we should attack this na-
    tion’s illegal drug problem with addiction treatment rather
    than criminal penalties rule that drug dealers did not commit
    sufficiently heinous crimes to deserve the loss of their gun
    rights? Should a judge ignore a crime such as tax evasion if it
    is committed by a person who has fallen on hard times, finan-
    cially speaking, and who is trying to find money for her fam-
    ily? I see no principled way to go down that road. Worse,
    18                                                   No. 22-1557
    Atkinson seems to be inviting us to consider the particular
    facts of every case, to see if the conduct underlying the con-
    viction ought to support restrictions on gun rights. Such a sys-
    tem would impose impossible burdens on courts and prose-
    cutors and would lead to an arbitrary patchwork of deci-
    sions—as far from the rule of law as one could imagine.
    With that in mind, I will continue on the assumption that
    Atkinson’s second argument is the serious one in this case:
    whether a permanent restriction on Second Amendment
    rights for all felons lies within Congress’s powers, or if instead
    we must go offense-by-offense, as we do under the categorical
    approach for armed career criminals, see 
    18 U.S.C. § 924
    (c),
    and decide which felony convictions call for that measure.
    The Supreme Court’s guidance satisfies me that the Court rec-
    ognizes that certain across-the-board disqualifications from
    gun ownership have always been part of the U.S. approach to
    gun regulation and thus have the kind of historical support
    that Bruen demands. I say this in full awareness of the fact that
    Supreme Court decisions are not to be read as statutes. This
    court noted the problem with such an approach in United
    States v. Skoien, 
    614 F.3d 638
    , 640 (7th Cir. 2010) (en banc) (up-
    holding 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(9) against a Second Amendment
    challenge), and I have no quarrel with the admonition to treat
    language in opinions as informative rather than as a compre-
    hensive code.
    II
    So what has the Supreme Court told us about general lim-
    itations on the right to bear arms? I would begin with its well-
    known passage in Heller:
    No. 22-1557                                                    19
    Like most rights, the right secured by the Second
    Amendment is not unlimited. From Blackstone through
    the 19th-century cases, commentators and courts routinely
    explained that the right was not a right to keep and carry
    any weapon whatsoever in any manner whatsoever and
    for whatever purpose. … For example, the majority of the
    19th-century courts to consider the question held that pro-
    hibitions on carrying concealed weapons were lawful un-
    der the Second Amendment or state analogues. … Alt-
    hough we do not undertake an exhaustive historical anal-
    ysis today of the full scope of the Second Amendment,
    nothing in our opinion should be taken to cast doubt on
    longstanding prohibitions on the possession of firearms
    by felons and the mentally ill, or laws forbidding the car-
    rying of firearms in sensitive places such as schools and
    government buildings, or laws imposing conditions and
    qualifications on the commercial sale of arms.
    
    554 U.S. at
    626–27 (citations omitted); see also Bruen, 142 S. Ct.
    at 2128 (repeating the reference to Blackstone). The Heller
    Court went on to recognize “another important limitation on
    the right to keep and carry arms”—it was limited to “the sorts
    of weapons” that were “in common use at the time.” 
    554 U.S. at 627
    . Let me pause for a moment on the phrase “in common
    use.” In Heller, the Court explained it this way: “[United States
    v. Miller, 
    307 U.S. 174
     (1939)] said … that the sorts of weapons
    protected were those ‘in common use at the time.’ 
    307 U.S. at 179
    . We think that limitation is fairly supported by the histor-
    ical tradition of prohibiting the carrying of ‘dangerous and
    unusual weapons.’” 
    554 U.S. at 627
    .
    The Court’s reference to historical tradition indicates that
    the relevant time for the “common use” inquiry is when the
    20                                                  No. 22-1557
    Second Amendment was adopted, not when the current law-
    suit arose. Otherwise the weapons that qualify as being in
    “common use” would vary over time in capricious ways.
    Think about the modern pistols that have been available since
    the 1980s. Presumably someone who wanted to own and
    carry such a pistol during the first year it was on the market
    would have had a hard time showing “common use”—it was
    a new product, after all. But in time it became very popular.
    The early purchasers of such a pistol do not have to wait for
    that popularity before they can rely on Second Amendment
    protections; rather, they would have analogized it to the
    smaller, pistol-style weapons in common use in 1791. What
    Heller and Bruen demand is not a headcount of how many
    people today own a certain firearm or how many are sold. In-
    stead, those decisions ask which historical analogue the mod-
    ern weapon most strongly resembles. If the analogue is one
    that people were entitled to use, then that part of Second
    Amendment analysis is satisfied; if instead the item is more
    like the “dangerous and unusual weapons” of yore, then it is
    not one of the “arms” protected by the Amendment.
    A
    Let’s turn, then, to those “longstanding prohibitions on
    the possession of firearms by felons and the mentally ill, or
    laws forbidding the carrying of firearms in sensitive places
    such as schools and government buildings, or laws impos-
    ing conditions and qualifications on the commercial sale of
    arms,” Heller, 
    554 U.S. at
    626–27, to see if they hold the key to
    the resolution of Atkinson’s case. The first point to make is
    that nothing in that list may be justified by the means/end test
    that Bruen disapproved. But these were “longstanding prohi-
    bitions” and thus fall squarely within the historical test to
    No. 22-1557                                                      21
    which courts must now confine themselves. I accept for pre-
    sent purposes that this passage from Heller alone is not
    enough to resolve Atkinson’s case, since (as we noted in
    Skoien) the Supreme Court may have been merely observing
    that the Heller case did not require it to evaluate those re-
    strictions. It was able to save them for another day, and in this
    case, we have reached that day.
    The “who” question presented by our case—who may be
    subject to restrictions on their Second Amendment rights—is
    now governed by Bruen’s framework. Bruen does not slam the
    door on all gun regulation; it acknowledges that a given reg-
    ulation or restriction may be defended if it is “consistent with
    this Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation.” 142 S.
    Ct. at 2126. This approach poses enormous challenges to the
    district and circuit courts of this country, not to mention the
    myriad state courts that must also deal with the Second
    Amendment in light of McDonald v. City of Chicago. See 
    561 U.S. 742
    , 750 (2010) (holding that the Second Amendment ap-
    plies to the states, through incorporation under the Four-
    teenth Amendment). Every unit of government, from the
    smallest village or municipality, through counties and par-
    ishes, states, federal enclaves, and the federal government it-
    self, has had something to say about guns. Many of them have
    laws going back to the origins of this country. What are we to
    make of all this?
    History does not write itself. Historiographers would cau-
    tion us that the choice of sources, facts, organizational princi-
    ples, and theories, all contribute to the final narrative. See, e.g.,
    “Historiography,” Merriam-Webster, https://www.merriam-
    webster.com/dictionary/historiography (defining historiog-
    raphy as “the writing of history, especially: the writing of
    22                                                   No. 22-1557
    history based on the critical examination of sources, the selec-
    tion of particulars from the authentic materials, and the syn-
    thesis of particulars into a narrative that will stand the test of
    critical methods”). Only a professional historian would know
    how to evaluate often-conflicting claims about the social, cul-
    tural, and legal landscape of an earlier period, and that person
    likely would not jump to any conclusions without devoting
    significant time to an evaluation of original sources.
    In Bruen, the Court optimistically said at a few points that
    all that was needed was a search for analogues—something
    that common-law judges do every day. But a closer look at the
    opinion shows that it did not have something quite that sim-
    ple in mind. Some historical examples proffered by the parties
    met with its approval; others were dismissed as not being suf-
    ficiently widespread, or sufficiently analogous to the modern
    situation, to be useful. We are left with something not much
    better than the Goldilocks solution: history can’t be viewed
    too specifically, and it can’t be viewed too generally. It must
    be, like the bed, the chair, or the porridge, “just right.” See
    Jake Charles, Bruen, Analogies, and the Quest for Goldilocks His-
    tory, Duke Center for Firearms Law Blog (June 28, 2022). And
    that “perfect” length, or height, or temperature will remain in
    the eye of the beholder, or perhaps the final court to consider
    the matter.
    Lest I be accused of exaggerating, let me give a few exam-
    ples of the fine lines courts are now being asked to draw. First,
    Bruen tells us that the historical analogue must be neither too
    old nor too recent. It adds that the most persuasive analogous
    regulations are those enacted or in place at the time the Sec-
    ond Amendment was ratified (1791) or those that date from
    the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment (1868)
    No. 22-1557                                                    23
    (presumably if the regulation at issue comes from a state en-
    tity rather than the federal government). As Justice Thomas
    reminded us, “[c]onstitutional rights are enshrined with the
    scope they were understood to have when the people adopted
    them.” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2126 (quoting Heller, 
    554 U.S. at
    634–
    35). Next, the historical analogues must be abundant, though
    they need not appear in every jurisdiction. Being able to point
    to three colonial regulations is not enough to demonstrate a
    regulatory “tradition,” 
    id.
     at 2142–43, even if the three colo-
    nies in question represented nearly a quarter of the original
    13 and accounted for almost half the country’s population.
    Furthermore, the regulations must have been “actually” en-
    forced by the authorities, though we do not know what ratio
    between incidence of the regulated action and prosecutions is
    enough to make enforcement “actual.” And laws that were
    “short lived” “deserve little weight.” Id. at 2155.
    Having said all that, the Court gave back with the left
    hand a little of what it had taken away with the right: it
    stressed that “analogical reasoning under the Second Amend-
    ment is neither a regulatory straitjacket nor a regulatory blank
    check.” Id. at 2133. It assured readers that courts do not need
    to track down a “historical twin” that corresponds to a mod-
    ern regulation in order for a restriction on firearm possession
    to pass constitutional muster. We must ask instead “how and
    why the regulations burden a law-abiding citizen’s right to
    armed self-defense” and decide whether that “how” and
    “why” are relevantly similar to the historical antecedents. Id.
    (Note once again that the assumption is that the citizen is
    “law-abiding.” The Court said nothing about what makes
    someone law-abiding or not.) A lower court judge could be
    forgiven for thinking that there is a great deal of play in these
    joints.
    24                                                   No. 22-1557
    B
    Taking Bruen at its word, as we all must in our hierarchical
    judicial system, what I see in the nation’s history is a nuanced
    approach toward gun possession, ownership, and use. The
    Second Amendment’s history and tradition are steeped in a
    rich regulatory background. For what it is worth, I would say
    exactly the same thing about the First Amendment, which the
    Court has often equated to the Second Amendment. Although
    Justice Hugo Black was famous for taking a strict view of the
    First Amendment, insisting that the words “NO LAW” with
    which it begins meant literally “NO LAW,” the truth is that
    the First Amendment has always been circumscribed by lim-
    iting principles. The Supreme Court understands that a per-
    son cannot shout “FIRE” in a crowded theater, see Schenck v.
    United States, 
    249 U.S. 47
     (1919); that “fighting words” are not
    protected, see Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 
    315 U.S. 568
    (1942); that a person who credibly issues a verbal threat to kill
    the President may be prosecuted, see Rankin v. McPherson, 
    483 U.S. 378
     (1987); that obscenity and child pornography do not
    qualify as protected speech, see Miller v. California, 
    413 U.S. 15
    (1973) (obscenity), New York v. Ferber, 
    458 U.S. 747
     (1982)
    (child pornography); and that the First Amendment did not
    totally displace common-law libel and slander, see New York
    Times Co. v. Sullivan, 
    376 U.S. 254
     (1964). The Second Amend-
    ment is the same: while it robustly protects the right of law-
    abiding citizens to keep and bear arms for self-defense, sport,
    and other lawful uses, it does not categorically displace all
    other laws—not laws regulating the terms and conditions that
    govern lawful firearm ownership, including the types of
    weapons that may be possessed, and not laws governing the
    situations under which those pre-existing rights may be for-
    feited.
    No. 22-1557                                                  25
    C
    History and tradition bear this out. Gun ownership and
    use in this country (both before and after the adoption of the
    1787 Constitution) have always been subject to reasonable
    regulations. Joseph Blocher & Darrell A.H. Miller, The Positive
    Second Amendment: Rights, Regulation, and the Future of Heller
    4 (2018) (“[T]he [Second Amendment] protects some private
    purposes, and … it is and has always been subject to regula-
    tion.”). Moreover, while I recognize that we must not allow
    the prefatory clause of the Second Amendment—the one that
    highlights the role of a well-regulated militia—to assume un-
    due importance, it is equally true that we are not at liberty to
    delete words from the Constitution. History demands that we
    give each part appropriate weight.
    Long before the United States of America was a gleam in
    anyone’s eye, there was a close relation in England between,
    on the one side, the right of citizens to have arms and, on the
    other side, their responsibility to answer the King’s call for
    armed forces when the need arose. Indeed, as Joyce Lee Mal-
    colm writes, originally the “bearing” of arms was a duty owed
    to higher political authorities, not an individual right against
    those authorities. See Joyce Lee Malcolm, To Keep and Bear
    Arms: The Origins of an Anglo-American Right 1 (1994). The in-
    tertwining of right and duty had an effect on the types of arms
    people were allowed to keep. Arms that, in times of need,
    could be used in the militia, could also be retained at home
    for self-defense and for hunting (though not poaching—the
    latter would result in the deprivation of the right to keep the
    weapon). And it was from those seeds that the individual
    right recognized in Heller originally grew. But note how
    closely related to militia service the scope of the right is. As
    26                                                    No. 22-1557
    one commentator noted, there is no way to disentangle the
    private right to bear arms from the history of the King’s right
    to call upon a civilian militia to protect the state. Saul Cornell,
    A Well Regulated Right: The Early American Origins of Gun Con-
    trol, 
    73 Fordham L. Rev. 487
    , 503 (2004).
    As far back as the Middle Ages, Englishmen were required
    to participate in local peacemaking. Malcolm, To Keep and Bear
    Arms at 1 (who describes this duty as existing since “time out
    of mind”). As Malcolm notes, “[t]he requirement to raise a
    ‘hue and cry’ dates from at least the thirteenth century. A writ
    of 1252 explained that upon the raising of the cry neighbours
    [sic] were to turn out with weapons they were bound to keep.”
    
    Id.
     at 181 n.4. This operated as an obligation or a duty, not as
    a right to own weaponry. It was also seen as a tax of sorts,
    because subjects were required to use their own funds to pur-
    chase and maintain their weapons. The feudal lord monitored
    their compliance, and it was the lord (later the governing po-
    litical authority) who had the right to call upon the militia to
    its defense. This right included the power to govern private
    arms—who had to keep weapons, what those persons had to
    keep, and how the weapons were stored.
    By the time the colonies were organizing themselves into
    the United States of America, the status of the right had also
    evolved in England. In particular, as the Supreme Court
    pointed out in Bruen, England experienced its Glorious Revo-
    lution in 1688, in the wake of James II’s tumultuous reign. The
    next year, with William III and Mary II securely on the throne,
    Parliament passed the Declaration of Rights, which enshrined
    basic civil liberties and royal succession, as well as parliamen-
    tary privilege. See Eng. Bill of Rights 1 Will. & Mar. Sess. 2,
    c. 2 (1689). Like the Magna Carta, the Declaration is one of the
    No. 22-1557                                                      27
    central documents that makes up Britain’s unwritten consti-
    tution. One of the “ancient rights and liberties” it mentions is
    the following: “Protestants may have arms for their defence
    suitable to their conditions and as allowed by law.” 
    Id.
     at Sess. 2,
    c. 2, cl. 7 (emphasis added). Not quite a ringing endorsement
    of an untrammeled right to keep and bear arms, it instead
    builds in the idea that this right exists “as allowed by law.”
    The purpose of this clause, according to historians, was to
    leave no doubt that it was Parliament that had regulatory
    power over firearms, not the Crown. See Carl T. Bogus, The
    Hidden History of the Second Amendment, 
    31 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 309
    , 379–82, 384 (1998). Parliament asserted this regulatory
    power in response to the turmoil surrounding James II’s ef-
    forts to disarm Protestants. The fear of James’s Catholicism
    was a major factor behind Parliament’s decision to turn the
    throne over to William of Orange and Mary, James II’s
    Protestant daughter, thereby ending the Stuart dynasty and
    ushering in the Hanovers. But it bears repeating: the concern
    was about who would regulate firearms—not whether they
    could be regulated.
    There is much more one could say about these historical
    practices, but for present purposes it is enough to note that,
    by the time of William and Mary, Parliament claimed the right
    to control weapons designed for the militia but held in private
    hands. It is also worth noting that the standing British Army
    was founded in the mid-17th century, around the same time.
    When the time came to draft our own Bill of Rights, the
    militia tradition, as well as the role of standing armies, was a
    central concern for the American colonists. James Madison, in
    Federalist 46, wrote that any federal army could be checked
    by the (populist) militia. This was a point that reassured those
    28                                                  No. 22-1557
    who feared the power of the federal government to compro-
    mise the sovereignty of the states. It is notable that the Decla-
    ration of Independence includes, among the list of grievances
    against King George III, that “He has kept among us, in times
    of peace, Standing Armies without the Consent of our legisla-
    tures.”
    These concerns persisted even as the need for a standing
    army became clear. During the Revolutionary War, George
    Washington was continually begging the Second Continental
    Congress to professionalize the army. He did so because the
    colonial militias were less reliable; they had short periods of
    enlistment and members were free to return home when they
    chose. But Congress repeatedly resisted his importuning. Fur-
    thermore, the delegates at the Constitutional Convention had
    just lived through Shays’s Rebellion, an uprising of farmers
    protesting debt-collection courts in Massachusetts. The
    leader, Daniel Shays, led a group of 4,000 rebels that wanted
    to seize the state armory; the confederal government was un-
    able to muster a response and so the protestors were stopped
    by the Massachusetts State militia and a privately funded lo-
    cal militia. This incident was quite salient for the drafters of
    the Bill of Rights, who feared future rebellions: people were
    looking for assurance that the new Constitution would pro-
    vide a framework for an effective national defense. See Paul
    Finkelman, A Well Regulated Militia: The Second Amendment in
    Historical Perspective, 
    76 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 195
    , 196 (2000).
    These competing goals, of national security and the preserva-
    tion of state sovereignty, set the stage for the ratification de-
    bates. And in borrowing from the English Declaration of
    Rights when crafting the Second Amendment, the primary
    dispute among the Founders was over which political unit
    No. 22-1557                                                   29
    would regulate the civilian militias, not whether regulation
    was entirely off the table.
    For example, the Anti-Federalists expressed fears about
    the power of the new federal government. The Pennsylvania
    Anti-Federalists proposed several constitutional amendments
    to check federal power and the threat of the standing federal
    army. Some of those amendments were designed to address
    private weapons ownership, but many were focused on the
    proper allocation of power. The topics included: (1) the right
    of self-protection through the ownership of weapons; (2) the
    right to serve in the militia; (3) the right to hunt and fish; (4)
    the prevention of a standing army; (5) the power of Congress
    over the states; and (6) the power of the states to control their
    own armies or militias. Finkelman, A Well Regulated Militia, at
    208–09. Although private rights were surely implicated in
    these proposals, so too was state sovereignty and the power
    of the state to control the militia. Anti-Federalists feared that
    the militia “would be under control of the president and the
    Senate” (rather than the states), and that the national govern-
    ment might even destroy the militia. 
    Id. at 224
    .
    Other militia-related concerns that were reflected in the
    Second Amendment were, from a modern perspective, more
    shameful. Southern states feared that federal control of armed
    force might compromise their ability to deal with rebelling
    slaves. See Bogus, The Hidden History of the Second Amendment,
    at 332–34. Those same states relied on (and wanted to con-
    tinue relying on) their militias to control the growing popula-
    tion of enslaved Black people. One author observed that many
    Southern militias “were transformed into slave patrols.”
    Blocher & Miller, The Positive Second Amendment at 36 (quoting
    Adam Winkler, Gunfight: The Battle Over the Right to Bear Arms
    30                                                  No. 22-1557
    in America 133 (2009)). They accordingly wanted to ensure
    their ability to police their enslaved populations by retaining
    control of their militias.
    The pre-constitutional understanding reflected in the Sec-
    ond Amendment thus had two key elements: the history of
    the institution of a civilian militia in the Anglo-American tra-
    dition; and the individual right to own, carry, and use “arms.”
    The public meaning of the Amendment thus includes ele-
    ments of both sources. The individual right existed, to be sure,
    but it was subject to regulation, as the Constitution itself ex-
    pressly notes. The federal government was given the power
    to “call[] forth the Militia to execute the Laws of the Union,
    suppress Insurrections, and repel Invasions,” see U.S. Const.
    art. I, § 8, while the states retained their police power over
    state militias and were empowered to prevent federal dis-
    armament of individual citizens. This structure makes gun
    laws all but inevitable, and indeed, at the time the Constitu-
    tion was written (1787) and the Second Amendment was rati-
    fied (1791), laws regulating gun possession and use were
    ubiquitous in the new country.
    D
    Out of this tradition, one can find a vast and diverse array
    of gun laws stretching from the colonial period, through the
    Founding Era, through Reconstruction (when the Fourteenth
    Amendment was added to the Constitution and ultimately
    made the Second Amendment applicable to state regulation),
    up to the present day. This is what makes up the text, history,
    and tradition to which Bruen directs us. And text, history, and
    tradition all point in the same direction: firearms have always
    been regulated in precisely the ways that concern us in the
    third decade of the 21st century. That includes what types of
    No. 22-1557                                                  31
    weapons may be owned privately; what formalities may or
    must accompany the purchase of weapons; and which groups
    of people are categorically restricted from firearm ownership
    and use, on account of such disqualifying factors as mental
    health, criminal record, loyalty, and character. Naturally, reg-
    ulation on any of these grounds cannot be a pretext for
    measures that would impair the rights of law-abiding, men-
    tally stable, mature members of the polity. But that does not
    mean that every restriction must be assessed on a person-by-
    person basis, any more than the First Amendment demands
    that the right to have and produce child pornography must
    be assessed on an individual basis. Nor does it mean that cat-
    egorical restrictions are not subject to independent constitu-
    tional provisions. The days are long gone when the legislature
    can prohibit Catholics from having guns (as Parliament did
    during the Stuart era), and it would be equally reprehensible
    to ban gun ownership based on race, sexual orientation, disa-
    bility, or other protected characteristics.
    A closer look at the types of regulation that were pervasive
    in the states in the late 18th century supports this conclusion.
    Around the time of the American Revolution through the
    drafting and adoption of the Constitution and the Bill of
    Rights, gun regulations covered three principal topics: (1)
    storage, (2) militias, and (3) loyalty. There was robust regula-
    tion surrounding the storage and transport of gunpowder.
    These laws were “enacted to protect the growing population
    centers, such as Boston, Philadelphia, and New York City.”
    Cornell, A Well Regulated Right, at 511–12. The laws included
    limits on the amount of gunpowder a person could possess,
    rules about where powder could lawfully be stored, and laws
    for safe transport. Id. These laws also relied on state police
    32                                                             No. 22-1557
    powers to require forfeiture of firearms that were improperly
    stored. Id. at 512.
    The militia laws in the 18th century were both extensive
    and comprehensive. They dictated who was expected to serve
    in the militia, as well as the obligations that accompanied that
    service. Id. at 509. (And always recall that the militia was seen
    as the alternative to the dreaded standing army—it was an al-
    ternative much closer to the people and much less likely to
    support an out-of-control Executive.) Those subject to militia
    service had to turn out for regular musters, had to possess the
    required equipment, and were subject to regular arms inspec-
    tions. Id. at 509–10.
    Finally, loyalty oaths did not die with the 1689 English
    Declaration of Rights or with the passage of the colonists to
    the New World. During the American Revolution, several
    states passed laws providing for the confiscation of weapons
    owned by persons who refused to swear an oath of allegiance
    to the state or to the United States. Id. at 506. 1 The practice of
    disarming those whose loyalty was questionable continued
    after the Revolution. Those who refused to swear to a loyalty
    oath were forced to deliver their weapons to the state. Id. at
    507–08.
    Looked at another way, these laws touched on six distinct
    areas of regulation. See Eugene Volokh, Implementing the Right
    to Keep and Bear Arms for Self-Defense: An Analytical Framework
    and a Research Agenda, 
    56 UCLA L. Rev. 1443
     (2009). Each of
    1 See, e.g., 
    1778 Pa. Laws 123
    , ch. LXI, § 5 (requiring those who refused
    to take an oath to forfeit their arms and ammunition); Act of May 5, 1777,
    ch. 3, 9 Hening’s Statutes at Large 281, 281–82 (Virginia law disarming
    those who refused to give “assurance of Allegiance”).
    No. 22-1557                                                  33
    these types has existed throughout American history—nota-
    bly, at the time of the Founding and in the mid-19th century,
    the critical times identified in Bruen:
    a) The “what”: restrictions on the kinds of weapons
    that could be privately possessed. Id. at 1475.
    b) The “who”: restrictions on who was allowed to own
    weapons. Id. at 1493.
    c) The “where”: restrictions on the places in which
    weapons could be carried. Id. at 1515.
    d) The “how”: restrictions on places weapons could be
    stored. Id. at 1534.
    e) The “when”: restrictions on the times during which
    weapons could be carried. Id. at 1535.
    f) Miscellaneous: regulations focused on licensing,
    permitting, and sales. Id. at 1542, 1545.
    III
    This overview has barely scratched the surface of the out-
    pouring of scholarship on the origins and meaning of the Sec-
    ond Amendment, but it is enough to permit me to move on to
    the task Bruen has given us: to demonstrate that the statute
    under consideration, 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1), is “consistent with
    this Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation.” 142 S.
    Ct. at 2126. This, as I noted earlier, can only be a question of
    law, just like any determination of the meaning of a constitu-
    tional provision or a statute, and just like the determination
    of the meaning of a foreign law, see Fed. R. Civ. P. 44.1.
    The assessment of any gun regulation should begin with a
    look at the type of measure under consideration: to use Pro-
    fessor Volokh’s taxonomy, is it a “what, who, where, how, or
    34                                                  No. 22-1557
    when” regulation? Once we know that, we can begin the task
    of identifying the proper historical analogues. For example,
    felon disarmament is a “who” restriction. That directs us to
    historical restrictions on the classes of persons who were al-
    lowed to own or possess guns. In addition, one needs to look
    at the regulatory method the statute embodies: total disarma-
    ment for life; disarmament for a term of years; qualified rights
    to have the weapon with proper sureties; restrictions on par-
    ticularly sensitive places (courthouses, churches, schools) or
    times or manner (open-carry, concealed-carry). Throughout
    all of this, one must also bear in mind that Bruen does not de-
    mand historical “dead ringers.” It is enough to identify a
    problem with private gun ownership and find the relevantly
    similar type of solution that was thought to be adequate by
    our forebears.
    Bruen also asks courts to focus on “how and why the reg-
    ulation burdens a law-abiding citizen’s right to armed self-
    defense.” 142 S. Ct. at 2133. If a certain burden was under-
    stood to be acceptable in the period immediately preceding
    independence, going up to 1791 when the Bill of Rights was
    adopted, then we are safe in concluding that the pre-existing
    right enshrined in the Second Amendment incorporates that
    qualification.
    Applying that approach, one sees that the courts have long
    recognized that “[t]he preservation of the public peace, and
    the protection of the people against violence, are constitu-
    tional duties of the legislature, and the guarantee of the right
    to keep and bear arms is to be understood and construed in
    connection and in harmony with these constitutional duties.”
    Hill v. State, 
    53 Ga. 472
    , 377 (1874); see also Joseph Blocher &
    Reva B. Siegel, Guided by History: Protecting the Public Sphere
    No. 22-1557                                                               35
    from Weapons Threats under Bruen, 
    98 N.Y.U. L. Rev. __
     (forth-
    coming 2023) at 8.
    With the open-mindedness that the historical approach in-
    herently reflects, we have not only the right, but the obliga-
    tion, to look carefully at the record behind the felon disenti-
    tlement statutes. That record reveals that, since the founding,
    governments have been understood to have the power to sin-
    gle out categories of persons who will face total disarmament
    based on the danger they pose to the political community if
    armed. That presumptive power is on display in the loyalty
    oath laws previously discussed, and in the laws that disarmed
    persons found guilty of treason and members of native
    tribes. 2 Though some of those laws would no longer pass
    muster under the Equal Protection Clause, they reveal conclu-
    sively the scope of governmental power that was understood
    to exist at the time the Second Amendment was adopted. This
    power allowed the creation of categorical restrictions without
    any case-by-case escape hatch. Section 922(g)(1) does pre-
    cisely what statutes have been doing since the mid-18th
    2  For the laws regarding the disarmament of native people, see, e.g.,
    1723 Conn. Acts 292 (preventing the sale of firearms to Indians); 1757–68
    Md. Acts 53, ch. 4, § 3 (same); 
    1763 Pa. Laws 319
    , § 1 (same); Laws of the
    Colony of Massachusetts 492 (1769) (same); Statutes of the Mississippi Ter-
    ritory, Indian Intercourse, § 9 (1807) (same); 
    1844 Mo. Laws 577
    , ch. 80, § 4
    (same); 
    1853 Or. Laws 257
    , § 1 (same); Statute Law of the State of Florida,
    For the Prevention of Indians Roaming at Large Throughout the State, § 1
    (1847) (authorizing the seizure of arms from Indians found beyond reser-
    vation borders). For other laws disarming an entire category of persons,
    see, e.g., 
    1776 Pa. Laws 11
    , § 1 (disarming all non-associators, the American
    colonists who refused to sign militia association charters); 
    1787 Mass. Acts 555
    , ch. IV (disarming all persons found guilty of treason or aiding rebel-
    lion, even after pardon by the governor and an oath of allegiance).
    36                                                            No. 22-1557
    century. It identifies the group of persons deemed dangerous
    to the political community—those convicted of the defined
    felonies—and it makes it unlawful for them to possess a fire-
    arm. 3 To the extent people in that group want to contest the
    suitability of the dangerousness label to their situation, that is
    once again an equal protection argument and not an argu-
    ment about the scope of government authority under the Sec-
    ond Amendment.
    Though I am satisfied with these historical analogues, I
    understand that there remain several open questions about
    how to evaluate today’s gun laws. The Supreme Court’s anal-
    ysis in Bruen could not have been intended to be the last word
    on historical analysis relevant to the Second Amendment. In-
    stead, it set the methodological stage. There have been schol-
    arly criticisms of its assumption that three colonial-era regu-
    lations do not suffice to establish a historical tradition and its
    decision not to give any weight to the territorial laws. These
    critiques may be well taken, but it is not my purpose today to
    confront them. They can be useful to a lower-court judge in-
    sofar as they highlight what evidence is needed and why the
    Bruen majority found the record in that case insufficient to
    save the New York law in question. If three colonies out of 13
    isn’t enough, then what about four? Would the case have been
    different if population had been emphasized instead of polit-
    ical units? Given that territories were subjected to the
    3 Relief from that disability is possible through executive clemency. In
    addition, there is a mechanism that Congress has never chosen to activate
    that would permit the Attorney General to restore a person’s gun rights.
    See 
    18 U.S.C. § 925
    (c). While we certainly would have a different case be-
    fore us if section 925(c) were available, my argument does not depend on
    its existence.
    No. 22-1557                                                      37
    Constitution and the Bill of Rights even before the Fourteenth
    Amendment, what do the territorial laws tell us about legis-
    lating under the dictate of those documents? See Andrew
    Willinger, The Territories Under Text, History, and Tradition, 
    101 Wash. U. L. Rev. __
     (forthcoming 2023) at 27. Taking the Court
    at its word, new historical research should be welcome—just
    as it was when Justice Brandeis wrote Erie R.R. Co. v. Tomp-
    kins, 
    304 U.S. 64
     (1938) and highlighted what was then new
    research on the Rules of Decision Act.
    As other courts have begun to apply Bruen, this need for
    further research and further guidance has become clear. The
    Third, Fifth, Eighth, and Eleventh Circuits have all published
    precedential opinions discussing whether a challenged gun
    law is consistent with Bruen’s history and tradition test. See
    Range v. U.S. Attorney General, -- F.4th -- (3d Cir. 2023) (en banc)
    (in an as-applied challenge, enjoining enforcement of section
    922(g)(1) against someone who was convicted of a single, non-
    violent offense of making false statements on a food stamp
    application); United States v. Rahimi, 
    61 F.4th 443
     (5th Cir.
    2023) (holding section 922(g)(8)—which makes it unlawful to
    possess a firearm if under a court order related to domestic
    violence—unconstitutional); United States v. Jackson, -- F.4th -
    - (8th Cir. 2023) (upholding section 922(g)(1) as applied to
    people with prior drug felony convictions); United States v.
    Sitladeen, 
    64 F.4th 978
     (8th Cir. 2023) (upholding section
    922(g)(5)(A) which makes it unlawful for those who are ille-
    gally in the United States to possess a firearm); Nat’l Rifle Ass’n
    v. Bondi, 
    61 F.4th 1317
     (11th Cir. 2023) (upholding a Florida
    law that requires the purchaser of a gun to be 21 years old).
    These cases and their varying outcomes illustrate the chal-
    lenges created by Bruen—the Supreme Court threw down a
    38                                                    No. 22-1557
    gauntlet, and it is our job to take it up. For example, consider-
    ing only the question raised by section 922(g)(1), four courts
    have come out four different ways on its constitutionality. In
    Atkinson’s case, the majority is directing the district court to
    develop the historical record, without any notion of how
    much is enough. The Eighth Circuit conducted the evaluation
    in much the manner I suggest, noting the presumptive power
    to disarm categories of persons deemed dangerous, as illus-
    trated in laws that disarmed Native Americans, religious mi-
    norities, and those who refused to take a loyalty oath. See Jack-
    son, -- F.4th at *5. This led the Jackson court to conclude “his-
    tory demonstrates that there is no requirement for an individ-
    ualized determination of dangerousness as to each person in
    a class of prohibited persons.” 
    Id. at *6
    . The Third Circuit
    panel that originally heard Range agreed that section 922(g)(1)
    was constitutional but came to that determination because
    people “whose criminal records evince disrespect for the law
    are outside the community of law-abiding citizens entitled to
    keep and bear arms” and therefore the regulated conduct was
    not covered by the Second Amendment’s plain text. See 
    53 F.4th 262
    , 273 (3d. Cir. 2022), vacated for rehearing, 
    56 F.4th 992
    (3d. Cir. 2023). Then on rehearing, a divided en banc Third Cir-
    cuit reversed course and decided that the history and tradi-
    tion of the Second Amendment did not support the disarming
    of a nonviolent felon.
    There is much more that one could say about these other
    circuit court opinions (not to mention countless thoughtful
    district-court opinions from courts around the country) and
    how they approached the analysis required by Bruen. Four
    outcomes in four cases demonstrates just how inconclusive
    this project will prove to be. The information available to us
    (inevitably filtered through the lens of each individual
    No. 22-1557                                                  39
    historian) does not reveal a definitive and original public
    meaning of the Second Amendment. All we can do is to con-
    sult the public record, discern the generally applicable princi-
    ples, and avoid unnecessary reliance on statutory minutiae.
    My own effort to do so convinces me that the pre-constitu-
    tional understanding of the right to keep and bear arms me-
    morialized in the Second Amendment came with an under-
    standing that the right existed only as to those arms “suitable
    to their conditions and as allowed by law.” Eng. Bill of Rights,
    supra.
    Further to that point, modern society has the same need as
    17th-century England and 18th-century America to restrict
    the right to keep and bear arms when a person ceases to be
    one of the law-abiding citizens entitled to have weapons for
    self-defense, hunting, and other lawful uses. For example,
    looking at 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(8), which bars gun possession for
    a person subject to a court-imposed domestic-violence re-
    straining order, we can easily see that Congress rationally
    concluded that such a person is not part of the law-abiding
    community of citizens. Reports indicate that 85 percent of in-
    timate partner violence victims are women and that this type
    of violence results in nearly 1,300 deaths a year. See Emory
    University School of Medicine Nia Project, Domestic Vio-
    lence/Intimate Partner Violence Facts, https://psychia-
    try.emory.edu/niaproject/resources/dv-facts.html. The Na-
    tional Coalition against Domestic Violence estimates that in
    2018, 1,014 women were killed by male intimate partners. Na-
    tional Coalition Against Domestic Violence, Domestic Vio-
    lence & Firearms 1 (2022) https://assets.speakcdn.com/as-
    sets/2497/guns_and_dv_2022.pdf. The Second Amendment
    leaves room for legislatures to take these facts into account,
    not as a matter of means/end scrutiny but as a matter of
    40                                                   No. 22-1557
    solving modern problems of lawlessness, with the same stat-
    utory tools—including categorical disarmament—that gov-
    ernments in this country used in the 18th and 19th centuries.
    IV
    As this brief discussion has shown, the right to keep and
    bear arms always has been subject to careful limitations.
    These limitations are at their zenith when applied to people
    who are the antithesis of the law-abiding citizen who wants
    to exercise his or her right to self-defense, whether at home or
    in public, and who may also enjoy the various sports and
    other activities that involve guns. Even under the English
    Declaration of Rights, no one thought anything of disarming
    people who were not loyal to the Crown, or who had commit-
    ted serious crimes (called felonies), or who had abused their
    gun rights (often by poaching on lands to which they had no
    right). This history and tradition follows an unbroken line
    from long before the Constitution was written, through the
    17th and 18th centuries up to the present day.
    If anything is clear, it is that the legislature (first Parlia-
    ment, and later Congress and the state bodies) was empow-
    ered to regulate guns through categorical restrictions. Some-
    times they exercised that power; sometimes (as with the
    surety laws) they chose to operate on an individualized basis.
    The choice between one mechanism or the other is a classic
    legislative option. Courts should not, in the name of the Sec-
    ond Amendment, be making that choice themselves.
    If today’s panel were to undertake the thorough historical
    analysis that Bruen demands, I would be happy to delve even
    more deeply into these materials. But I am fully satisfied,
    based on what I have addressed here and on the Supreme
    No. 22-1557                                                 41
    Court’s own use of history in Bruen, that 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1)
    is constitutional as written. I therefore would not remand this
    case to the district court. I would instead affirm its judgment
    and uphold the statute.