SUSAN LATTA v. C. L. OTTER ( 2015 )


Menu:
  •                                                                  FILED
    FOR PUBLICATION                        JAN 09 2015
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS             MOLLY C. DWYER, CLERK
    U.S. COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT
    SUSAN LATTA; TRACI EHLERS; LORI             No. 14-35420
    WATSEN; SHARENE WATSEN;
    SHELIA ROBERTSON; ANDREA                    D.C. No. 1:13-cv-00482-CWD
    ALTMAYER; AMBER BEIERLE;                    District of Idaho,
    RACHAEL ROBERTSON,                          Boise
    Plaintiffs - Appellees,
    ORDER
    v.
    C. L. OTTER, 'Butch'; Governor of the
    State of Idaho, in his official capacity,
    Defendant - Appellant,
    And
    CHRISTOPHER RICH, Recorder of Ada
    County, Idaho, in his official capacity,
    Defendant,
    STATE OF IDAHO,
    Intervenor-Defendant.
    SUSAN LATTA; TRACI EHLERS; LORI             No. 14-35421
    WATSEN; SHARENE WATSEN;
    SHELIA ROBERTSON; ANDREA                    D.C. No. 1:13-cv-00482-CWD
    ALTMAYER; AMBER BEIERLE;                    District of Idaho,
    RACHAEL ROBERTSON,                          Boise
    Plaintiffs - Appellees,
    v.
    C. L. OTTER, 'Butch'; Governor of the
    State of Idaho, in his official capacity,
    Defendant,
    And
    CHRISTOPHER RICH, Recorder of Ada
    County, Idaho, in his official capacity,
    Defendant - Appellant,
    STATE OF IDAHO,
    Intervenor-Defendant -
    Appellant.
    BEVERLY SEVCIK; MARY                        No. 12-17668
    BARANOVICH; ANTIOCO CARRILLO;
    THEODORE SMALL; KAREN GOODY;                D.C. No. 2:12-cv-00578-RCJ-PAL
    KAREN VIBE; FLETCHER                        District of Nevada,
    WHITWELL; GREG FLAMER;                      Las Vegas
    MIKYLA MILLER; KATRINA MILLER;
    ADELE TERRANOVA; TARA
    NEWBERRY; CAREN CAFFERATA-
    JENKINS; FARRELL CAFFERATA-
    JENKINS; MEGAN LANZ; SARA
    GEIGER,
    Plaintiffs - Appellants,
    v.
    BRIAN SANDOVAL, in his official
    capacity as Governor of the State of
    Nevada; DIANA ALBA, in her official
    capacity as the County Clerµ and
    Commissioner of Civil Marriages for
    Clarµ County, Nevada; AMY HARVEY,
    in her official capacity as the County Clerµ
    and Commissioner of Civil Marriages for
    Washoe County, Nevada; ALAN
    GLOVER, in his official capacity as the
    Clerµ Recorder for Carson City, Nevada,
    Defendants - Appellees,
    And
    COALITION FOR THE PROTECTION
    OF MARRIAGE,
    Intervenor-Defendant -
    Appellee.
    Before: REINHARDT, GOULD, and BERZON, Circuit Judges.
    The panel has voted to deny the petitions for rehearing en banc.
    The full court was advised of the petitions for rehearing en banc. A judge
    requested a vote on whether to rehear the matter en banc. The matter failed to
    receive a majority of the votes of the nonrecused active judges in favor of en banc
    reconsideration. Fed. R. App. P. 35.
    The petitions for rehearing en banc are denied.
    FILED
    Latta v. Otter, Nos. 14-35420, 14-35421;                                     JAN 09 2015
    Sevciµ v. Sandoval, No. 12-17668                                        MOLLY C. DWYER, CLERK
    U.S. COURT OF APPEALS
    O'SCANNLAIN, Circuit Judge, joined by RAWLINSON and BEA, Circuit
    Judges, dissenting from the denial of rehearing en banc::
    One month after the panel in these cases strucµ down the traditional
    marriage laws of Idaho and Nevada, the Sixth Circuit upheld the essentially
    identical laws of Michigan, Ohio, Tennessee, and Kentucµy. See DeBoer v.
    Snyder, 
    772 F.3d 388
     (6th Cir. 2014). Clearly the same-sex marriage debate is not
    over. Indeed, not only does the debate now divide the federal circuit courts and
    state legislatures, but it continues to divide the American public.1 And, of course,
    1
    See, e.g.,
    http://www.nbcnews.com/politics/elections/2014/US/house/exitpoll (showing that
    in exit polling at the November 2014 election, respondents were equally divided,
    48û-48û, on the question of whether same-sex marriage should be legally
    recognized in their state).
    The debate even divides the globe--and the DeBoer majority is in
    agreement with one of the world's most prominent human rights' tribunals. Only a
    few months ago, the European Court of Human Rights, hardly a hotbed of hardline
    conservatism, made clear that the European Convention for the Protection of
    Human Rights and Fundamental Freedom 'enshrines the traditional concept of
    marriage as being between a man and a woman,' and 'cannot be interpreted as
    imposing an obligation on Contracting States to grant same-sex couples access to
    marriage.' H772 F.3d 388
    .
    Whether my colleagues agree or disagree with the DeBoer majority, at the very
    least, the panel should have granted rehearing to address the points raised in that
    Notably, even the dissenters on the particular issue before the
    court--recognition of a married person's change in gender identity--agreed that
    'States have a legitimate interest in protecting marriage in the traditional sense by
    legally reserving marriage to heterosexual partners.' Id. at *34 (Joint Dissenting
    Opinion of Judges Sajs, Keller, and Lemmens).
    2
    What the Supreme Court has decided is that the federal courts should not
    intrude, as the panel does here, on the choices of state electorates regarding
    whether to define marriage as a male-female union. Baµer v. Nelson, 
    409 U.S. 810
    (1972); see Part I, infra.
    2
    opinion. Instead, we have utterly ignored another circuit's reasoned contribution to
    the debate. Such a clear circuit split on such an exceptionally important issue
    demands en banc review.3
    Because the panel opinion neglects to address the issues raised in the
    conflicting Sixth Circuit opinion, and 1) overlooµs binding Supreme Court
    precedent, 2) fails to respect bedrocµ principles of democratic self-governance, and
    3) ignores the adverse implications of its opinion on our federal structure, I must
    respectfully dissent from our decision not to rehear these cases en banc.
    I
    Even if the exceptional importance of the issues and the circuit split were
    somehow insufficient to warrant our rehearing these cases en banc, we still should
    have concluded rehearing was merited. The panel fails to follow the Supreme
    Court's precedential command that federal courts must avoid substituting their
    own definition of marriage for that adopted by the states' citizenry. By refusing to
    3
    See F.R.A.P. 35(b)(1)(B) (explaining that 'a petition may assert that a
    proceeding presents a question of exceptional importance if it involves an issue on
    which the panel decision conflicts with the authoritative decisions of other United
    States Courts of Appeals'); see also Groves v. Ring Screw Worµs, 
    498 U.S. 168
    ,
    172 n.8 (1990) (citing 'a square conflict in the Circuits,' as grounds for maµing
    rehearing en banc 'appropriate'); Ninth Circuit Rule 35-1 (explaining that a direct
    conflict with another court of appeals 'is an appropriate ground for petitioning for
    rehearing en banc').
    3
    rectify this error, we let stand an impermissible judicial intrusion into a debate
    reserved to the states' political processes.
    A
    For decades, our nation has engaged in an 'earnest and profound debate' on
    marriage policy. See Washington v. Glucµsberg, 
    521 U.S. 702
    , 735 (1997)
    (praising the American public's on-going conversation on the 'morality, legality,
    and practicality of physician-assisted suicide' and ultimately declining to
    interfere); see also Hollingsworth v. Perry, 
    133 S. Ct. 2652
    , 2659 (2013) ('The
    public is currently engaged in an active political debate over whether same-sex
    couples should be allowed to marry.'). State by state, citizens have considered the
    issue of same-sex marriage and, through legislation, popular referendum, or
    constitutional amendment, voiced their views on this question of immense public
    importance.4
    Until quite recently, the judiciary has allowed this earnest democratic debate
    to continue unobstructed. Forty-two years ago, the Supreme Court dismissed an
    appeal from a Minnesota Supreme Court decision, Baµer v. Nelson, which held that
    4
    To date, thirteen states and the District of Columbia have extended the
    traditional definition of marriage to include same-sex couples by statute or ballot
    initiative. See infra footnote 9. Many other states, including Idaho and Nevada,
    have used their democratic processes to retain the traditional definition of
    marriage.
    4
    '[t]he equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, liµe the due process
    clause, is not offended by the state's classification of persons authorized to marry.'
    
    191 N.W.2d 185
    , 187 (Minn. 1971) (emphasis added). Dismissing the plaintiffs'
    appeal 'for want of a substantial federal question,' 409 U.S. at 810 (emphasis
    added), the Baµer Court confirmed that the Constitution commits questions of
    marriage policy to the citizens of each state, and that absent exceptional
    circumstances, federal courts should resist the temptation to interfere with a state
    marriage regulation.
    This is not to say that a state's 'powers to regulate marriage are unlimited
    notwithstanding the commands of the Fourteenth Amendment.' Loving v.
    Virginia, 
    388 U.S. 1
    , 7 (1967). There are clearly exceptional circumstances in
    which judicial interference is needed--no more so than when a husband and wife
    face criminal sanctions merely for marrying when they happen to be of different
    races. See 
    id.
    But while 'invidious racial discriminations' warranted judicial action in
    Loving v. Virginia, no such discrimination is implicated here.5 Indeed, to argue
    that Loving controls here requires asserting that the Supreme Court forgot about
    5
    Indeed, the panel majority--though not Judge Reinhardt, see Latta v. Otter,
    No. 14-35420, slip op. at 1 (9th Cir. Oct. 7, 2014) (Reinhardt, J.,
    concurring)--does not rest its decision on Loving.
    5
    Loving only five years later when it decided Baµer. If the panel had any lingering
    doubts as to whether judicial interference is appropriate, Baµer maµes clear that it
    is not.
    B
    Loving holds that 'restricting the freedom to marry solely because of racial
    classifications violates the central meaning of the Equal Protection Clause' and
    that the 'Fourteenth Amendment requires that the freedom of choice to marry not
    be restricted by invidious racial discriminations.' Loving, 
    388 U.S. at 12
    . Thus,
    Loving stands as a clear prohibition on racial discrimination in laws defining and
    regulating marriage, but it simply does not follow that Loving also somehow
    prevents the states from defining marriage as a union of a man and a woman.
    Indeed state laws that define marriage as a union of a man and a woman bear
    little resemblance to the Virginia statute that criminalized Mildred and Richard
    Loving's marriage merely because Mildred was blacµ and Richard was white. 
    Id. at 11
    . Virginia recognized that Mildred and Richard had married in the District of
    Columbia, but 'to maintain White Supremacy,' 
    id.,
     the state legislature chose to
    punish them for having the courage to do so.
    Chief Justice Warren recognized that such punishment contravened the
    constitutional command that 'the freedom of choice to marry not be restricted by
    6
    invidious racial discriminations.' 
    Id. at 12
    . But it is difficult to draw from this
    holding the conclusion that Loving is 'directly on point,' Latta, slip op. at 3
    (Reinhardt, J., concurring), as to whether marriage may be defined as an opposite-
    sex relationship.
    Of course, states are not compelled to define marriage as such an opposite-
    sex union--simply looµ to the many states that, since Loving, have defined it by
    statute or popular vote to extend to gay and lesbian couples.6 But states are also
    not compelled by the federal Constitution to define marriage differently than the
    'generally accepted' opposite-sex relationship Mildred and Richard sought to enter
    in Loving. See Loving, 
    388 U.S. at 11
    ; cf. Bishop v. Smith, 
    760 F.3d 1070
    ,
    1108-09 (10th Cir. 2014) (Holmes, J., concurring) (explaining that Oµlahoma's
    codification of marriage as an opposite-sex relationship 'cannot sensibly be
    depicted as 'unusual' where the State was simply exercising its age-old police
    power to define marriage in the way that it, along with every other State, always
    had' and noting that Oµlahoma's law 'formalized a definition that every State had
    employed for almost all of American history, and it did so in a province the states
    had always dominated'); H388 U.S. at 12
    .
    C
    It is utterly unsurprising then, that only five years after Loving, when the
    viability of the 'generally accepted' opposite-sex definition of marriage was
    squarely before the Court, the Court concluded no substantial federal question was
    implicated. Baµer, 
    409 U.S. 810
    . Such a conclusion was completely consistent
    with Loving: there simply is no conflict in holding both that the Constitution
    prohibits racial restrictions on the right to enter marriage, and that the Constitution
    is not offended by a state's choice to define marriage as an opposite-sex
    relationship.
    Of course we cannot ignore Chief Justice Marshall's observation, as true as
    7
    Notwithstanding my views on the applicability of foreign law in the
    analysis of constitutional terms, see Diarmuid F. O'Scannlain, What Role Should
    Foreign Practice and Precedent Play in the Interpretation of Domestic Lawá, 80
    NOTRE DAME L. REV. 1893 (2005), marriage is not defined in the U.S.
    Constitution, and it is telling that the ECHR has left such a fundamental issue to be
    resolved by member-states rather than via judicial fiat.
    8
    ever, that if 'the Courts are to regard the Constitution, and the Constitution is
    superior to any ordinary act of the Legislature, the Constitution, and not such
    ordinary act, must govern the case to which they both apply.' Marbury v.
    Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 177 (1803).
    We must asµ, then: Is leaving the political process intact here not an
    impermissible abdication of our 'authority, and indeed [] responsibility, to right
    fundamental wrongs left excused by a majority of the electorateá' DeBoer, 772
    F.3d at 436-37 (Daughtrey, J., dissenting). Is this situation not analogous to those,
    where, even while recognizing 'that certain matters requiring political judgments
    are best left to the political branches,' we must ensure that courts and not the
    political branches, 'say what the law isá' Boumediene v. Bush, 
    553 U.S. 723
    , 765
    (2008) (citing Marbury, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) at 177).
    Simply put, no. We are a Court of Appeals, not the Supreme Court, and our
    obligation is to
    adhere to the view that if the Court has branded a question as
    unsubstantial, it remains so except when doctrinal developments indicate
    otherwise. . . . [T]he lower courts are bound by summary decisions by th[e
    Supreme] Court until such time as the Court informs [them] that [they] are
    not.
    Hicµs v. Miranda, 
    422 U.S. 332
    , 344-45 (1975) (citations omitted).
    Far from avoiding our responsibilities, following Baµer here constitutes the
    9
    only permissible exercise of our limited authority--the eagerness of the panel
    members to pronounce their views on the merits of same-sex marriage
    notwithstanding.8 When the Supreme Court 'concludes [an] appeal should be
    dismissed because the constitutional challenge' presented 'was not a substantial
    one,' it maµes a precedential decision on the merits. Hicµs, 
    422 U.S. at
    344 (citing
    Ohio ex rel. Eaton v. Price, 
    360 U.S. 246
    , 247 (1959); R. Stern & E. Gressman,
    Supreme Court Practice 197 (4th ed. 1969); C. Wright, Law of Federal Courts 495
    (2d ed. 1970)).
    Indeed, when 'a precedent of th[e Supreme] Court has direct application in a
    case,' we must follow it even if it 'appears to rest on reasons rejected in some
    other line of decisions.' Rodriguez de Ïuijas v. Shearson/AMEÈ, Inc., 
    490 U.S. 477
    , 484 (1989). '[T]he Court of Appeals should follow the case which directly
    8
    It is questionable whether judicial intrusion on the peoples' political choices
    is truly an effective means of advancing the same-sex marriage cause. As one legal
    academic and same-sex marriage supporter explains:
    Court victories are hollow victories for the LGBT community, failing to
    deliver the societal respect they seeµ, and in fact removing the opportunity
    for collective expression of such respect through voluntary legislative
    reform or popular referendum.
    James G. Dwyer, Same-Sex Cynicism and the Self-Defeating Pursuit of Social
    Acceptance Through Litigation, 68 S.M.U. L. REV. ÁÁÁ (forthcoming 2015).
    Courts 'cannot deliver the type of dignity that comprises social respect'--in fact
    'a judicial victory obviates legislative change, and therefore collective or
    majoritarian expression of respect.' 
    Id.
    10
    controls, leaving to [the Supreme] Court the prerogative of overruling its own
    decisions.' 
    Id.
     Baµer is a precedential disposition on the merits which Hicµs and
    Rodriguez de Ïuijas maµe clear we are not at liberty to disregard.
    The panel ignores Rodriguez de Ïuijas and attempts to turn the command of
    Hicµs on its head. Rather than heeding the clear statement that 'the lower courts
    are bound by summary decisions by th[e Supreme] Court until such time as the
    Court informs [them] that [they] are not,' the panel searches for 'doctrinal
    developments' that, when interpreted just so, imply that Baµer is no longer good
    law. Apparently the panel believes the Supreme Court, rather than speaµing
    clearly when it overrules dispositions on the merits, 'informs' the lower courts of
    an overruling with so many winµs and nods.
    Unfortunately, the panel is not without company in its approach. See, e.g.,
    Basµin v. Bogan, 
    766 F.3d 648
    , 659-60 (7th Cir. 2014) (doctrinal developments
    preclude application of Baµer); Bostic v. Schaefer, 
    760 F.3d 352
    , 373-75 (4th Cir.
    2014) (same); Bishop, 760 F.3d at 1079-81 (same); Kitchen v. Herbert, 
    755 F.3d 1193
    , 1204-08 (10th Cir. 2014) (same).
    Yet neither am I. See, e.g., DeBoer, 772 F.3d at 399-402 (Baµer is still
    binding precedent); Massachusetts v. U.S. Dep't of Health & Human Servs., 
    682 F.3d 1
    , 8 (1st Cir. 2012) (same), cited in U. S. v. Windsor, 
    133 S. Ct. 2675
    , 2688,
    11
    2693 (2013); Conde-Vidal v. Garcia-Padilla, No. 14-1253 PG, 
    2014 WL 5361987
    , at *6 (D.P.R. Oct. 21, 2014) (same); cf., H133
    S.Ct. 2675
    , Lawrence v. Texas, 
    539 U.S. 558
     (2003), and Romer v. Evans, 
    517 U.S. 620
     (1996). But each of these cases presented distinctly different questions from
    whether a state may lawfully define marriage as between a man and a woman.
    1
    In Windsor, the Court strucµ down a federal law that intruded on a state's
    prerogative to define marriage, what the Court characterized as ''virtually [an]
    exclusive province of the States.'' Windsor, 133 S. Ct. at 2691 (quoting Sosna v.
    Iowa, 
    418 U.S. 393
    , 303 (1975)). If anything, Windsor's emphasis on the
    unprecedented federal intrusion into the states' authority over domestic relations
    12
    reaffirms Baµer's conclusion that a state's definition of marriage presents no
    'substantial federal question.' Baµer, 409 U.S. at 810. The Windsor opinion
    expressly 'confined [itself] to . . . lawful marriages' recognized by other states and
    disavowed having any effect on state laws which themselves regulate marriage.
    Windsor, 
    133 S. Ct. at 2696
    .
    2
    Liµewise, in Lawrence, the Court did not implicate Baµer when it strucµ
    down Texas's criminal anti-sodomy law on the ground that it interfered with
    personal autonomy. Liµe in Windsor, the Lawrence Court expressly stated that it
    was not deciding whether a state must recognize same-sex marriages. See
    Lawrence, 
    539 U.S. at 578
     ('The present case does not involve . . . whether the
    government must give formal recognition to any relationship that homosexual
    persons seeµ to enter.').
    3
    Similarly, Romer did not involve the definition of marriage, but rather a
    Colorado constitutional amendment that 'nullifie[d] specific legal protections for
    [homosexuals] in all transactions in housing, sale of real estate, insurance, health
    and welfare services, private education, and employment' as well as laws
    providing protection 'from discrimination by every level of Colorado
    13
    government.' Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 629
    . Such a '[s]weeping and comprehensive
    change' in Colorado law that withdrew existing anti-discrimination protections for
    homosexuals 'across the board' is easily distinguishable from a law defining
    marriage. 
    Id. at 627, 633
    ; see also Kenji Yoshino, The New Equal Protection, 124
    HARV. L. REV. 747, 777-78 (2011) (noting that 'the Court emphasized that Romer
    might be a ticµet good only for one day' as the amendment at issue effectuated an
    'unprecedented' harm).
    4
    Windsor, Lawrence, and Romer simply do not limit the states' authority to
    define marriage and certainly do not contradict Baµer's conclusion that the
    Constitution does not require states to recognize same-sex marriage. See Bishop,
    760 F.3d at 1104 (Holmes, J., concurring) (explaining that state laws defining
    marriage as between an opposite-sex couple are clearly distinguishable from those
    at issue in Romer and Windsor as they neither 'target[] the rights of a minority in a
    dangerously expansive and novel fashion' as in Romer, nor do they 'stray[] from
    the historical territory of the lawmaµing sovereign just to eliminate privileges that
    a group would otherwise receive,' as the federal law did in Windsor).
    Our place in the federal judicial hierarchy carries with it restrictions that,
    inconvenient as they may be to implementing our policy choices, restrain and
    14
    guide our discretion. We cannot ignore our obligation to follow Baµer's precedent.
    II
    Not only does the panel fail to abide by Supreme Court precedent, but, by
    injecting itself in the public's 'active political debate over whether same-sex
    couples should be allowed to marry,' Hollingsworth, 
    133 S. Ct. at 2659
    , it acts in
    a way Justice Kennedy has deemed 'inconsistent with the underlying premises of a
    responsible, functioning democracy.' Schuette v. Coalition to Defend Affirmative
    Action, 
    134 S.Ct. 1623
    , 1637 (2014) (plurality opinion). Rather than allow further
    change 'primarily [to] be made by legislative revision and judicial interpretation of
    the existing system,' the panel chooses to 'leap ahead--revising (or even
    discarding) the system by creating a new constitutional right and taµing over
    responsibility for refining it.' Dist. Attorney's Office for Third Judicial Dist. v.
    Osborne, 
    557 U.S. 52
    , 74 (2009). Such a leap should never be made lightly, yet
    here the panel taµes it without regard to the fact that our country's citizens have
    shown themselves quite capable of 'engag[ing] in serious, thoughtful
    examinations' of the issue of same-sex marriage. Glucµsberg, 
    521 U.S. at 719
    .
    In some states, democratic majorities have enacted laws that expand the
    traditional definition of marriage to include same-sex relationships. See Windsor,
    
    133 S. Ct. at 2710-11
     (noting, for example, that in Maryland, voters approved a
    15
    measure, by a vote of 52û to 48û, establishing that 'Maryland's civil marriage
    laws allow gay and lesbian couples to obtain a civil marriage license').9 In other
    states, voters have elected to retain the centuries-old, traditional idea that marriage
    is limited to opposite-sex couples. 
    Id.
     (noting a North Carolina constitutional
    amendment providing that '[m]arriage between one man and one woman is the
    only domestic legal union that shall be valid or recognized in this State'). Indeed,
    in Maine, citizens voted to reject same-sex marriage in 2009 (by a vote of 53û to
    47û) only to change course in 2012, voting to permit same-sex marriages by that
    same margin. 
    Id.
     It seems marriage-defining is a state-law issue that the states are
    quite capably handling through deliberation in their own state lawmaµing
    processes.10
    9
    See also Cal. Fam. Code y 300 (permitting same-sex marriage); Conn. Gen.
    Stat. Ann. y 46b-20a (same); Del. Code Ann. tit. 13, y 129 (same); Haw. Rev. Stat.
    y 572-1 (same); 750 Ill. Comp. Stat. Ann. 5/212 (same); Md. Code Ann., Fam.
    Law y 2-201 (same); Minn. Stat. Ann. y 517.01 (same); N.H. Rev. Stat. Ann. y
    5-C:42 (same); N.Y. Dom. Rel. Law y 10 (same); R.I. Gen. Laws Ann. y 15-1-1
    (same); V.T. Stat. Ann. tit. 15, y 8 (same); Wash. Rev. Code Ann. y 26.04.010
    (same). If marriage is to be extended to same-sex couples, our democratic
    institutions provide the proper means to effect such an extension.
    10
    State-by-state variances in marriage law, of course, are not limited to same-
    sex marriage. For instance, states have different age requirements. Compare Idaho
    Code Ann. y 32-202 (individuals must be 18 to marry without parental consent),
    with Miss. Code. Ann. y 93-1-5 (individuals must be 21). States also differ in their
    consanguinity requirements. Compare Idaho Code Ann. y 32-206 (prohibiting
    marriages between first cousins), with Cal. Fam. Code y 2200 (permitting such
    16
    The panel's opinion cuts short these 'earnest and profound debate[s],'
    silencing the voices of millions of engaged and politically active citizens.
    Glucµsberg, 
    521 U.S. at 735
    . By doing so, the panel suggests that citizens of
    Nevada and Idaho, indeed of the nation, are not capable of having this
    conversation, or of reaching the 'correct' conclusion. But such a view eschews the
    very foundational premises of democratic self-governance. As Justice Kennedy
    wrote in Schuette, 'It is demeaning to the democratic process to presume that the
    voters are not capable of deciding an issue of this sensitivity on decent and rational
    grounds . . . . Freedom embraces the right, indeed the duty, to engage in a rational,
    civic discourse in order to determine how best to form a consensus to shape the
    destiny of the Nation and its people.' Schuette, 
    134 S.Ct. at 1637
    .
    A
    Nothing about the issue of same-sex marriage exempts it from the general
    principle that it is the right of the people to decide for themselves important issues
    of social policy. On the contrary, the Court's decision in Windsor recognizes the
    importance to democratic self-government of letting the People debate marriage
    marriages). Other differences include whether states recognize or prohibit
    common law marriages. Compare Idaho Code Ann. y 32-201 (prohibiting common
    law marriages), with Mont. Code Ann. y 40-1-403 (permitting such marriages).
    Ïuery if the panel's holding nullifies such prohibitions as well.
    17
    policy. The Windsor Court reminded us that '[t]he dynamics of state government
    in the federal system are to allow the formation of consensus respecting the way
    the members of a discrete community treat each other in their daily contact and
    constant interaction with each other.' Windsor, 
    133 S. Ct. at 2692
    .
    Despite such express instruction from the High Court, the panel assumes it is
    its right, indeed its duty to reach the conclusion that it does. But recent
    developments suggest otherwise. As the Sixth Circuit's DeBoer decision reminds
    us, it is '[b]etter in this instance . . . to allow change through the customary
    political processes, in which the people, gay and straight aliµe, become the heroes
    of their own stories by meeting each other not as adversaries in a court system but
    as fellow citizens seeµing to resolve a new social issue in a fair-minded way.'
    DeBoer, 772 F.3d at 421; see also Garcia-Padilla, No. 14-1253 PG, 
    2014 WL 5361987
    , at *11 ('[O]ne basic principle remains: the people, acting through their
    elected representatives, may legitimately regulate marriage by law.'); Robicheaux
    v. Caldwell, 
    2 F.Supp.3d 910
    , 926-27 (E.D. La. 2014) (noting the importance of
    respecting democratic voices).11
    11
    Of course, blind deference to legislative majorities would be an abdication
    of our judicial duty. But, as explained in Part I, no such blind deference occurs
    when inferior courts follow Supreme Court precedent directly on point, the states
    have codified rational and long-accepted definitions of marriage, and the
    legislative process has shown itself to be capable of giving voice (and winning
    18
    The healthy, spirited, and engaged debate over marriage policy represents
    the virtues of democratic self-governance. The panel's opinion shuts down the
    debate, removing the issue from the public square. In so doing, it reflects a
    profound distrust in--or even a downright rejection of--our constitutional
    structure. As the Court warned in Osborne, this course of action 'taµes[s] the
    development of rules and procedures in this area out of legislatures and state courts
    shaping policy in a focused manner and turn[s] it over to federal courts applying
    the broad parameters of the [Fourteenth Amendment].' 
    557 U.S. at 56
    .
    Justice Powell, dissenting in the noted death penalty case Furman v.
    Georgia, warned of the 'shattering effect' such an approach has on the principles
    of 'federalism, judicial restraint and--most importantly--separation of powers.'
    
    408 U.S. 238
    , 417 (1972) (Powell, J., dissenting). Justice Powell acµnowledged
    that in situations where, as here, 'the language of the applicable provision provides
    great leeway and where the underlying social policies are felt to be of vital
    importance, the temptation to read personal preference into the Constitution is
    understandably great.' 
    Id.
     Nevertheless, he maintained that despite the
    temptation, 'it is not the business of [courts] to pronounce policy.' 
    Id.
     Here, the
    panel's inability to resist such temptation reflects a 'lacµ of faith and confidence in
    results) to both sides of the heretofore on-going conversation.
    19
    the democratic process.' Id. at 464-65.
    Federal courts have a 'proper--and properly limited--role' in a democratic
    society. Allen v. Wright, 
    468 U.S. 737
    , 750 (1984) (quoting Warth v. Seldin, 
    422 U.S. 490
    , 498 (1975)). When we artificially expand our role, not only does it flout
    the Constitution, it also has deleterious effects on the civic health of our country.
    We should not be so quicµ to presume we µnow what's best. Judicial humility in
    service of democratic self-rule is reason alone to rehear these cases en banc.
    III
    In addition to sweeping aside the virtues of democracy, the panel ignores our
    federal structure. The panel fails to recognize the principle that marriage law, liµe
    other areas of domestic relations, has been and should continue to be an area
    committed to the states. See Windsor, 
    133 S.Ct. at 2691-92
     ('State laws defining
    and regulating marriage, of course, must respect the constitutional rights of
    persons, but, subject to those guarantees, regulation of domestic relations is an area
    that has long been regarded as a virtually exclusive province of the States. . . . [T]he
    incidents, benefits, and obligations of marriage are uniform for all married couples
    within each State, though they may vary, subject to constitutional guarantees, from
    one State to the next.' (emphasis added)); U.S. Dep't of Health & Human Servs.,
    682 F.3d at 12 (explaining that 'DOMA intrudes extensively into a realm that has
    20
    from the start of the nation been primarily confided to state regulation--domestic
    relations and the definition and incidents of lawful marriage' (emphasis added)).
    The panel's opinion ignores this important aspect of Our Federalism.
    A
    'Long ago,' the Supreme Court 'observed that 'the whole subject of the
    domestic relations of husband and wife, parent and child, belongs to the laws of the
    States and not to the laws of the United States.'' Elµ Grove Unified Sch. Dist. v.
    Newdow, 
    542 U.S. 1
    , 12 (2004) (quoting In re Burrus, 
    136 U.S. 586
    , 593-94
    (1890)). Indeed, for over a century, federal courts have recognized that actions
    concerning domestic relations are entrusted to state legislatures and state courts.
    In the latest Supreme Court opinion addressing the issue of same-sex
    marriage, the Court gave a ringing endorsement of the central role of the states in
    fashioning their own marriage policy. Windsor, 133 S. Ct. at 2689-93. 'By
    history and tradition,' the Court stated in Windsor, 'the definition and regulation
    of marriage . . . has been treated as being within the authority and realm of the
    separate States.' Id. at 2689-90. Indeed, the Court continued, '[t]he recognition
    of civil marriages is central to state domestic relations law applicable to its
    residents and citizens.' Id. at 2691 (emphasis added); see also id. ('The definition
    of marriage is the foundation of the State's broader authority to regulate the subject
    21
    of domestic relations . . . .'); Williams v. North Carolina, 
    317 U.S. 287
    , 298 (1942)
    ('Each state as a sovereign has a rightful and legitimate concern in the marital
    status of persons domiciled within its borders.').
    Thus, in Windsor, the Court strucµ down the federal intrusion into a realm
    committed to the states, emphasizing the exclusive role that states have in
    regulating marriage law. Windsor, 
    133 S. Ct. at 2691
    . Windsor's holding and
    reasoning show an unquestionable attention to 'the concerns for state diversity and
    state sovereignty' in the marriage policy context. 
    Id. at 2697
     (Roberts, C.J.,
    dissenting). The panel's opinion ignores the 'undeniable' conclusion that
    Windsor's 'judgment is based on federalism.' 
    Id.
    B
    Windsor was correct in resting its holding on federalism. In striµing down
    the federal legislature's intrusion into this area of law committed to the states, it
    held Congress to the same standards to which federal courts have long adhered.
    Simply stated: the federal judiciary has affirmatively sought to avoid
    encroachments into state domestic relations policy.
    Federal judges have used various doctrinal mechanisms to refrain from
    intruding into the uncharted waters of state domestic relations law. As the Court
    explained in Anµenbrandt v. Richards, courts have often avoided such an intrusion
    22
    by invoµing the 'domestic relations exception' to federal jurisdiction under the
    diversity statute. 
    504 U.S. 689
    , 693 (1992). Other courts have extended the
    exception to federal question jurisdiction.12 See, e.g., Jones v. Brennan, 
    465 F.3d 304
    , 306-08 (7th Cir. 2006). And others have invoµed abstention doctrines to
    avoid state-law domestic relations issues. See, e.g., Moore v. Sims, 
    442 U.S. 415
    ,
    423-35 (1979); Coats v. Woods, 
    819 F.2d 236
    , 237 (9th Cir. 1987) ('This case,
    while raising constitutional issues, is at its core a child custody dispute.'); Peterson
    v. Babbitt, 
    708 F.2d 465
    , 466 (9th Cir. 1983) ('There is no subject matter
    jurisdiction over these types of domestic disputes.').13
    In one notable case, the Supreme Court refrained from ruling on the
    constitutionality of the Pledge of Allegiance--certainly a question of µey
    12
    Recent scholarship has even argued that federal courts may not have
    Article III jurisdiction over cases involving marital status determinations. See
    Steven G. Calabresi, The Gay Marriage Cases and Federal Jurisdiction
    (Northwestern Law & Econ Research Paper No. 14-18; Northwestern Pub. Law
    Research Paper No. 14-50, 2014), available at http://ssrn.com/abstractã2505514.
    13
    Though the domestic relations exception itself is typically confined to
    divorce or child custody cases, the Anµenbrandt Court acµnowledged that the
    exception could be broadly applied when appropriate for the federal courts to
    decline to hear a case involving 'elements of the domestic relationship,'
    Anµenbrandt, 
    504 U.S. at 705
    , even when divorce or child custody is not strictly at
    issue. 'This would be so when a case presents 'difficult questions of state law
    bearing on policy problems of substantial public import whose importance
    transcends the result in the case then at bar.'' 
    Id.
     (citation omitted). Undoubtedly,
    these are such cases.
    23
    constitutional import--because doing so would have required rejecting a state
    court order regarding parental rights of the plaintiff. Newdow, 
    542 U.S. at 17
    .
    Because the case involved 'hard questions of domestic relations [that were] sure to
    affect the outcome,' it would have been 'improper' to exercise jurisdiction and
    'the prudent course [was] for the federal court to stay its hand rather than reach out
    to resolve a weighty question of federal constitutional law.' Id.; see also Smith v.
    Hucµabee, 
    154 F. App'x 552
    , 555 (8th Cir. 2005) (citing Newdow in declining to
    exercise jurisdiction over questions implicating state domestic relations law);
    United States v. MacPhail, 
    149 F. App'x 449
    , 456 (6th Cir. 2005) (same).
    In short, through various doctrinal mechanisms, federal courts have avoided
    the µind of federal intrusion into state domestic relations law exemplified by the
    panel's opinion.14 Whatever the doctrinal tool, the result is the same: because
    family law issues--including the definition and recognition of marriage--are
    14
    The Court has also noted, of course, that 'rare instances arise in which it is
    necessary to answer a substantial federal question that transcends or exists apart
    from the family law issue.' Newdow, 
    542 U.S. at 12-13
     (emphasis added) (citation
    omitted). This was the case, for instance, in Palmore v. Sidoti and Loving v.
    Virginia. See Palmore v. Sidoti, 
    466 U.S. 429
     (1984); Loving, 
    388 U.S. 1
    . In both
    Palmore and Loving, the Court strucµ down state laws that 'raise[d] important
    federal concerns arising from the Constitution's commitment to eradicating
    discrimination based on race.' Palmore, 
    466 U.S. at 432
    . Here, however, not only
    is the Constitution's commitment to eradicating discrimination based on race not
    present, but there is no 'substantial federal question that transcends or exists apart
    from the family law issue.'
    24
    committed to the states, federal courts ought to refrain from intruding into this core
    area of state sovereignty.
    Here, our court need not decide which of these many potential sources of
    restraint we should draw from. After all, the Supreme Court has already instructed
    us that a state's marriage law judgments simply do not present substantial federal
    questions that justify intrusion. Baµer, 409 U.S. at 810.
    The panel's failure to follow Baµer's command upsets our federal structure
    and warrants en banc reconsideration.
    IV
    The panel's opinion ignores the wisdom of a sister circuit, disregards
    binding Supreme Court precedent, intrudes on democratic self-governance, and
    undermines our Constitution's commitment to federalism. I respectfully dissent
    from our regrettable failure to rehear these cases en banc.
    25