KRISTIN PERRY v. EDMUND G. BROWN, Jr. ( 2012 )


Menu:
  •                    FOR PUBLICATION
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT
    KRISTIN M. PERRY; SANDRA B.              
    STIER; PAUL T. KATAMI; JEFFREY J.
    ZARRILLO,
    Plaintiffs-Appellees,
    CITY AND COUNTY OF SAN
    FRANCISCO,
    Intervenor-Plaintiff-Appellee,
    v.
    EDMUND G. BROWN, JR., in his
    official capacity as Governor of
    California; KAMALA D. HARRIS, in
    her official capacity as Attorney
    General of California; MARK B.
    HORTON, in his official capacity as
    Director of the California               
    Department of Public Health &
    State Registrar of Vital Statistics;
    LINETTE SCOTT, in her official
    capacity as Deputy Director of
    Health Information & Strategic
    Planning for the California
    Department of Public Health;
    PATRICK O’CONNELL, in his official
    capacity as Clerk-Recorder for the
    County of Alameda; DEAN C.
    LOGAN, in his official capacity as
    Registrar-Recorder/County Clerk
    for the County of Los Angeles,
    Defendants,
    
    1569
    1570                    PERRY v. BROWN
    HAK-SHING WILLIAM TAM,                   
    Intervenor-Defendant,
    and
    DENNIS HOLLINGSWORTH; GAIL J.                 No. 10-16696
    KNIGHT; MARTIN F. GUTIERREZ;
    MARK A. JANSSON;                               D.C. No.
    3:09-cv-02292-
    PROTECTMARRIAGE.COM-YES ON 8,                     VRW
    A PROJECT OF CALIFORNIA
    RENEWAL, as official proponents of
    Proposition 8,
    Intervenor-Defendants-Appellants.
    
    KRISTIN M. PERRY; SANDRA B.              
    STIER; PAUL T. KATAMI; JEFFREY J.
    ZARRILLO,
    Plaintiffs-Appellees,
    CITY AND COUNTY OF SAN
    FRANCISCO,
    Intervenor-Plaintiff-Appellee,
    v.
    EDMUND G. BROWN, JR., in his             
    official capacity as Governor of
    California; KAMALA D. HARRIS, in
    her official capacity as Attorney
    General of California; MARK B.
    HORTON, in his official capacity as
    Director of the California
    Department of Public Health &
    State Registrar of Vital Statistics;
    
    PERRY v. BROWN                    1571
    LINETTE SCOTT, in her official        
    capacity as Deputy Director of
    Health Information & Strategic
    Planning for the California
    Department of Public Health;
    PATRICK O’CONNELL, in his official
    capacity as Clerk-Recorder for the
    County of Alameda; DEAN C.
    LOGAN, in his official capacity as
    Registrar-Recorder/County Clerk
    for the County of Los Angeles,              No. 11-16577
    HAK-SHING WILLIAM TAM,
    Defendants,
           D.C. No.
    3:09-cv-02292-JW
    Intervenor-Defendant,            OPINION
    and
    DENNIS HOLLINGSWORTH; GAIL J.
    KNIGHT; MARTIN F. GUTIERREZ;
    MARK A. JANSSON;
    PROTECTMARRIAGE.COM-YES ON 8,
    A PROJECT OF CALIFORNIA
    RENEWAL, as official proponents of
    Proposition 8,
    Intervenor-Defendants-Appellants.
    
    Appeal from the United States District Court
    for the Northern District of California
    Vaughn R. Walker, Chief District Judge, Presiding
    (No. 10-16696)
    James Ware, Chief District Judge, Presiding
    (No. 11-16577)
    1572                PERRY v. BROWN
    No. 10-16696:
    Argued and Submitted December 6, 2010
    San Francisco, California
    Submission Withdrawn January 4, 2011
    Resubmitted February 7, 2012
    No. 11-16577:
    Argued and Submitted December 8, 2011
    San Francisco, California
    Filed February 7, 2012
    Before: Stephen Reinhardt, Michael Daly Hawkins, and
    N. Randy Smith, Circuit Judges.
    Opinion by Judge Reinhardt;
    Partial Concurrence and Partial Dissent by
    Judge N.R. Smith
    1576                  PERRY v. BROWN
    COUNSEL
    No. 10-16696:
    Theodore J. Boutrous, Jr., Christopher D. Dusseault, Theane
    Evangelis Kapur, Sarah E. Piepmeier, Enrique A. Monagas,
    and Joshua S. Lipshutz, Gibson, Dunn & Crutcher LLP, Los
    Angeles, California; Theodore B. Olson (argued), Matthew D.
    McGill, and Amir C. Tayrani, Gibson, Dunn & Crutcher LLP,
    Washington, D.C.; David Boies (argued), Jeremy M. Gold-
    man, and Theodore H. Uno, Boies, Schiller & Flexner LLP,
    PERRY v. BROWN                     1577
    Armonk, New York; for plaintiffs-appellees Kristin M. Perry,
    Sandra B. Stier, Paul T. Katami, and Jeffrey J. Zarrillo.
    Dennis J. Herrera, City Attorney; Therese M. Stewart
    (argued), Chief Deputy City Attorney; Christine Van Aken
    and Mollie M. Lee, Deputy City Attorneys; San Francisco,
    California; for intervenor-plaintiff-appellee City and County
    of San Francisco.
    Andrew P. Pugno, Law Offices of Andrew P. Pugno, Folsom,
    California; Charles J. Cooper (argued), David H. Thompson,
    Howard C. Nielson, Jr., and Peter A. Patterson, Cooper and
    Kirk, PLLC, Washington, D.C.; Brian W. Raum and James A.
    Campbell, Alliance Defense Fund, Scottsdale, Arizona; for
    intervenor-defendants-appellants Dennis Hollingsworth, Gail
    J. Knight, Martin F. Gutierrez, Mark A. Jansson, and Protect-
    Marriage.com.
    James Joseph Lynch, Jr., Sacramento, California; for amicus
    curiae Margie Reilly.
    Paul Benjamin Linton, Thomas More Society, Northbrook,
    Illinois; Christopher M. Gacek, Family Research Council,
    Washington, D.C.; Thomas Brejcha, Thomas More Society,
    Chicago, Illinois; for amicus curiae The Family Research
    Council.
    Kelly J. Shackelford, Jeffrey C. Mateer, Hiriam S. Sasser, III,
    and Justin E. Butterfield, Liberty Institute, Plano, Texas; for
    amici curiae Liberty Institute, Association of Maryland Fami-
    lies, California Family Council, Center for Arizona Policy,
    Citizens for Community Values, Cornerstone Action, Corner-
    stone Family Council, Delaware Family Policy Council, Fam-
    ily Action Council of Tennessee, The Family Foundation, The
    Family Policy Council of West Virginia, Family Policy Insti-
    tute of Washington, Florida Family Policy Council, Georgia
    Family Council, Illinois Family Institute, Independence Law
    Center, Iowa Family Policy Center, Louisiana Family Forum
    1578                  PERRY v. BROWN
    Action, Massachusetts Family Institute, Michigan Family
    Forum, Minnesota Family Council, Missouri Family Policy
    Council, Montana Family Foundation, New Jersey Family
    First, New Jersey Family Policy Council, North Carolina
    Family Policy Council, Oklahoma Family Policy Council,
    Oregon Family Council, Palmetto Family Council, Pennsyl-
    vania Family Institute, Wisconsin Family Action, and
    Wywatch Family Action.
    Lynn D. Wardle, Marriage Law Project, J. Reuben Clark Law
    School, Provo, Utah; Stephen Kent Ehat, Lindon, Utah; Lin-
    coln C. Oliphant, Columbus School of Law, The Catholic
    University of America, Washington, D.C.; for amici curiae
    High Impact Leadership Coalition, The Center for Urban
    Renewal and Education, and The Frederick Douglass Founda-
    tion, Inc.
    Dean R. Broyles and James M. Griffiths, The Western Center
    for Law & Policy, Escondido, California; for amici curiae
    Parents and Friends of Ex-Gays and Desert Stream Ministries.
    M. Edward Whelan III, Ethics and Public Policy Center,
    Washington, D.C.; for amicus curiae The Ethics and Public
    Policy Center.
    Mary E. McAlister, Stephen M. Crampton, and Rena M.
    Lindevaldsen, Liberty Counsel, Lynchburg, Virginia; Mat-
    thew D. Staver and Anita L. Staver, Liberty Counsel,
    Orlando, Florida; for amici curiae Liberty Counsel, Campaign
    for Children and Families, and JONAH Inc.
    Jay Alan Sekulow, Stuart J. Roth, and Walter M. Weber,
    American Center for Law & Justice, Washington, D.C.; for
    amicus curiae The American Center for Law and Justice.
    Donald W. MacPherson, The MacPherson Group, Phoenix,
    Arizona; for amicus curiae The Hausvater Project.
    PERRY v. BROWN                    1579
    Matthew B. McReynolds and Kevin T. Snider, Pacific Justice
    Institute, Sacramento, California; for amicus curiae Pacific
    Justice Institute.
    Von G. Keetch, Alexander Dushku, and R. Shawn Gunnar-
    son, Kirton & McConkie, Salt Lake City, Utah; Anthony R.
    Picarello, Jr., Jeffrey Hunter Moon, and Michael F. Moses,
    U.S. Conference of Catholic Bishops, Washington, D.C.; Carl
    H. Esbeck, National Association of Evangelicals, Washing-
    ton, D.C.; James F. Sweeney, Sweeney & Greene LLP, Elk
    Grove, California; for amici curiae United States Conference
    of Catholic Bishops, California Catholic Conference, National
    Association of Evangelicals, The Church of Jesus Christ of
    Latter-day Saints, The Ethics & Religious Liberty Commis-
    sion, Lutheran Church–Missouri Synod, Calvary Chapel Fel-
    lowship of Ministries of California, The Christian and
    Missionary Alliance, Coral Ridge Ministries, The Council of
    Korean Churches in Southern California, Southern California
    Korean Ministers Association, and Holy Movement for Amer-
    ica.
    Kristen K. Waggoner and Steven T. O’Ban, Ellis, Li & McK-
    instry PLLC, Seattle, Washington; for amici curiae Robert P.
    George, Sherif Girgis, and Ryan T. Anderson.
    Gary G. Kreep, United States Justice Foundation, Ramona,
    California; for amicus curiae National Association for
    Research & Therapy of Homosexuality (NARTH).
    Abram J. Pafford, Pafford, Lawrence & Ross, PLLC, Wash-
    ington, D.C.; for amicus curiae American College of Pediatri-
    cians.
    John C. Eastman, Anthony T. Caso, and Karen J. Lugo, Cen-
    ter for Constitutional Jurisprudence, Orange, California; for
    amicus curiae Center for Constitutional Jurisprudence.
    1580                   PERRY v. BROWN
    Kevin J. Hasson and Lori H. Windham, The Becket Fund for
    Religious Liberty, Washington, D.C.; for amicus curiae The
    Becket Fund for Religious Liberty.
    Steven W. Fitschen, The National Legal Foundation, Virginia
    Beach, Virginia; for amicus curiae National Legal Founda-
    tion.
    Lawrence J. Joseph, Washington, D.C.; for amicus curiae
    Eagle Forum Education & Legal Defense Fund.
    Holly L. Carmichael, Los Gatos, California; for amicus curiae
    Concerned Women of America.
    William C. Duncan, Marriage Law Foundation, Lehi, Utah;
    Joshua K. Baker, National Organization for Marriage, Wash-
    ington, D.C.; for amici curiae National Organization for Mar-
    riage, National Organization for Marriage Rhode Island, and
    Family Leader.
    Herbert G. Grey, Beaverton, Oregon; for amicus curiae Paul
    McHugh.
    Eugene Dong, Palo Alto, California; for amicus curiae
    Eugene Dong.
    Gregory F. Zoeller, Attorney General; Thomas M. Fischer,
    Solicitor General; and Ellen H. Meilaender, Deputy Attorney
    General, State of Indiana; Kenneth T. Cuccinelli, II, Attorney
    General; E. Duncan Getchell, Solicitor General; and Stephen
    McCullough, Deputy Solicitor General, State of Virginia;
    Michael A. Cox, Attorney General and Eric Restuccia, Solici-
    tor General, State of Michigan; James D. Caldwell, Attorney
    General and Kyle Duncan, Appellate Chief, State of Louisi-
    ana; Troy King, Attorney General, State of Alabama; Daniel
    S. Sullivan, Attorney General, State of Alaska; Bill McCol-
    lum, Attorney General, State of Florida; Lawrence G. Was-
    den, Attorney General, State of Idaho; Jon Bruning, Attorney
    PERRY v. BROWN                    1581
    General, State of Nebraska; Thomas W. Corbett, Jr., Attorney
    General, Commonwealth of Pennsylvania; Henry McMaster,
    Attorney General, State of South Carolina; Mark L. Shurtleff,
    Attorney General, State of Utah; Bruce A. Salzburg, Attorney
    General, State of Wyoming; for amici curiae States of Indi-
    ana, Virginia, Louisiana, Michigan, Alabama, Alaska, Flor-
    ida, Idaho, Nebraska, Pennsylvania, South Carolina, Utah,
    and Wyoming.
    Kenneth A. Klukowski, American Civil Rights Union, Alex-
    andria, Virginia; for amicus curiae American Civil Rights
    Union.
    Richard G. Katerndahl, San Rafael, California; for amicus
    curiae Catholics for the Common Good.
    Jerome C. Roth, Michelle Friedland, Mark R. Conrad, and
    Miriam L. Seifter, Munger, Tolles & Olson LLP, San Fran-
    cisco, California; for amici curiae Bay Area Lawyers for Indi-
    vidual Freedom, Alameda County Bar Association, Bar
    Association of San Francisco, Los Angeles County Bar Asso-
    ciation, Marin County Bar Association, Santa Clara County
    Bar Association, AIDS Legal Referral Panel, API Equality–
    LA, Asian American Bar Association of the Greater Bay
    Area, Asian Pacific American Bar Association of Los Ange-
    les County, Asian Pacific Bar Association of Silicon Valley,
    Asian Pacific Islander Legal Outreach, Bay Area Association
    of Muslim Lawyers, California Employment Lawyers Associ-
    ation, California Women’s Law Center, East Bay La Raza
    Lawyers Association, Equal Justice Society, Family Equality
    Council, Filipino Bar Association of Northern California,
    Freedom to Marry, Impact Fund, Japanese American Bar
    Association of Greater Los Angeles, Korean American Bar
    Association of Northern California, Latina and Latino Critical
    Legal Theory, Inc., Law Foundation of Silicon Valley, Law-
    yers’ Committee for Civil Rights of the San Francisco Bay
    Area, Legal Aid Society-Employment Law Center, Lesbian
    and Gay Lawyers Association of Los Angeles, Marriage
    1582                  PERRY v. BROWN
    Equality USA, Mexican American Bar Association, National
    Asian Pacific American Bar Association, National Lawyers
    Guild San Francisco Bay Area Chapter, People for the Ameri-
    can Way Foundation, Queen’s Bench Bar Association, San
    Francisco Chamber of Commerce, San Francisco La Raza
    Lawyers Association, San Francisco Trial Lawyers Associa-
    tion, Santa Clara County Black Lawyers Association, Society
    of American Law Teachers, South Asian Bar Association of
    Northern California, Transgender Law Center, and Women
    Lawyers of Alameda County.
    Elizabeth B. Wydra, David H. Gans, Douglas T. Kendall, and
    Judith E. Schaeffer, Constitutional Accountability Center,
    Washington, D.C.; for amicus curiae Constitutional Account-
    ability Center.
    Daniel H. Squire, Wilmer Cutler Pickering Hale and Dorr
    LLP, Washington, D.C.; Alan E. Schoenfeld, David Sapir
    Lesser, and Erin G.H. Sloane, Wilmer Cutler Pickering Hale
    and Dorr LLP, New York, New York; for amici curiae Legis-
    lators from United States Jurisdictions That Have Legalized
    Same-Sex Marriage.
    Nathalie F.P. Gilfoyle, American Psychological Association,
    Washington, D.C.; Paul M. Smith, William M. Hohengarten,
    and Julia K. Martinez, Jenner & Block LLP, Washington,
    D.C.; for amici curiae American Psychological Association,
    The California Psychological Association, The American Psy-
    chiatric Association, and The American Association for Mar-
    riage and Family Therapy.
    Laura W. Brill, Nicholas F. Daum, and Richard M. Simon,
    Kendall Brill & Klieger LLP, Los Angeles, California; for
    amicus curiae Jon B. Eisenberg.
    Herma Hill Kay, University of California—Berkeley School
    of Law, Berkeley, California; Michael S. Wald, Stanford Law
    PERRY v. BROWN                    1583
    School, Stanford, California; for amici curiae California Pro-
    fessors of Family Law.
    Aderson François, Howard University School of Law Civil
    Rights Clinic, Washington, D.C.; Ayesha N. Khan, Ameri-
    cans United for Separation of Church and State, Washington
    D.C.; Brad W. Seiling, Kathryn A.B. Bartow, and Benjamin
    G. Shatz, Manatt, Phelps & Phillips, LLP, Los Angeles, Cali-
    fornia; Jon B. Streeter, Susan J. Harriman, and Jo W. Golub,
    Keker & Van Nest, LLP, San Francisco, California; for amici
    curiae Howard University School of Law Civil Rights Clinic
    and Americans United for Separation of Church and State.
    Justin Ford, O’Melveny & Myers LLP, Los Angeles, Califor-
    nia; Walter Dellinger, Jonathan D. Hacker, Sarah Goldfrank,
    and Anton Metlitsky, O’Melveny & Myers LLP, Washington,
    D.C.; for amicus curiae National LGBT Bar Association.
    Martha Coakley, Attorney General; Maura T. Healey, Jona-
    than B. Miller, and Christopher K. Barry-Smith, Assistant
    Attorneys General, Boston, Massachusetts; for amicus curiae
    The Commonwealth of Massachusetts.
    Christopher L. Lebsock and Arthur N. Bailey, Jr., Hausfeld
    LLP, San Francisco, California; for amicus curiae The Cali-
    fornia Teachers Association.
    Steven M. Freeman, Steven C. Sheinberg, Deborah Besinger,
    and Michelle Deutchman, Anti-Defamation League, New
    York, New York; Victoria F. Maroulis, Anna T. Neill, and
    Brett J. Arnold, Quinn Emanuel Urquhart & Sullivan, LLP,
    Redwood Shores, California; for amicus curiae Anti-
    Defamation League.
    John Payton, Debo P. Adegbile, and Dale E. Ho, NAACP
    Legal Defense & Educational Fund, Inc., New York, New
    York; for amicus curiae NAACP Legal Defense & Educa-
    tional Fund, Inc.
    1584                   PERRY v. BROWN
    Kathleen M. O’Sullivan and Abha Khanna, Perkins Coie
    LLP, Seattle, Washington; for amici curiae Professors Wil-
    liam N. Eskridge, Jr., Bruce A. Ackerman, Rebecca L.
    Brown, Daniel A. Farber, Kenneth L. Karst, and Andrew
    Koppelman.
    Sonya D. Winner, Bruce R. Deming, David M. Jolley, and
    John D. Freed, Covington & Burling LLP, San Francisco,
    California; for amici curiae American Anthropological Asso-
    ciation, American Psychoanalytic Association, National Asso-
    ciation of Social Workers, National Association of Social
    Workers, California Chapter, American Sociological Associa-
    tion, and American Academy of Pediatrics, California.
    Jon W. Davidson, Jennifer C. Pizer, and Tara L. Borelli,
    Lambda Legal Defense and Education Fund, Inc., Los Ange-
    les, California; Alan L. Schlosser and Elizabeth O. Gill,
    ACLU Foundation of Northern California, San Francisco,
    California; Shannon P. Minter, Christopher F. Stoll, and Ilona
    M. Turner, National Center for Lesbian Rights, San Fran-
    cisco, California; for amici curiae ACLU Foundation of
    Northern California, Gay and Lesbian Advocates and Defend-
    ers, Lambda Legal Defense and Education Fund, Inc., and
    National Center for Lesbian Rights.
    Eric Alan Isaacson, San Diego, California; Stacey M. Kaplan,
    San Francisco, California; for amici curiae California Faith
    for Equality, California Council of Churches, General Synod
    of the United Church of Christ, Universal Fellowship of Met-
    ropolitan Community Churches, The Episcopal Bishops of
    California and Los Angeles, Progressive Jewish Alliance,
    Pacific Association of Reform Rabbis, Unitarian Universalist
    Association, and Unitarian Universalist Legislative Ministry
    California.
    David C. Codell, Linda M. Burrow, Albert Giang, and Benja-
    min A. Au, Caldwell Leslie & Proctor, PC, Los Angeles, Cal-
    ifornia; for amicus curiae Equality California.
    PERRY v. BROWN                    1585
    Diana E. Richmond and Louis P. Feuchtbaum, Sideman &
    Bancroft LLP, San Francisco, California; Richard B. Rosen-
    thal, The Law Offices of Richard B. Rosenthal, P.A., San
    Rafael, California; for amici curiae Donald B. King, Justice
    (Ret.) and The American Academy of Matrimonial Lawyers
    (Northern California Chapter).
    Elizabeth J. Cabraser, Kelly M. Dermody, Brendan P.
    Glackin, Anne Shaver, and Alison Stocking, Lieff, Cabraser,
    Heimann & Bernstein, LLP, San Francisco, California;
    Rachel Geman, Lieff, Cabraser, Heimann & Bernstein, LLP,
    New York, New York; for amici curiae Professors Bryan
    Adamson, Janet Cooper Alexander, Barbara A. Atwood, Bar-
    bara Babcock, Erwin Chemerinsky, Joshua P. Davis, David L.
    Faigman, Pamela S. Karlan, Toni M. Massaro, Arthur Miller,
    David Oppenheimer, Judith Resnik, Fred Smith, and Larry
    Yackle.
    Scott Wm. Davenport, Jason J. Molnar, Darin L. Wessel, and
    Peter C. Catalanotti, Manning & Marder, Kass, Ellrod,
    Ramirez LLP, Irvine, California; for amicus curiae The
    Southern Poverty Law Center.
    Peter Obstler, Jee Young You, Suneeta D. Fernandes, and
    Doug Karpa, Bingham McCutchen LLP, San Francisco, Cali-
    fornia; for amici curiae Asian American Justice Center, Asian
    Law Caucus, Asian American Institute, Asian Pacific Ameri-
    can Legal Center, Asian Pacific American Women Lawyers
    Alliance, Asian Pacific Islander Legal Outreach, API Equal-
    ity, California Conference of the NAACP, Chinese for Affir-
    mative Action, Coalition for Humane Immigrant Rights of
    Los Angeles, Korematsu Center at Seattle University, Mexi-
    can American Legal Defense and Education Fund, and Zuna
    Institute.
    Susan M. Popik and Merri A. Baldwin, Chapman, Popik &
    White LLP, San Francisco, California; Suzanne B. Goldberg,
    Clinical Professor of Law and Director, Sexuality & Gender
    1586                    PERRY v. BROWN
    Law Clinic, Columbia Law School, New York, New York;
    for amici curiae National Gay and Lesbian Task Force Foun-
    dation, Human Rights Campaign, American Humanist Asso-
    ciation, and Courage Campaign Institute.
    No. 11-16577:
    David Boies (argued), Jeremy M. Goldman, and Theodore H.
    Uno, Boies, Schiller & Flexner LLP, Armonk, New York;
    Theodore B. Olson, Matthew D. McGill, and Amir C. Tay-
    rani, Gibson, Dunn & Crutcher LLP, Washington, D.C.; The-
    odore J. Boutrous, Jr., Christopher D. Dusseault, Theane
    Evangelis Kapur, Enrique A. Monagas, and Joshua S. Lip-
    shutz, Gibson, Dunn & Crutcher LLP, Los Angeles, Califor-
    nia; for plaintiffs-appellees Kristin M. Perry, Sandra B. Stier,
    Paul T. Katami, and Jeffrey J. Zarrillo.
    Dennis J. Herrera, Therese M. Stewart (argued), and Christine
    Van Aken, City and County of San Francisco, San Francisco,
    California; for intervenor-plaintiff-appellee City and County
    of San Francisco.
    Andrew P. Pugno, Law Offices of Andrew P. Pugno, Folsom,
    California; Charles J. Cooper (argued), David H. Thompson,
    Howard C. Nielson, Jr., and Peter A. Patterson, Cooper and
    Kirk, PLLC, Washington, D.C.; Brian W. Raum and James A.
    Campbell, Alliance Defense Fund, Scottsdale, Arizona; for
    intervenor-defendants-appellants Dennis Hollingsworth, Gail
    J. Knight, Martin F. Gutierrez, Mark A. Jansson, and Protect-
    Marriage.com.
    Jon W. Davidson, Tara L. Borelli, and Peter C. Renn, Lambda
    Legal Defense and Education Fund, Los Angeles, California;
    Shannon P. Minter, Christopher F. Stoll, and Ilona M. Turner,
    National Center for Lesbian Rights, San Francisco, Califor-
    nia; Alan L. Schlosser and Elizabeth O. Gill, ACLU Founda-
    tion of Northern California, San Francisco, California; for
    amici curiae Lambda Legal Defense and Education Fund,
    PERRY v. BROWN                      1587
    National Center for Lesbian Rights, ACLU Foundation of
    Northern California, and Equality California.
    David M. Balabanian, Frank Busch, Elizabeth Benson, and
    Kathryn Conrad, Bingham McCutchen LLP, San Francisco,
    California; for amicus curiae The Bar Association of San
    Francisco.
    OPINION
    REINHARDT, Circuit Judge:
    Prior to November 4, 2008, the California Constitution
    guaranteed the right to marry to opposite-sex couples and
    same-sex couples alike. On that day, the People of California
    adopted Proposition 8, which amended the state constitution
    to eliminate the right of same-sex couples to marry. We con-
    sider whether that amendment violates the Fourteenth
    Amendment to the United States Constitution. We conclude
    that it does.
    Although the Constitution permits communities to enact
    most laws they believe to be desirable, it requires that there
    be at least a legitimate reason for the passage of a law that
    treats different classes of people differently. There was no
    such reason that Proposition 8 could have been enacted.
    Because under California statutory law, same-sex couples had
    all the rights of opposite-sex couples, regardless of their mari-
    tal status, all parties agree that Proposition 8 had one effect
    only. It stripped same-sex couples of the ability they previ-
    ously possessed to obtain from the State, or any other autho-
    rized party, an important right—the right to obtain and use the
    designation of ‘marriage’ to describe their relationships.
    Nothing more, nothing less. Proposition 8 therefore could not
    have been enacted to advance California’s interests in child-
    rearing or responsible procreation, for it had no effect on the
    1588                    PERRY v. BROWN
    rights of same-sex couples to raise children or on the procre-
    ative practices of other couples. Nor did Proposition 8 have
    any effect on religious freedom or on parents’ rights to control
    their children’s education; it could not have been enacted to
    safeguard these liberties.
    All that Proposition 8 accomplished was to take away from
    same-sex couples the right to be granted marriage licenses
    and thus legally to use the designation of ‘marriage,’ which
    symbolizes state legitimization and societal recognition of
    their committed relationships. Proposition 8 serves no pur-
    pose, and has no effect, other than to lessen the status and
    human dignity of gays and lesbians in California, and to offi-
    cially reclassify their relationships and families as inferior to
    those of opposite-sex couples. The Constitution simply does
    not allow for “laws of this sort.” Romer v. Evans, 
    517 U.S. 620
    , 633 (1996).
    “Broader issues have been urged for our consideration, but
    we adhere to the principle of deciding constitutional questions
    only in the context of the particular case before the Court.”
    Sweatt v. Painter, 
    339 U.S. 629
    , 631 (1950). Whether under
    the Constitution same-sex couples may ever be denied the
    right to marry, a right that has long been enjoyed by opposite-
    sex couples, is an important and highly controversial question.
    It is currently a matter of great debate in our nation, and an
    issue over which people of good will may disagree, some-
    times strongly. Of course, when questions of constitutional
    law are necessary to the resolution of a case, courts may not
    and should not abstain from deciding them simply because
    they are controversial. We need not and do not answer the
    broader question in this case, however, because California had
    already extended to committed same-sex couples both the
    incidents of marriage and the official designation of ‘mar-
    riage,’ and Proposition 8’s only effect was to take away that
    important and legally significant designation, while leaving in
    place all of its incidents. This unique and strictly limited
    PERRY v. BROWN                       1589
    effect of Proposition 8 allows us to address the amendment’s
    constitutionality on narrow grounds.
    Thus, as a result of our “traditional reluctance to extend
    constitutional interpretations to situations or facts which are
    not before the Court, much of the excellent research and
    detailed argument presented in th[is] case[ ] is unnecessary to
    [its] disposition.” 
    Id.
     Were we unable, however, to resolve the
    matter on the basis we do, we would not hesitate to proceed
    to the broader question—the constitutionality of denying
    same-sex couples the right to marry.
    Before considering the constitutional question of the valid-
    ity of Proposition 8’s elimination of the rights of same-sex
    couples to marry, we first decide that the official sponsors of
    Proposition 8 are entitled to appeal the decision below, which
    declared the measure unconstitutional and enjoined its
    enforcement. The California Constitution and Elections Code
    endow the official sponsors of an initiative measure with the
    authority to represent the State’s interest in establishing the
    validity of a measure enacted by the voters, when the State’s
    elected leaders refuse to do so. See Perry v. Brown, 
    134 Cal. Rptr. 3d 499
     (2011). It is for the State of California to decide
    who may assert its interests in litigation, and we respect its
    decision by holding that Proposition 8’s proponents have
    standing to bring this appeal on behalf of the State. We there-
    fore conclude that, through the proponents of ballot measures,
    the People of California must be allowed to defend in federal
    courts, including on appeal, the validity of their use of the ini-
    tiative power. Here, however, their defense fails on the merits.
    The People may not employ the initiative power to single out
    a disfavored group for unequal treatment and strip them, with-
    out a legitimate justification, of a right as important as the
    right to marry. Accordingly, we affirm the judgment of the
    district court.
    We also affirm—for substantially the reasons set forth in
    the district court’s opinion—the denial of the motion by the
    1590                    PERRY v. BROWN
    official sponsors of Proposition 8 to vacate the judgment
    entered by former Chief Judge Walker, on the basis of his
    purported interest in being allowed to marry his same-sex
    partner.
    I
    A
    Upon its founding, the State of California recognized the
    legal institution of civil marriage for its residents. See, e.g.,
    Cal. Const. of 1849, art. XI, §§ 12, 14 (discussing marriage
    contracts and marital property); Cal. Stats. 1850, ch. 140 (“An
    Act regulating Marriages”). Marriage in California was under-
    stood, at the time and well into the twentieth century, to be
    limited to relationships between a man and a woman. See In
    re Marriage Cases, 
    183 P.3d 384
    , 407-09 (Cal. 2008). In
    1977, that much was made explicit by the California Legisla-
    ture, which amended the marriage statute to read, “Marriage
    is a personal relation arising out of a civil contract between
    a man and a woman, to which the consent of the parties capa-
    ble of making that contract is necessary.” Cal. Stats. 1977, ch.
    339, § 1. The 1977 provision remains codified in California
    statute. See 
    Cal. Fam. Code § 300
    (a).
    Following the enactment of the Defense of Marriage Act of
    1996, Pub. L. 104-199, 
    110 Stat. 2419
     (codified in relevant
    part at 
    1 U.S.C. § 7
    ), which expressly limited the federal defi-
    nition of marriage to relationships between one man and one
    woman, dozens of states enacted similar provisions into state
    law. See Andrew Koppelman, The Difference the Mini-
    DOMAs Make, 
    38 Loy. U. Chi. L.J. 265
    , 265-66 (2007). Cali-
    fornia did so in 2000 by adopting Proposition 22, an initiative
    statute, which provided, “Only marriage between a man and
    a woman is valid or recognized in California.” 
    Cal. Fam. Code § 308.5
    . The proposition ensured that same-sex mar-
    riages performed in any state that might permit such mar-
    riages in the future would not be recognized in California, and
    PERRY v. BROWN                        1591
    it guaranteed that any legislative repeal of the 1977 statute
    would not allow same-sex couples to marry within the State,
    because the Legislature may not amend or repeal an initiative
    statute enacted by the People. See Marriage Cases, 183 P.3d
    at 409-10.
    Meanwhile, however, California had created the designa-
    tion “domestic partnership” for “two adults who have chosen
    to share one another’s lives in an intimate and committed rela-
    tionship of mutual caring.” Cal. Stats. 1999, ch. 588, § 2 (cod-
    ified at 
    Cal. Fam. Code § 297
    (a)). At first, California gave
    registered domestic partners only limited rights, such as hos-
    pital visitation privileges, 
    id.
     § 4, and health benefits for the
    domestic partners of certain state employees, id. § 3. Over the
    next several years, however, the State substantially expanded
    the rights of domestic partners. By 2008, “California statutory
    provisions generally afford[ed] same-sex couples the opportu-
    nity to . . . obtain virtually all of the benefits and responsibili-
    ties afforded by California law to married opposite-sex
    couples.” Marriage Cases, 183 P.3d at 417-18. The 2003
    Domestic Partner Act provided broadly: “Registered domestic
    partners shall have the same rights, protections, and benefits,
    and shall be subject to the same responsibilities, obligations,
    and duties under law, whether they derive from statutes,
    administrative regulations, court rules, government policies,
    common law, or any other provisions or sources of law, as are
    granted to and imposed upon spouses.” Cal. Stats. 2003, ch.
    421, § 4 (codified at 
    Cal. Fam. Code § 297.5
    (a)). It withheld
    only the official designation of marriage and thus the offi-
    cially conferred and societally recognized status that accom-
    panies that designation.
    B
    In 2004, same-sex couples and the City and County of San
    Francisco filed actions in California state courts alleging that
    the State’s marriage statutes violated the California Constitu-
    tion. Proposition 22 was among the statutes challenged,
    1592                         PERRY v. BROWN
    because as an initiative statutory enactment, it was equal in
    dignity to an enactment by the Legislature and thus subject to
    the restrictions of the state constitution.1 The consolidated
    cases were eventually decided by the California Supreme
    Court, which held the statutes to be unconstitutional, for two
    independent reasons.
    First, the court held that the fundamental right to marry
    provided by the California Constitution could not be denied
    to same-sex couples, who are guaranteed “the same substan-
    tive constitutional rights as opposite-sex couples to choose
    one’s life partner and enter with that person into a committed,
    officially recognized, and protected family relationship that
    enjoys all of the constitutionally based incidents of marriage.”
    Marriage Cases, 183 P.3d at 433-34. The court began by reaf-
    firming that “the right to marry is an integral component of
    an individual’s interest in personal autonomy protected by the
    privacy provision of article I, section 1 [of the California Con-
    stitution], and of the liberty interest protected by the due pro-
    cess clause of article I, section 7.” Id. at 426 (emphasis
    omitted). It then held “that an individual’s homosexual orien-
    tation is not a constitutionally legitimate basis for withholding
    or restricting the individual’s legal rights.” Id. at 429. The
    court acknowledged that although such an inclusive under-
    standing of the right to marry was one that had developed
    only “in recent decades,” as the State extended greater recog-
    nition to same-sex couples and households, it was “apparent
    that history alone does not provide a justification for interpret-
    1
    The California Constitution differentiates between initiative statutes,
    which require petitions signed by five percent of electors, and initiative
    constitutional amendments, which require petitions signed by eight per-
    cent of electors. Cal. Const. art. 2, § 8(b). An initiative statutory enactment
    has somewhat greater status than a statute adopted by the Legislature, in
    that the Legislature may not amend or repeal the initiative statute without
    submitting the change to approval by the electors (unless the initiative
    statute provides otherwise). Id. § 10(c). Yet, like a statutory enactment by
    the Legislature, and unlike an initiative constitutional amendment, it is
    subject to the terms of the state constitution.
    PERRY v. BROWN                       1593
    ing the constitutional right to marry as protecting only one’s
    ability to enter into an officially recognized family relation-
    ship with a person of the opposite sex,” because
    “ ‘[f]undamental rights, once recognized, cannot be denied to
    particular groups on the ground that these groups have histori-
    cally been denied those rights.’ ” Id. at 428-30 (quoting Her-
    nandez v. Robles, 
    7 N.Y.3d 338
    , 381 (2006) (Kaye, C.J.,
    dissenting)).
    The court concluded its due process analysis by rejecting
    the argument that the availability of domestic partnerships sat-
    isfied “all of the personal and dignity interests that have tradi-
    tionally informed the right to marry,” because “[t]he current
    statutes—by drawing a distinction between the name assigned
    to the family relationship available to opposite-sex couples
    and the name assigned to the family relationship available to
    same-sex couples, and by reserving the historic and highly
    respected designation of ‘marriage’ exclusively to opposite-
    sex couples while offering same-sex couples only the new and
    unfamiliar designation of domestic partnership—pose a seri-
    ous risk of denying the official family relationship of same-
    sex couples the equal dignity and respect that is a core ele-
    ment of the constitutional right to marry.” 
    Id. at 434-35
    .
    Second, the court held that “[t]he current statutory assign-
    ment of different names for the official family relationships of
    opposite-sex couples on the one hand, and of same-sex cou-
    ples on the other” violated the equal protection clause in arti-
    cle I, section 7 of the California Constitution. 
    Id. at 435
    , 452-
    53. The court determined that the State had no interest in
    reserving the name ‘marriage’ for opposite-sex couples; “the
    historic and well-established nature of this limitation” could
    not itself justify the differential treatment, and the court found
    no reason that restricting the designation of ‘marriage’ to
    opposite-sex couples was necessary to preserve the benefits of
    marriage enjoyed by opposite-sex couples or their children.
    
    Id. at 450-52
    . The court noted specifically that “the distinction
    in nomenclature between marriage and domestic partnership
    1594                    PERRY v. BROWN
    cannot be defended on the basis of an asserted difference in
    the effect on children of being raised by an opposite-sex cou-
    ple instead of by a same-sex couple,” because “the governing
    California statutes permit same-sex couples to adopt and raise
    children and additionally draw no distinction between married
    couples and domestic partners with regard to the legal rights
    and responsibilities relating to children raised within each of
    these family relationships.” 
    Id.
     at 452 n.72. Restricting access
    to the designation of ‘marriage’ did, however, “work[ ] a real
    and appreciable harm upon same-sex couples and their chil-
    dren,” because “providing only a novel, alternative institution
    for same-sex couples” constituted “an official statement that
    the family relationship of same-sex couples is not of compara-
    ble stature or equal dignity to the family relationship of
    opposite-sex couples.” 
    Id. at 452
    . Consequently, the court
    determined that withholding only the name ‘marriage’ from
    same-sex couples violated the California Constitution’s guar-
    antee of equal protection.
    The court remedied these constitutional violations by strik-
    ing the language from the marriage statutes “limiting the des-
    ignation of marriage to a union ‘between a man and a
    woman,’ ” invalidating Proposition 22, and ordering that the
    designation of ‘marriage’ be made available to both opposite-
    sex and same-sex couples. 
    Id. at 453
    . Following the court’s
    decision, California counties issued more than 18,000 mar-
    riage licenses to same-sex couples.
    C
    Five      California      residents—defendants-intervenors-
    appellants Dennis Hollingsworth, Gail J. Knight, Martin F.
    Gutierrez, Hak-Shing William Tam, and Mark A. Jansson
    (collectively, “Proponents”)—collected voter signatures and
    filed petitions with the state government to place an initiative
    on the November 4, 2008, ballot. Unlike Proposition 22, this
    was an initiative constitutional amendment, which would be
    equal in effect to any other provision of the California Consti-
    PERRY v. BROWN                      1595
    tution, rather than subordinate to it. The Proponents’ measure,
    designated Proposition 8, proposed to add a new provision to
    the California Constitution’s Declaration of Rights, immedi-
    ately following the Constitution’s due process and equal pro-
    tection clauses. The provision states, “Only marriage between
    a man and a woman is valid or recognized in California.”
    According to the official voter information guide, Proposition
    8 “[c]hanges the California Constitution to eliminate the right
    of same-sex couples to marry in California.” Official Voter
    Information Guide, California General Election (Nov. 4,
    2008), at 54. Following a contentious campaign, a slim major-
    ity of California voters (52.3 percent) approved Proposition 8.
    Pursuant to the state constitution, Proposition 8 took effect the
    next day, as article I, section 7.5 of the California Constitu-
    tion.
    Opponents of Proposition 8 then brought an original action
    for a writ of mandate in the California Supreme Court. They
    contended that Proposition 8 exceeded the scope of the Peo-
    ple’s initiative power because it revised, rather than amended,
    the California Constitution. The opponents did not raise any
    federal constitutional challenge to Proposition 8 in the state
    court. The state officials named as respondents refused to
    defend the measure’s validity, but Proponents were permitted
    to intervene and do so. Following argument, the court upheld
    Proposition 8 as a valid initiative but construed the measure
    as not nullifying the 18,000-plus marriages of same-sex cou-
    ples that had already been performed in the State. Strauss v.
    Horton, 
    207 P.3d 48
    , 98-110, 119-22 (Cal. 2009).
    The court also explained Proposition 8’s precise effect on
    California law: “[T]he measure carves out a narrow and lim-
    ited exception to the[ ] state constitutional rights [articulated
    in the Marriage Cases], reserving the official designation of
    the term ‘marriage’ for the union of opposite-sex couples as
    a matter of state constitutional law, but leaving undisturbed all
    of the other extremely significant substantive aspects of a
    same-sex couple’s state constitutional right to establish an
    1596                       PERRY v. BROWN
    officially recognized and protected family relationship and the
    guarantee of equal protection of the laws.” Id. at 61; see also
    id. at 75. In other words, after Proposition 8, “[s]ame-sex cou-
    ples retain all of the fundamental substantive components
    encompassed within the constitutional rights of privacy and
    due process, with the sole (albeit significant) exception of the
    right to equal access to the designation ‘marriage.’ ” Id. at
    116. Proposition 8 accomplished this result not by “declar-
    [ing] the state of the law as it existed when the Marriage
    Cases decision was rendered, but instead [by] establish[ing]
    a new substantive state constitutional rule that became effec-
    tive once Proposition 8 was approved by the voters.” Id. at
    115; see also id. at 63.
    II
    A
    Two same-sex couples—plaintiffs Kristin Perry and Sandra
    Stier, and Paul Katami and Jeffrey Zarrillo—filed this action
    under 
    42 U.S.C. § 1983
     in May 2009, after being denied mar-
    riage licenses by the County Clerks of Alameda County and
    Los Angeles County, respectively. Alleging that Proposition
    8 violates the Fourteenth Amendment to the United States
    Constitution, they sought a declaration of its unconstitutional-
    ity and an injunction barring its enforcement. The City and
    County of San Francisco (“San Francisco”) was later permit-
    ted to intervene as a plaintiff to present evidence of the
    amendment’s effects on its governmental interests. The
    defendants—the two county clerks and four state officers,
    including the Governor and Attorney General—filed answers
    to the complaint but once again refused to argue in favor of
    Proposition 8’s constitutionality. As a result, the district court
    granted Proponents’ motion to intervene as of right under
    Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 24(a) to defend the validity
    of the proposition they had sponsored.2
    2
    The district court subsequently denied the motion to intervene brought
    by the Campaign for California Families, a public interest organization
    PERRY v. BROWN                             1597
    The district court held a twelve-day bench trial, during
    which it heard testimony from nineteen witnesses and, after
    giving the parties a full and fair opportunity to present evi-
    dence and argument, built an extensive evidentiary record.3 In
    a thorough opinion in August 2010, the court made eighty
    findings of fact and adopted the relevant conclusions of law.
    Perry v. Schwarzenegger (Perry IV), 
    704 F. Supp. 2d 921
    (N.D. Cal. 2010).4 The court held Proposition 8 unconstitu-
    that supported Proposition 8 but was not the measure’s official sponsor.
    We affirmed that decision in Perry v. Proposition 8 Official Proponents
    (Perry I), 
    587 F.3d 947
     (9th Cir. 2009). The district court also denied
    leave to intervene to a coalition of civil rights advocacy organizations. 
    Id.
    at 950 n.1.
    3
    A number of ancillary matters, none of which we need revisit here,
    were presented to this court immediately prior to and during the trial. First,
    we granted Proponents’ petition for a writ of mandamus to protect their
    First Amendment interests in campaign communications against intrusion
    by Plaintiffs’ discovery requests. Perry v. Schwarzenegger (Perry II), 
    591 F.3d 1147
     (9th Cir. 2010), amending and denying reh’g en banc of 
    591 F.3d 1126
     (9th Cir. 2009). Second, we denied a similar mandamus petition
    brought by three non-party organizations that had campaigned against
    Proposition 8. Perry v. Schwarzenegger (Perry III), 
    602 F.3d 976
     (9th Cir.
    2010). Finally, a motions panel of this court denied Proponents’ emer-
    gency petition for a writ of mandamus, filed on the eve of trial, to prohibit
    the district court from broadcasting the trial via streaming video and audio
    to a few federal courthouses around the country. The Supreme Court then
    granted Proponents’ application for a temporary and eventually permanent
    stay of the broadcast. Hollingsworth v. Perry, 
    130 S. Ct. 1132
     (2010)
    (mem.); Hollingsworth v. Perry, 
    130 S. Ct. 705
     (2010).
    4
    The court found, among other things, that (1) marriage benefits society
    by organizing individuals into cohesive family units, developing a realm
    of liberty for intimacy and free decision making, creating stable house-
    holds, legitimating children, assigning individuals to care for one another,
    and facilitating property ownership, id. at 961; (2) marriage benefits
    spouses and their children physically, psychologically, and economically,
    id. at 962-63, whether the spouses are of the same or opposite sexes, id.
    at 969-70; (3) domestic partnerships lack the social meaning associated
    with marriage, id. at 970, 973-75; (4) permitting same-sex couples to
    marry would not affect the number or stability of opposite-sex marriages,
    id. at 972-73; (5) the children of same-sex couples benefit when their par-
    1598                         PERRY v. BROWN
    tional under the Due Process Clause because no compelling
    state interest justifies denying same-sex couples the funda-
    mental right to marry. Id. at 991-95. The court also deter-
    mined that Proposition 8 violated the Equal Protection Clause,
    because there is no rational basis for limiting the designation
    of ‘marriage’ to opposite-sex couples. Id. at 997-1003. The
    court therefore entered the following injunction: “Defendants
    in their official capacities, and all persons under the control
    or supervision of defendants, are permanently enjoined from
    applying or enforcing Article I, § 7.5 of the California Constitu-
    tion.”5 Doc. 728 (Permanent Injunction), Perry v. Schwar-
    zenegger, No. 09-cv-02292 (N.D. Cal. Aug. 12, 2010).6
    B
    Proponents appealed immediately, and a motions panel of
    this court stayed the district court’s injunction pending appeal.
    ents marry, and they fare just as well as children raised by opposite-sex
    parents, id. at 973, 980-81; (6) Proposition 8 stigmatizes same-sex couples
    as having relationships inferior to those of opposite-sex couples, id. at
    973-74, 979-80; (7) Proposition 8 eliminated same-sex couples’ right to
    marry but did not affect any other substantive right they enjoyed, id. at
    977; and (8) the campaign in favor of Proposition 8 relied upon stereo-
    types and unfounded fears about gays and lesbians, id. at 988-91.
    5
    Without explanation, the district court failed to enter a separate declar-
    atory judgment as Plaintiffs had requested. The court’s opinion made clear
    its holding “that Proposition 8 is unconstitutional.” 
    704 F. Supp. 2d at 1003
    . But the clerk apparently never issued this declaratory judgment as
    a separate document, as Fed. R. Civ. P. 58 requires.
    6
    Concurrently with its decision on the merits of Plaintiffs’ claim, the
    district court denied a motion to intervene as a defendant brought by Impe-
    rial County, its board of supervisors, and one of its Deputy County Clerks.
    We affirmed the district court’s denial of the motion, on alternative
    grounds, in Perry v. Schwarzenegger (Perry VI), 
    630 F.3d 898
     (9th Cir.
    2011). The newly elected County Clerk of Imperial County subsequently
    moved to intervene in this court in the companion appeal, No. 10-16751.
    In light of the fact that Proponents have standing to appeal, we deny the
    motion as untimely but have considered the Clerk’s filings as briefs amici
    curiae.
    PERRY v. BROWN                          1599
    The motions panel asked the parties to discuss in their briefs,
    as a preliminary matter, whether the Proponents had standing
    to seek review of the district court order. After considering
    the parties’ arguments, we concluded that Proponents’ stand-
    ing to appeal depended on the precise rights and interests
    given to official sponsors of an initiative under California law,
    which had never been clearly defined by the State’s highest
    court. We therefore certified the following question to the
    California Supreme Court:
    Whether under Article II, Section 8 of the California
    Constitution, or otherwise under California law, the
    official proponents of an initiative measure possess
    either a particularized interest in the initiative’s
    validity or the authority to assert the State’s interest
    in the initiative’s validity, which would enable them
    to defend the constitutionality of the initiative upon
    its adoption or appeal a judgment invalidating the
    initiative, when the public officials charged with that
    duty refuse to do so.
    Perry v. Schwarzenegger (Perry V), 
    628 F.3d 1191
    , 1193 (9th
    Cir. 2011). The state court granted our request for certifica-
    tion in February 2011, and in November 2011 rendered its
    decision. See Perry v. Brown (Perry VII), 
    134 Cal. Rptr. 3d 499
    ( 2011). We now resume consideration of this appeal.7
    III
    We begin, as we must, with the issue that has prolonged
    our consideration of this case: whether we have jurisdiction
    over an appeal brought by the defendant-intervenor Propo-
    nents, rather than the defendant state and local officers who
    were directly enjoined by the district court order.8 In view of
    7
    We vacated submission of this case upon ordering that our question be
    certified to the California Supreme Court. Perry V, 628 F.3d at 1200. The
    case is now ordered resubmitted.
    8
    Although we regret the delay that our need to resolve this issue has
    caused, we note that this delay was not of our own making. See Perry V,
    1600                       PERRY v. BROWN
    Proponents’ authority under California law, we conclude that
    they do have standing to appeal.
    For purposes of Article III standing, we start with the prem-
    ise that “a State has standing to defend the constitutionality of
    its [laws].” Diamond v. Charles, 
    476 U.S. 54
    , 62 (1986).
    When a state law is ruled unconstitutional, either the state or
    a state officer charged with the law’s enforcement may appeal
    that determination. Typically, the named defendant in an
    action challenging the constitutionality of a state law is a state
    officer, because sovereign immunity protects the state from
    being sued directly. See Ex parte Young, 
    209 U.S. 123
    , 157-
    58 (1908); L.A. County Bar Ass’n v. Eu, 
    979 F.2d 697
    , 704
    (9th Cir. 1992). In such cases, if a court invalidates the state
    law and enjoins its enforcement, there is no question that the
    state officer is entitled to appeal that determination. See, e.g.,
    Ysursa v. Pocatello Educ. Ass’n, 
    555 U.S. 353
     (2009) (Idaho
    Secretary of State and Attorney General appealed decision
    striking down an Idaho law on First Amendment grounds);
    Stenberg v. Carhart, 
    530 U.S. 914
     (2000) (Nebraska Attorney
    General appealed decision holding unconstitutional a
    Nebraska abortion law). Moreover, there is no reason that a
    state itself may not also choose to intervene as a defendant,
    and indeed a state must be permitted to intervene if a state
    officer is not already party to an action in which the constitu-
    tionality of a state law is challenged. See 
    28 U.S.C. § 2403
    (b);
    Fed. R. Civ. P. 5.1; cf. Fed. R. App. P. 44(b). When a state
    does elect to become a defendant itself, the state may appeal
    an adverse decision about the constitutionality of one of its
    laws, just as a state officer may. See, e.g., Caruso v. Yamhill
    County ex rel. County Comm’r, 
    422 F.3d 848
    , 852-53 & n.2
    (9th Cir. 2005) (sole appellant was the State of Oregon, which
    had intervened as a defendant in the district court). In other
    628 F.3d at 1200-02 (Reinhardt, J., concurring). We are grateful to the
    California Supreme Court for the thoughtful and full consideration it gave
    our question.
    PERRY v. BROWN                          1601
    words, in a suit for an injunction against enforcement of an
    allegedly unconstitutional state law, it makes no practical dif-
    ference whether the formal party before the court is the state
    itself or a state officer in his official capacity. Cf. Pennhurst
    State Sch. & Hosp. v. Halderman, 
    465 U.S. 89
    , 114 n.25
    (1984) (discussing the “fiction” of Ex parte Young); see also
    Idaho v. Coeur d’Alene Tribe of Idaho, 
    521 U.S. 261
    , 269-70
    (1997) (same).
    Whether the defendant is the state or a state officer, the
    decision to assert the state’s own interest in the constitutional-
    ity of its laws is most commonly made by the state’s execu-
    tive branch—the part of state government that is usually
    charged with enforcing and defending state law. See, e.g.,
    Ysursa, 
    555 U.S. at 354
     (Idaho state officers represented by
    state Attorney General); Caruso, 
    422 F.3d at 851
     (State of
    Oregon represented by Oregon Department of Justice). Some
    sovereigns vest the authority to assert their interest in litiga-
    tion exclusively in certain executive officers. See, e.g., 
    28 U.S.C. §§ 516-19
    ; 
    28 C.F.R. § 0.20
    .
    The states need not follow that approach, however. It is
    their prerogative, as independent sovereigns, to decide for
    themselves who may assert their interests and under what cir-
    cumstances, and to bestow that authority accordingly. In Kar-
    cher v. May, 
    484 U.S. 72
     (1987), for example, the Supreme
    Court held that the State of New Jersey was properly repre-
    sented in litigation by the Speaker of the General Assembly
    and the President of the Senate, appearing on behalf of the
    Legislature, because “the New Jersey Legislature had author-
    ity under state law to represent the State’s interests.” 
    Id.
     at 82
    (citing In re Forsythe, 
    450 A.2d 499
    , 500 (N.J. 1982)).9 Prin-
    9
    See also Richardson v. Ramirez, 
    418 U.S. 24
     (1974), in which a county
    clerk was not barred from appealing a judgment invalidating California’s
    felon disenfranchisement law, even though the only state officer who had
    been sued, then-California Secretary of State Edmund G. Brown, Jr.,
    refused to pursue the appeal. 
    Id.
     at 26 n.1, 36-38.
    1602                     PERRY v. BROWN
    ciples of federalism require that federal courts respect such
    decisions by the states as to who may speak for them: “there
    are limits on the Federal Government’s power to affect the
    internal operations of a State.” Va. Office for Protection &
    Advocacy v. Stewart, 
    131 S. Ct. 1632
    , 1641 (2011). It is not
    for a federal court to tell a state who may appear on its behalf
    any more than it is for Congress to direct state law-
    enforcement officers to administer a federal regulatory
    scheme, see Printz v. United States, 
    521 U.S. 898
     (1997), to
    command a state to take ownership of waste generated within
    its borders, see New York v. United States, 
    505 U.S. 144
    (1992), or to dictate where a state shall locate its capital, see
    Coyle v. Smith, 
    221 U.S. 559
     (1911). Who may speak for the
    state is, necessarily, a question of state law. All a federal court
    need determine is that the state has suffered a harm sufficient
    to confer standing and that the party seeking to invoke the
    jurisdiction of the court is authorized by the state to represent
    its interest in remedying that harm.
    Proponents claim to assert the interest of the People of Cal-
    ifornia in the constitutionality of Proposition 8, which the
    People themselves enacted. When faced with a case arising in
    a similar posture, in which an Arizona initiative constitutional
    amendment was defended only by its sponsors, the Supreme
    Court expressed “grave doubts” about the sponsors’ standing
    given that the Court was “aware of no Arizona law appointing
    initiative sponsors as agents of the people of Arizona to
    defend, in lieu of public officials, the constitutionality of ini-
    tiatives made law of the State.” Arizonans for Official English
    v. Arizona (Arizonans), 
    520 U.S. 43
    , 65-66 (1997). Absent
    some conferral of authority by state law, akin to the authority
    that the New Jersey legislators in Karcher had as “elected rep-
    resentatives,” the Court suggested that proponents of a ballot
    measure would not be able to appeal a decision striking down
    the initiative they sponsored. 
    Id. at 65
    .
    [1] Here, unlike in Arizonans, we do know that California
    law confers on “initiative sponsors” the authority “to defend,
    PERRY v. BROWN                        1603
    in lieu of public officials, the constitutionality of initiatives
    made law of the State.” The California Supreme Court has
    told us, in a published opinion containing an exhaustive
    review of the California Constitution and statutes, that it does.
    In answering our certified question, the court held
    that when the public officials who ordinarily defend
    a challenged state law or appeal a judgment invali-
    dating the law decline to do so, under article II, sec-
    tion 8 of the California Constitution and the relevant
    provisions of the Elections Code, the official propo-
    nents of a voter-approved initiative measure are
    authorized to assert the state’s interest in the initia-
    tive’s validity, enabling the proponents to defend the
    constitutionality of the initiative and to appeal a
    judgment invalidating the initiative.
    Perry VII, 134 Cal. Rptr. 3d at 536-37. “[T]he role played by
    the proponents in such litigation,” the court explained, “is
    comparable to the role ordinarily played by the Attorney Gen-
    eral or other public officials in vigorously defending a duly
    enacted state law and raising all arguable legal theories upon
    which a challenged provision may be sustained.” Id. at 525.
    The State’s highest court thus held that California law pro-
    vides precisely what the Arizonans Court found lacking in
    Arizona law: it confers on the official proponents of an initia-
    tive the authority to assert the State’s interests in defending
    the constitutionality of that initiative, where the state officials
    who would ordinarily assume that responsibility choose not to
    do so.
    We are bound to accept the California court’s determina-
    tion. Although other states may act differently, California’s
    conferral upon proponents of the authority to represent the
    People’s interest in the initiative measure they sponsored is
    consistent with that state’s unparalleled commitment to the
    authority of the electorate: “No other state in the nation car-
    ries the concept of initiatives as ‘written in stone’ to such
    1604                    PERRY v. BROWN
    lengths as” does California. People v. Kelly, 
    222 P.3d 186
    ,
    200 (Cal. 2010) (internal quotation marks omitted). Indeed,
    California defines the initiative power as “one of the most
    precious rights of our democratic process,” and considers “the
    sovereign people’s initiative power” to be a “fundamental
    right” under the state constitution. Assoc. Home Builders v.
    City of Livermore, 
    557 P.2d 473
    , 477 (Cal. 1976); Brosnahan
    v. Brown, 
    651 P.2d 274
    , 277 (Cal. 1982); Costa v. Super. Ct.,
    
    128 P.3d 675
    , 686 (Cal. 2006). As the California Supreme
    Court explained in answering our certified question, “[t]he
    initiative power would be significantly impaired if there were
    no one to assert the state’s interest in the validity of the mea-
    sure when elected officials decline to defend it in court or to
    appeal a judgment invalidating the measure.” Perry VII, 134
    Cal. Rptr. 3d at 523. The authority of official proponents to
    “assert[ ] the state’s interest in the validity of an initiative
    measure” thus “serves to safeguard the unique elements and
    integrity of the initiative process.” Id. at 533.
    It matters not whether federal courts think it wise or desir-
    able for California to afford proponents this authority to speak
    for the State, just as it makes no difference whether federal
    courts think it a good idea that California allows its constitu-
    tion to be amended by a majority vote through a ballot mea-
    sure in the first place. Cf. Pac. States Tel. & Tel. Co. v.
    Oregon, 
    223 U.S. 118
     (1912) (holding nonjusticiable a Guar-
    anty Clause challenge to Oregon’s initiative system). The
    People of California are largely free to structure their system
    of governance as they choose, and we respect their choice. All
    that matters, for federal standing purposes, is that the People
    have an interest in the validity of Proposition 8 and that, under
    California law, Proponents are authorized to represent the
    People’s interest. That is the case here.
    In their supplemental brief on the issue of standing, Plain-
    tiffs argue for the first time that Proponents must satisfy the
    requirements of third-party standing in order to assert the
    interests of the State of California in this litigation. Litigants
    PERRY v. BROWN                        1605
    who wish “to bring actions on behalf of third parties” must
    satisfy three requirements. Powers v. Ohio, 
    499 U.S. 400
    ,
    410-11 (1991). First, they “must have suffered an ‘injury in
    fact,’ thus giving [them] a ‘sufficiently concrete interest’ in
    the outcome of the issue in dispute.” 
    Id. at 411
    . Second, they
    “must have a close relation to the third party.” 
    Id.
     Third,
    “there must exist some hindrance to the third party’s ability
    to protect his or her own interests.” 
    Id.
     Plaintiffs contend that
    Proponents cannot satisfy these requirements with respect to
    the State of California as a third party.
    The requirements of third-party standing, however, are
    beside the point: the State of California is no more a “third
    party” relative to Proponents than it is to the executive offi-
    cers of the State who ordinarily assert the State’s interest in
    litigation. As the California Supreme Court has explained,
    “the role played by the proponents” in litigation “regarding
    the validity or proper interpretation of a voter-approved initia-
    tive measure . . . is comparable to the role ordinarily played
    by the Attorney General or other public officials in vigorously
    defending a duly enacted state law.” Perry VII, 134 Cal. Rptr.
    3d at 525. When the Attorney General of California appears
    in federal court to defend the validity of a state statute, she
    obviously need not satisfy the requirements of third-party
    standing; she stands in the shoes of the State to assert its inter-
    ests in litigation. For the purposes of the litigation, she speaks
    to the court as the State, not as a third party. The same is true
    of Proponents here, just as it was true of the presiding legisla-
    tive officers in Karcher, 
    484 U.S. at 82
    . The requirements of
    third-party standing are therefore not relevant.
    [2] Nor is it relevant whether Proponents have suffered a
    personal injury, in their capacities as private individuals.
    Although we asked the California Supreme Court whether
    “the official proponents of an initiative measure possess either
    a particularized interest in the initiative’s validity or the
    authority to assert the State’s interest in the initiative’s validi-
    ty,” Perry V, 628 F.3d at 1193 (emphasis added), the Court
    1606                         PERRY v. BROWN
    chose to address only the latter type of interest. Perry VII, 134
    Cal. Rptr. 3d at 515 (“Because [our] conclusion [that propo-
    nents are authorized to assert the State’s interest] is sufficient
    to support an affirmative response to the question posed by
    the Ninth Circuit, we need not decide whether, under Califor-
    nia law, the official proponents also possess a particularized
    interest in a voter-approved initiative’s validity.”). The exclu-
    sive basis of our holding that Proponents possess Article III
    standing is their authority to assert the interests of the State
    of California, rather than any authority that they might have
    to assert particularized interests of their own. Just as the
    Attorney General of California need not satisfy the require-
    ments of third-party standing when she appears in federal
    court to defend the validity of a state statute, she obviously
    need not show that she would suffer any personal injury as a
    result of the statute’s invalidity. The injury of which she com-
    plains is the State’s, not her own. The same is true here.
    Because “a State has standing to defend the constitutionality
    of its [laws],” Diamond, 
    476 U.S. at 62
    , Proponents need not
    show that they would suffer any personal injury from the
    invalidation of Proposition 8. That the State would suffer an
    injury, 
    id.,
     is enough for Proponents to have Article III stand-
    ing when state law authorizes them to assert the State’s inter-
    ests.
    To be clear, we do not suggest that state law has any
    “power directly to enlarge or contract federal jurisdiction.”
    Duchek v. Jacobi, 
    646 F.2d 415
    , 419 (9th Cir. 1981). “Stand-
    ing to sue in any Article III court is, of course, a federal ques-
    tion which does not depend on the party’s . . . standing in state
    court.” Phillips Petroleum Co. v. Shutts, 
    472 U.S. 797
    , 804
    (1985). State courts may afford litigants standing to appear
    where federal courts would not,10 but whether they do so has
    no bearing on the parties’ Article III standing in federal court.
    10
    Cf. City of Los Angeles v. Lyons, 
    461 U.S. 95
    , 113 (1983) (“[T]he
    state courts need not impose the same standing or remedial requirements
    that govern federal-court proceedings. The individual States may permit
    their courts to use injunctions to oversee the conduct of law enforcement
    authorities on a continuing basis. But this is not the role of a federal court
    . . . .”).
    PERRY v. BROWN                        1607
    [3] State law does have the power, however, to answer
    questions antecedent to determining federal standing, such as
    the one here: who is authorized to assert the People’s interest
    in the constitutionality of an initiative measure? Because the
    State of California has Article III standing to defend the con-
    stitutionality of Proposition 8, and because both the California
    Constitution and California law authorize “the official propo-
    nents of [an] initiative . . . to appear and assert the state’s
    interest in the initiative’s validity and to appeal a judgment
    invalidating the measure when the public officials who ordi-
    narily defend the measure or appeal such a judgment decline
    to do so,” Perry VII, 134 Cal. Rptr. 3d at 505, we conclude
    that Proponents are proper appellants here. They possess Arti-
    cle III standing to prosecute this appeal from the district
    court’s judgment invalidating Proposition 8.
    IV
    We review the district court’s decision to grant a permanent
    injunction for abuse of discretion, but we review the determi-
    nations underlying that decision by the standard that applies
    to each determination. Accordingly, we review the court’s
    conclusions of law de novo and its findings of fact for clear
    error. See Ting v. AT&T, 
    319 F.3d 1126
    , 1134-35 (9th Cir.
    2003); Fed. R. Civ. P. 52(a).
    Plaintiffs and Proponents dispute whether the district
    court’s findings of fact concern the types of “facts”—so-
    called “adjudicative facts”—that are capable of being “found”
    by a court through the clash of proofs presented in adjudica-
    tion, as opposed to “legislative facts,” which are generally not
    capable of being found in that fashion. “Adjudicative facts are
    facts about the parties and their activities . . . , usually answer-
    ing the questions of who did what, where, when, how, why,
    with what motive or intent”—the types of “facts that go to a
    jury in a jury case,” or to the factfinder in a bench trial. Mar-
    shall v. Sawyer, 
    365 F.2d 105
    , 111 (9th Cir. 1966) (quoting
    Kenneth Culp Davis, The Requirement of a Trial-Type Hear-
    1608                    PERRY v. BROWN
    ing, 
    70 Harv. L. Rev. 193
    , 199 (1956)) (internal quotation
    marks omitted). “Legislative facts,” by contrast, “do not usu-
    ally concern [only] the immediate parties but are general facts
    which help the tribunal decide questions of law, policy, and
    discretion.” 
    Id.
    It is debatable whether some of the district court’s findings
    of fact concerning matters of history or social science are
    more appropriately characterized as “legislative facts” or as
    “adjudicative facts.” We need not resolve what standard of
    review should apply to any such findings, however, because
    the only findings to which we give any deferential weight—
    those concerning the messages in support of Proposition 8
    that Proponents communicated to the voters to encourage
    their approval of the measure, Perry IV, 
    704 F. Supp. 2d at
    990-91—are clearly “adjudicative facts” concerning the par-
    ties and “ ‘who did what, where, when, how, why, with what
    motive or intent.’ ” Marshall, 
    365 F.2d at 111
    . Aside from
    these findings, the only fact found by the district court that
    matters to our analysis is that “[d]omestic partnerships lack
    the social meaning associated with marriage”—that the differ-
    ence between the designation of ‘marriage’ and the designa-
    tion of ‘domestic partnership’ is meaningful. Perry IV, 
    704 F. Supp. 2d at 970
    . This fact was conceded by Proponents during
    discovery. Defendant-Intervenors’ Response to Plaintiffs’
    First Set of Requests for Admission, Exhibit No. PX 0707, at
    2 (“Proponents admit that the word ‘marriage’ has a unique
    meaning.”); id. at 11 (Proponents “[a]dmit that there is a sig-
    nificant symbolic disparity between domestic partnership and
    marriage”). Our analysis therefore does not hinge on what
    standard we use to review the district court’s findings of fact.
    Cf. Lockhart v. McCree, 
    476 U.S. 162
    , 168 n.3 (1986)
    (“Because we do not ultimately base our decision today on the
    [validity or] invalidity of the lower courts’ ‘factual’ findings,
    we need not decide the ‘standard of review’ issue”—whether
    “the ‘clearly erroneous’ standard of Rule 52(a) applies to the
    kind of ‘legislative’ facts at issue here.”).
    PERRY v. BROWN                     1609
    V
    We now turn to the merits of Proposition 8’s constitutional-
    ity.
    A
    The district court held Proposition 8 unconstitutional for
    two reasons: first, it deprives same-sex couples of the funda-
    mental right to marry, which is guaranteed by the Due Process
    Clause, see Perry IV, 
    704 F. Supp. 2d at 991-95
    ; and second,
    it excludes same-sex couples from state-sponsored marriage
    while allowing opposite-sex couples access to that honored
    status, in violation of the Equal Protection Clause, see 
    id. at 997-1003
    . Plaintiffs elaborate upon those arguments on
    appeal.
    Plaintiffs and Plaintiff-Intervenor San Francisco also offer
    a third argument: Proposition 8 singles out same-sex couples
    for unequal treatment by taking away from them alone the
    right to marry, and this action amounts to a distinct constitu-
    tional violation because the Equal Protection Clause protects
    minority groups from being targeted for the deprivation of an
    existing right without a legitimate reason. Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 634-35
    . Because this third argument applies to the specific
    history of same-sex marriage in California, it is the narrowest
    ground for adjudicating the constitutional questions before us,
    while the first two theories, if correct, would apply on a
    broader basis. Because courts generally decide constitutional
    questions on the narrowest ground available, we consider the
    third argument first. See Plaut v. Spendthrift Farm, Inc., 
    514 U.S. 211
    , 217 (1995) (citing Ashwander v. Tenn. Valley Auth.,
    
    297 U.S. 288
    , 347 (1936) (Brandeis, J., concurring)).
    B
    [4] Proposition 8 worked a singular and limited change to
    the California Constitution: it stripped same-sex couples of
    1610                        PERRY v. BROWN
    the right to have their committed relationships recognized by
    the State with the designation of ‘marriage,’ which the state
    constitution had previously guaranteed them, while leaving in
    place all of their other rights and responsibilities as partners—
    rights and responsibilities that are identical to those of mar-
    ried spouses and form an integral part of the marriage rela-
    tionship. In determining that the law had this effect, “[w]e
    rely not upon our own interpretation of the amendment but
    upon the authoritative construction of [California’s] Supreme
    Court.” Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 626
    . The state high court held in
    Strauss that “Proposition 8 reasonably must be interpreted in
    a limited fashion as eliminating only the right of same-sex
    couples to equal access to the designation of marriage, and as
    not otherwise affecting the constitutional right of those cou-
    ples to establish an officially recognized family relationship,”
    which California calls a ‘domestic partnership.’ 207 P.3d at
    76. Proposition 8 “leaves intact all of the other very signifi-
    cant constitutional protections afforded same-sex couples,”
    including “the constitutional right to enter into an officially
    recognized and protected family relationship with the person
    of one’s choice and to raise children in that family if the cou-
    ple so chooses.” Id. at 102. Thus, the extent of the amend-
    ment’s effect was to “establish[ ] a new substantive state
    constitutional rule,” id. at 63, which “carves out a narrow and
    limited exception to these state constitutional rights,” by “re-
    serving the official designation of the term ‘marriage’ for the
    union of opposite-sex couples as a matter of state constitu-
    tional law,” id. at 61.11
    11
    In rejecting the argument that Proposition 8 had impermissibly
    revised, rather than amended, the state constitution, Strauss explained that
    it “drastically overstates the effect of Proposition 8 on the fundamental
    state constitutional rights of same-sex couples” to suggest that the proposi-
    tion “ ‘eliminat[ed]’ or ‘stripp[ed]’ same-sex couples of a fundamental
    constitutional right,” because the substantive protections of the state equal
    protection clause and due process and privacy provisions remained intact
    —with the “sole, albeit significant, exception” of the right to use the des-
    ignation of ‘marriage,’ which was eliminated for same-sex couples. 207
    P.3d at 102.
    PERRY v. BROWN                        1611
    Both before and after Proposition 8, same-sex partners
    could enter into an official, state-recognized relationship that
    affords them “the same rights, protections, and benefits” as an
    opposite-sex union and subjects them “to the same responsi-
    bilities, obligations, and duties under law, whether they derive
    from statutes, administrative regulations, court rules, govern-
    ment policies, common law, or any other provisions or
    sources of law, as are granted to and imposed upon spouses.”
    
    Cal. Fam. Code § 297.5
    (a). Now as before, same-sex partners
    may:
    •   Raise children together, and have the same rights
    and obligations as to their children as spouses
    have, see 
    Cal. Fam. Code § 297.5
    (d);
    •   Enjoy the presumption of parentage as to a child
    born to either partner, see Elisa B. v. Super. Ct.,
    
    117 P.3d 660
    , 670 (Cal. 2005); Kristine M. v.
    David P., 
    135 Cal. App. 4th 783
     (2006); or
    adopted by one partner and raised jointly by both,
    S.Y. v. S.B., 
    201 Cal. App. 4th 1023
     (2011);
    •   Adopt each other’s children, see 
    Cal. Fam. Code § 9000
    (g);
    •   Become foster parents, see 
    Cal. Welf. & Inst. Code § 16013
    (a);
    •   Share community property, see 
    Cal. Fam. Code § 297.5
    (k);
    •   File state taxes jointly, see 
    Cal. Rev. & Tax. Code § 18521
    (d);
    •   Participate in a partner’s group health insurance
    policy on the same terms as a spouse, see 
    Cal. Ins. Code § 10121.7
    ;
    1612                    PERRY v. BROWN
    •   Enjoy hospital visitation privileges, see 
    Cal. Health & Safety Code § 1261
    ;
    •   Make medical decisions on behalf of an incapaci-
    tated partner, see 
    Cal. Prob. Code § 4716
    ;
    •   Be treated in a manner equal to that of a widow
    or widower with respect to a deceased partner,
    see 
    Cal. Fam. Code § 297.5
    (c);
    •   Serve as the conservator of a partner’s estate, see
    
    Cal. Prob. Code §§ 1811-1813.1
    ; and
    •   Sue for the wrongful death of a partner, see 
    Cal. Civ. Proc. Code § 377.60
    —among many other
    things.
    Proposition 8 did not affect these rights or any of the other
    “ ‘constitutionally based incidents of marriage’ ” guaranteed
    to same-sex couples and their families. Strauss, 207 P.3d at
    61 (quoting Marriage Cases, 183 P.3d at 434). In adopting
    the amendment, the People simply took the designation of
    ‘marriage’ away from lifelong same-sex partnerships, and
    with it the State’s authorization of that official status and the
    societal approval that comes with it.
    By emphasizing Proposition 8’s limited effect, we do not
    mean to minimize the harm that this change in the law caused
    to same-sex couples and their families. To the contrary, we
    emphasize the extraordinary significance of the official desig-
    nation of ‘marriage.’ That designation is important because
    ‘marriage’ is the name that society gives to the relationship
    that matters most between two adults. A rose by any other
    name may smell as sweet, but to the couple desiring to enter
    into a committed lifelong relationship, a marriage by the name
    of ‘registered domestic partnership’ does not. The word ‘mar-
    riage’ is singular in connoting “a harmony in living,” “a bilat-
    eral loyalty,” and “a coming together for better or for worse,
    PERRY v. BROWN                     1613
    hopefully enduring, and intimate to the degree of being
    sacred.” Griswold v. Connecticut, 
    381 U.S. 479
    , 486 (1965).
    As Proponents have admitted, “the word ‘marriage’ has a
    unique meaning,” and “there is a significant symbolic dispar-
    ity between domestic partnership and marriage.” It is the des-
    ignation of ‘marriage’ itself that expresses validation, by the
    state and the community, and that serves as a symbol, like a
    wedding ceremony or a wedding ring, of something pro-
    foundly important. See id. at 971.
    We need consider only the many ways in which we
    encounter the word ‘marriage’ in our daily lives and under-
    stand it, consciously or not, to convey a sense of significance.
    We are regularly given forms to complete that ask us whether
    we are “single” or “married.” Newspapers run announcements
    of births, deaths, and marriages. We are excited to see some-
    one ask, “Will you marry me?”, whether on bended knee in
    a restaurant or in text splashed across a stadium Jumbotron.
    Certainly it would not have the same effect to see “Will you
    enter into a registered domestic partnership with me?”.
    Groucho Marx’s one-liner, “Marriage is a wonderful institu-
    tion . . . but who wants to live in an institution?” would lack
    its punch if the word ‘marriage’ were replaced with the alter-
    native phrase. So too with Shakespeare’s “A young man mar-
    ried is a man that’s marr’d,” Lincoln’s “Marriage is neither
    heaven nor hell, it is simply purgatory,” and Sinatra’s “A man
    doesn’t know what happiness is until he’s married. By then
    it’s too late.” We see tropes like “marrying for love” versus
    “marrying for money” played out again and again in our films
    and literature because of the recognized importance and per-
    manence of the marriage relationship. Had Marilyn Monroe’s
    film been called How to Register a Domestic Partnership with
    a Millionaire, it would not have conveyed the same meaning
    as did her famous movie, even though the underlying drama
    for same-sex couples is no different. The name ‘marriage’ sig-
    nifies the unique recognition that society gives to harmonious,
    loyal, enduring, and intimate relationships. See Knight v.
    Super. Ct., 
    128 Cal. App. 4th 14
    , 31 (2005) (“[M]arriage is
    1614                       PERRY v. BROWN
    considered a more substantial relationship and is accorded a
    greater stature than a domestic partnership.”); cf. Griswold,
    
    381 U.S. at 486
    .
    The official, cherished status of ‘marriage’ is distinct from
    the incidents of marriage, such as those listed in the California
    Family Code. The incidents are both elements of the institu-
    tion and manifestations of the recognition that the State
    affords to those who are in stable and committed lifelong rela-
    tionships. We allow spouses but not siblings or roommates to
    file taxes jointly, for example, because we acknowledge the
    financial interdependence of those who have entered into an
    “enduring” relationship. The incidents of marriage, standing
    alone, do not, however, convey the same governmental and
    societal recognition as does the designation of ‘marriage’
    itself. We do not celebrate when two people merge their bank
    accounts; we celebrate when a couple marries. The designa-
    tion of ‘marriage’ is the status that we recognize. It is the
    principal manner in which the State attaches respect and dig-
    nity to the highest form of a committed relationship and to the
    individuals who have entered into it.12
    [5] We set this forth because we must evaluate Proposition
    8’s constitutionality in light of its actual and specific effects
    on committed same-sex couples desiring to enter into an offi-
    cially recognized lifelong relationship. Before Proposition 8,
    California guaranteed gays and lesbians both the incidents and
    the status and dignity of marriage. Proposition 8 left the inci-
    dents but took away the status and the dignity. It did so by
    12
    Cf. Marriage Cases, 183 P.3d at 434-35 (“[D]rawing a distinction
    between the name assigned to the family relationship available to
    opposite-sex couples and the name assigned to the family relationship
    available to same-sex couples, and . . . reserving the historic and highly
    respected designation of marriage exclusively to opposite-sex couples
    while offering same-sex couples only the new and unfamiliar designation
    of domestic partnership[,] pose[s] a serious risk of denying the official
    family relationship of same-sex couples the equal dignity and respect that
    is a core element of the constitutional right to marry.”).
    PERRY v. BROWN                      1615
    superseding the Marriage Cases and thus endorsing the “offi-
    cial statement that the family relationship of same-sex couples
    is not of comparable stature or equal dignity to the family
    relationship of opposite-sex couples.” Marriage Cases, 183
    P.3d at 452. The question we therefore consider is this: did
    the People of California have legitimate reasons for enacting
    a constitutional amendment that serves only to take away
    from same-sex couples the right to have their lifelong rela-
    tionships dignified by the official status of ‘marriage,’ and to
    compel the State and its officials and all others authorized to
    perform marriage ceremonies to substitute the label of
    ‘domestic partnership’ for their relationships?
    Proponents resist this framing of the question. They deem
    it irrelevant to our inquiry that the California Constitution, as
    interpreted by the Marriage Cases, had previously guaranteed
    same-sex couples the right to use the designation of ‘mar-
    riage,’ because In re Marriage Cases was a “short-lived deci-
    sion,” and same-sex couples were allowed to marry only
    during a “143-day hiatus” between the effective date of the
    Marriage Cases decision and the enactment of Proposition 8.
    Proponents’ Reply Br. 75, 79-80. According to Proponents, a
    decision to “restore” the “traditional definition of marriage”
    is indistinguishable from a decision to “adhere” to that defini-
    tion in the first place. Id. at 79-80. We are bound, however,
    by the California Supreme Court’s authoritative interpretation
    of Proposition 8’s effect on California law, see Romer, 
    517 U.S. at
    626: Proposition 8 “eliminat[ed] . . . the right of same-
    sex couples to equal access to the designation of marriage” by
    “carv[ing] out a narrow and limited exception to these state
    constitutional rights” that had previously guaranteed the des-
    ignation of ‘marriage’ to all couples, opposite-sex and same-
    sex alike. Strauss, 207 P.3d at 61, 76.
    Even were we not bound by the state court’s explanation,
    we would be obligated to consider Proposition 8 in light of its
    actual effect, which was, as the voters were told, to “eliminate
    the right of same-sex couples to marry in California.” Voter
    1616                    PERRY v. BROWN
    Information Guide at 54. The context matters. Withdrawing
    from a disfavored group the right to obtain a designation with
    significant societal consequences is different from declining
    to extend that designation in the first place, regardless of
    whether the right was withdrawn after a week, a year, or a
    decade. The action of changing something suggests a more
    deliberate purpose than does the inaction of leaving it as it is.
    As the California Supreme Court held, “Proposition 8 [did]
    not ‘readjudicate’ the issue that was litigated and resolved in
    the Marriage Cases.” Strauss, 207 P.3d at 63. Rather than
    “declar[ing] the state of the law as it existed under the Cali-
    fornia Constitution at the time of the Marriage Cases,” Propo-
    sition 8 “establishe[d] a new substantive state constitutional
    rule that took effect upon” its adoption by the electorate. Id.
    (emphasis added). Whether or not it is a historical accident,
    as Proponents argue, that Proposition 8 postdated the Mar-
    riage Cases rather than predating and thus preempting that
    decision, the relative timing of the two events is a fact, and
    we must decide this case on its facts.
    C
    1
    This is not the first time the voters of a state have enacted
    an initiative constitutional amendment that reduces the rights
    of gays and lesbians under state law. In 1992, Colorado
    adopted Amendment 2 to its state constitution, which prohib-
    ited the state and its political subdivisions from providing any
    protection against discrimination on the basis of sexual orien-
    tation. See Colo. Const. art. II, § 30b. Amendment 2 was pro-
    posed in response to a number of local ordinances that had
    banned sexual-orientation discrimination in such areas as
    housing, employment, education, public accommodations,
    and health and welfare services. The effect of Amendment 2
    was “to repeal” those local laws and “to prohibit any govern-
    mental entity from adopting similar, or more protective stat-
    utes, regulations, ordinances, or policies in the future.” Evans
    PERRY v. BROWN                            1617
    v. Romer, 
    854 P.2d 1270
    , 1284-85 (Colo. 1993). The law thus
    “withdr[ew] from homosexuals, but no others, specific legal
    protection . . . , and it forb[ade] reinstatement of these laws
    and policies.” Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 627
    .
    [6] The Supreme Court held that Amendment 2 violated
    the Equal Protection Clause because “[i]t is not within our
    constitutional tradition to enact laws of this sort”—laws that
    “singl[e] out a certain class of citizens for disfavored legal
    status,” which “raise the inevitable inference that the disad-
    vantage imposed is born of animosity toward the class of per-
    sons affected.” 
    Id. at 633-34
    . The Court considered possible
    justifications for Amendment 2 that might have overcome the
    “inference” of animus, but it found them all lacking. It there-
    fore concluded that the law “classifie[d] homosexuals not to
    further a proper legislative end but to make them unequal to
    everyone else.” 
    Id. at 635
    .13
    [7] Proposition 8 is remarkably similar to Amendment 2.
    Like Amendment 2, Proposition 8 “single[s] out a certain
    class of citizens for disfavored legal status . . . .” 
    Id. at 633
    .
    Like Amendment 2, Proposition 8 has the “peculiar property,”
    
    id. at 632
    , of “withdraw[ing] from homosexuals, but no oth-
    ers,” an existing legal right—here, access to the official desig-
    nation of ‘marriage’—that had been broadly available,
    notwithstanding the fact that the Constitution did not compel
    the state to confer it in the first place. 
    Id. at 627
    . Like Amend-
    13
    Romer did not apply heightened scrutiny to Amendment 2, even
    though the amendment targeted gays and lesbians. Instead, Romer found
    that Amendment 2 “fail[ed], indeed defie[d], even [the] conventional
    inquiry” for non-suspect classes, concerning whether a “legislative classi-
    fication . . . bears a rational relation to some legitimate end.” Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 631-32
    . Amendment 2 amounted to “a classification of persons
    undertaken for its own sake, something the Equal Protection Clause does
    not permit.” 
    Id. at 635
    . We follow this approach and reach the same con-
    clusion as to Proposition 8. See also High Tech Gays v. Defense Indus.
    Sec. Clearance Office, 
    895 F.2d 563
    , 574 (9th Cir. 1990) (declining to
    apply heightened scrutiny).
    1618                    PERRY v. BROWN
    ment 2, Proposition 8 denies “equal protection of the laws in
    the most literal sense,” 
    id. at 633
    , because it “carves out” an
    “exception” to California’s equal protection clause, by remov-
    ing equal access to marriage, which gays and lesbians had
    previously enjoyed, from the scope of that constitutional guar-
    antee. Strauss, 207 P.3d at 61. Like Amendment 2, Proposi-
    tion 8 “by state decree . . . put[s] [homosexuals] in a solitary
    class with respect to” an important aspect of human relations,
    and accordingly “imposes a special disability upon [homosex-
    uals] alone.” Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 627, 631
    . And like Amend-
    ment 2, Proposition 8 constitutionalizes that disability,
    meaning that gays and lesbians may overcome it “only by
    enlisting the citizenry of [the state] to amend the State Consti-
    tution” for a second time. 
    Id. at 631
    . As we explain below,
    Romer compels that we affirm the judgment of the district
    court.
    To be sure, there are some differences between Amend-
    ment 2 and Proposition 8. Amendment 2 “impos[ed] a broad
    and undifferentiated disability on a single named group” by
    “identif[ying] persons by a single trait and then den[ying]
    them protection across the board.” Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 632-33
    .
    Proposition 8, by contrast, excises with surgical precision one
    specific right: the right to use the designation of ‘marriage’ to
    describe a couple’s officially recognized relationship. Propo-
    nents argue that Proposition 8 thus merely “restor[es] the tra-
    ditional definition of marriage while otherwise leaving
    undisturbed the manifold rights and protections California law
    provides gays and lesbians,” making it unlike Amendment 2,
    which eliminated various substantive rights. Proponents’
    Reply Br. 77.
    These differences, however, do not render Romer less
    applicable. It is no doubt true that the “special disability” that
    Proposition 8 “imposes upon” gays and lesbians has a less
    sweeping effect on their public and private transactions than
    did Amendment 2. Nevertheless, Proposition 8 works a mean-
    ingful harm to gays and lesbians, by denying to their commit-
    PERRY v. BROWN                           1619
    ted lifelong relationships the societal status conveyed by the
    designation of ‘marriage,’ and this harm must be justified by
    some legitimate state interest. Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 631
    . Propo-
    sition 8 is no less problematic than Amendment 2 merely
    because its effect is narrower; to the contrary, the surgical
    precision with which it excises a right belonging to gay and
    lesbian couples makes it even more suspect. A law that has no
    practical effect except to strip one group of the right to use a
    state-authorized and socially meaningful designation is all the
    more “unprecedented” and “unusual” than a law that imposes
    broader changes, and raises an even stronger “inference that
    the disadvantage imposed is born of animosity toward the
    class of persons affected,” 
    id. at 633-34
    . In short, Romer gov-
    erns our analysis notwithstanding the differences between
    Amendment 2 and Proposition 8.
    [8] There is one further important similarity between this
    case and Romer. Neither case requires that the voters have
    stripped the state’s gay and lesbian citizens of any federal
    constitutional right. In Romer, Amendment 2 deprived gays
    and lesbians of statutory protections against discrimination;
    here, Proposition 8 deprived same-sex partners of the right to
    use the designation of ‘marriage.’ There is no necessity in
    either case that the privilege, benefit, or protection at issue be
    a constitutional right. We therefore need not and do not con-
    sider whether same-sex couples have a fundamental right to
    marry, or whether states that fail to afford the right to marry
    to gays and lesbians must do so. Further, we express no view
    on those questions.14
    14
    Because we do not address the question of the constitutionality of a
    state’s ban on same-sex marriage, the Supreme Court’s summary dismissal
    of Baker v. Nelson, 
    409 U.S. 810
     (1972) (mem.), is not pertinent here.
    In Baker, the Court “dismissed for want of a substantial federal ques-
    tion” an appeal from the Minnesota Supreme Court’s decision to uphold
    a state statute that did not permit marriage between two people of the same
    sex. 
    Id.
     Such dismissals “prevent lower courts from coming to opposite
    conclusions on the precise issues presented and necessarily decided by”
    1620                        PERRY v. BROWN
    Ordinarily, “if a law neither burdens a fundamental right
    nor targets a suspect class, we will uphold the legislative clas-
    sification so long as it bears a rational relation to some legiti-
    mate end.” Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 631
    . Such was the case in
    Romer, and it is the case here as well. The end must be one
    that is legitimate for the government to pursue, not just one
    that would be legitimate for a private actor. See 
    id. at 632, 635
    . The question here, then, is whether California had any
    more legitimate justification for withdrawing from gays and
    lesbians its constitutional protection with respect to the offi-
    cial designation of ‘marriage’ than Colorado did for with-
    drawing from that group all protection against discrimination
    generally.
    Proposition 8, like Amendment 2, enacts a
    “ ‘[d]iscrimination[ ] of an unusual character,’ ” which
    requires “ ‘careful consideration to determine whether [it] [is]
    obnoxious to the’ ” Constitution. 
    Id. at 633
     (quoting Louis-
    ville Gas & Elec. Co. v. Coleman, 
    277 U.S. 32
    , 37-38 (1928)).
    As in Romer, therefore, we must consider whether any legiti-
    them, Mandel v. Bradley, 
    432 U.S. 173
    , 176 (1977) (per curiam), “ ‘except
    when doctrinal developments indicate otherwise,’ ” Hicks v. Miranda, 
    422 U.S. 332
    , 344 (1975) (quoting Port Authority Bondholders Protective
    Committee v. Port of New York Authority, 
    387 F.2d 259
    , 263 n.3 (2d Cir.
    1967)). “[N]o more may be read into” them, however, “than was essential
    to sustain th[e] judgment. Questions which ‘merely lurk in the record’ are
    not resolved, and no resolution of them may be inferred.” Ill. State Bd. of
    Elections v. Socialist Workers Party, 
    440 U.S. 173
    , 183 (1979) (citations
    omitted).
    Whether or not the constitutionality of any ban on same-sex marriage
    was “presented and necessarily decided” in Baker, and whether or not
    Baker would govern that question in light of subsequent “doctrinal devel-
    opments,” we address no such question here. We address a wholly differ-
    ent question: whether the people of a state may by plebiscite strip a group
    of a right or benefit, constitutional or otherwise, that they had previously
    enjoyed on terms of equality with all others in the state. That question was
    not present in Baker and is squarely controlled by Romer, which postdates
    Baker by more than two decades.
    PERRY v. BROWN                           1621
    mate state interest constitutes a rational basis for Proposition
    8; otherwise, we must infer that it was enacted with only the
    constitutionally illegitimate basis of “animus toward the class
    it affects.” Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 632
    .
    2
    Before doing so, we briefly consider one other objection
    that Proponents raise to this analysis: the argument that
    because the Constitution “is not simply a one-way ratchet that
    forever binds a State to laws and policies that go beyond what
    the Fourteenth Amendment would otherwise require,” the
    State of California—“ ‘having gone beyond the requirements
    of the Federal Constitution’ ” in extending the right to marry
    to same-sex couples—“ ‘was free to return . . . to the standard
    prevailing generally throughout the United States.’ ” Propo-
    nents’ Reply Br. 76 (quoting Crawford v. Bd. of Educ., 
    458 U.S. 527
    , 542 (1982)). Proponents appear to suggest that
    unless the Fourteenth Amendment actually requires that the
    designation of ‘marriage’ be given to same-sex couples in the
    first place, there can be no constitutional infirmity in taking
    the designation away from that group of citizens, whatever the
    People’s reason for doing so.
    [9] Romer forecloses this argument. The rights that were
    repealed by Amendment 2 included protections against dis-
    crimination on the basis of sexual orientation in the private
    sphere. Those protections, like any protections against private
    discrimination, were not compelled by the Fourteenth Amend-
    ment.15 Rather, “[s]tates ha[d] chosen to counter discrimina-
    15
    Indeed, as the Court observed, not only does the Fourteenth Amend-
    ment not prohibit private discrimination; it does not even “give Congress
    a general power to prohibit discrimination in public accommodations” by
    statute. Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 628
     (emphasis added) (citing Civil Rights
    Cases, 
    109 U.S. 3
    , 25 (1883)). Congress has passed antidiscrimination
    laws regulating private conduct only under its Article I powers. See, e.g.,
    Heart of Atlanta Motel, Inc. v. United States, 
    379 U.S. 241
     (1964)
    (upholding the Civil Rights Act of 1964 under the Commerce Clause).
    1622                       PERRY v. BROWN
    tion by enacting detailed statutory schemes” prohibiting
    discrimination in employment and public accommodations,
    among other contexts, and certain Colorado jurisdictions had
    chosen to extend those protections to gays and lesbians.
    Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 628
     (emphasis added). It was these elec-
    tive protections that Amendment 2 withdrew and forbade.16
    The relevant inquiry in Romer was not whether the state of
    the law after Amendment 2 was constitutional; there was no
    doubt that the Fourteenth Amendment did not require
    antidiscrimination protections to be afforded to gays and les-
    bians. The question, instead, was whether the change in the
    law that Amendment 2 effected could be justified by some
    legitimate purpose.
    The Supreme Court’s answer was “no”—there was no
    legitimate reason to take away broad legal protections from
    gays and lesbians alone, and to inscribe that deprivation of
    equality into the state constitution, once those protections had
    already been provided. We therefore need not decide whether
    a state may decline to provide the right to marry to same-sex
    couples. To determine the validity of Proposition 8, we must
    consider only whether the change in the law that it effected—
    eliminating by constitutional amendment the right of same-
    sex couples to have the official designation and status of
    ‘marriage’ bestowed upon their relationships, while maintain-
    ing that right for opposite-sex couples—was justified by a
    legitimate reason.
    [10] This does not mean that the Constitution is a “one-
    way ratchet,” as Proponents suggest. It means only that the
    Equal Protection Clause requires the state to have a legitimate
    reason for withdrawing a right or benefit from one group but
    16
    The protections at issue in Romer were not of substantially more dis-
    tant provenance than the protection at issue here. While Aspen and Boul-
    der had enacted their ordinances somewhat earlier, Denver’s ordinance—
    which covered a far greater population—had taken effect only the year
    before Colorado voters adopted Amendment 2. Evans, 854 P.2d at 1284.
    PERRY v. BROWN                          1623
    not others, whether or not it was required to confer that right
    or benefit in the first place. Thus, when Congress, having cho-
    sen to provide food stamps to the poor in the Food Stamp Act
    of 1964, amended the Act to exclude households of unrelated
    individuals, such as “hippies” living in “hippie communes,”
    the Supreme Court held the amendment unconstitutional
    because “a bare congressional desire to harm a politically
    unpopular group cannot constitute a legitimate governmental
    interest.” U.S. Dep’t of Agric. v. Moreno, 
    413 U.S. 528
    , 534
    (1973). In both Romer and Moreno, the constitutional viola-
    tion that the Supreme Court identified was not the failure to
    confer a right or benefit in the first place; Congress was no
    more obligated to provide food stamps than Colorado was to
    enact antidiscrimination laws. Rather, what the Supreme
    Court forbade in each case was the targeted exclusion of a
    group of citizens from a right or benefit that they had enjoyed
    on equal terms with all other citizens. The constitutional
    injury that Romer and Moreno identified—and that serves as
    a basis of our decision to strike down Proposition 8—has little
    to do with the substance of the right or benefit from which a
    group is excluded, and much to do with the act of exclusion
    itself. Proponents’ reliance on Crawford v. Board of Educa-
    tion, 
    458 U.S. 527
     (1982), is therefore misplaced. In Craw-
    ford, the Court affirmed Proposition 1, a California initiative
    constitutional amendment that barred state courts from order-
    ing school busing or pupil-assignment plans except when nec-
    essary to remedy a federal constitutional violation. 
    Id.
     at 531-
    32. Like Proposition 8, Proposition 1 was adopted in response
    to a decision of the California Supreme Court under the state
    constitution, which had held that state schools were obligated
    to take “reasonably feasible steps,” including busing and
    pupil-assignment plans, “to alleviate school segregation.”
    Crawford v. Bd. of Educ., 
    551 P.2d 28
    , 45 (Cal. 1976). The
    Supreme Court “reject[ed] the contention that once a State
    chooses to do ‘more’ than the Fourteenth Amendment
    requires, it may never recede.”17 Crawford, 
    458 U.S. at 535
    .
    17
    Additionally, the Court stated that it “would not interpret the Four-
    teenth Amendment to require the people of a State to adhere to a judicial
    1624                        PERRY v. BROWN
    That conclusion was consistent with the principle that states
    should be free “to experiment” with social policy, without
    fear of being locked in to “legislation that has proved unwork-
    able or harmful when the State was under no obligation to
    adopt the legislation in the first place.” 
    Id. at 535, 539-40
    .
    Critically, however, the Court noted that Proposition 1 did
    not itself draw any classification; “[i]t simply forb[ade] state
    courts” from ordering specific remedies under state law “in
    the absence of a Fourteenth Amendment violation,” while
    maintaining the state constitution’s more robust “right to
    desegregation than exists under the Federal Constitution.” 
    Id. at 537, 542
     (emphasis added); see also 
    id. at 544
     (noting that
    other remedies remained available). Most important, the prop-
    osition’s purported benefit, “neighborhood schooling,” was
    “made available regardless of race.” 
    Id.
     There was no evi-
    dence that the “purpose of [the] repealing legislation [was] to
    construction of their State Constitution when that Constitution itself vests
    final authority in the people.” Crawford, 
    458 U.S. at 540
    . In enacting
    Proposition 8, the People did not “declare the state of the law as it existed
    when the Marriage Cases decision was rendered, but instead establishe[d]
    a new substantive state constitutional rule” that amended the charter’s text
    to supersede the previous California Declaration of Rights. Strauss, 207
    P.3d at 115. The People thus acted as Congress does when it disapproves
    of a statutory interpretation by a federal court and enacts a new statute to
    produce its preferred result. See, e.g., Religious Freedom Restoration Act
    of 1993, Pub. L. No. 103-141 (enacted in response to the Supreme Court’s
    decision in Employment Division v. Smith, 
    494 U.S. 872
     (1990)). Of
    course, Crawford did not suggest that it ends the inquiry to note that the
    Fourteenth Amendment generally allows the People to exercise their state
    constitutional right to supersede a decision of the state supreme court by
    an initiative constitutional amendment. A federal court must still deter-
    mine whether the constitutional amendment enacted by the People is oth-
    erwise valid under the Federal Constitution; sometimes laws passed
    because of disagreement with judicial decisions are not. Cf. City of Boerne
    v. Flores, 
    521 U.S. 507
     (1997) (holding the Religious Freedom Restora-
    tion Act unconstitutional in part). Proposition 1 was valid because, in
    superseding a decision of the California Supreme Court, it did not draw
    an improper classification among groups. Proposition 8 is invalid because
    it does.
    PERRY v. BROWN                            1625
    disadvantage a racial minority,” which would have made the
    proposition unconstitutional. 
    Id.
     at 539 n.21, 543-45 (citing
    Reitman v. Mulkey, 
    387 U.S. 369
     (1967)). Because Proposi-
    tion 1 did not establish any classification, and because it was
    supported by permissible policy preferences against specific
    court remedies, the Supreme Court held that it was valid. On
    the same day, by contrast, the Court struck down a similar
    Washington initiative, because it had been “drawn for racial
    purposes” in a manner that “impose[d] substantial and unique
    burdens on racial minorities” and accordingly violated the
    Fourteenth Amendment. Washington v. Seattle Sch. Dist. No.
    1, 
    458 U.S. 457
    , 470-71 (1982).
    Romer, not Crawford, controls where a privilege or protec-
    tion is withdrawn without a legitimate reason from a class of
    disfavored individuals, even if that right may not have been
    required by the Constitution in the first place. Although Colo-
    rado presented before the Supreme Court an argument regard-
    ing Crawford identical to the one that Proponents present
    here, that argument did not persuade the Court.18 Neither
    Proposition 8 nor Amendment 2 was a law of general applica-
    bility that merely curtailed state courts’ remedial powers, as
    opposed to a single group’s rights. Rather, both Proposition 8
    and Amendment 2 “carve[d] out” rights from gays and lesbi-
    ans alone. Unlike the measure in Crawford, Proposition 8 is
    a “discrimination of an unusual character” that requires “care-
    ful consideration” of its purposes and effects, whether or not
    the Fourteenth Amendment required the right to be provided
    18
    See Petitioners’ Br. 32-33, 48, Romer v. Evans, 
    517 U.S. 620
     (1996)
    (No. 94-1039) (“Crawford controls this case. Through Amendment 2, Col-
    orado has simply defined the package of civil rights available to homosex-
    uals and bisexuals under the Colorado Constitution as no larger than that
    provided by the Constitution and laws of the United States. . . . While a
    state or local government can grant more protection than that required by
    the United States Constitution, a state or local government can also rescind
    that additional protection—and prohibit its subsequent reextension—
    without committing a federal constitutional violation. [Crawford, 
    458 U.S. at 538-39
    .] Amendment 2 does nothing more.”).
    1626                       PERRY v. BROWN
    ab initio. Following Romer, we must therefore decide whether
    a legitimate interest exists that justifies the People of Califor-
    nia’s action in taking away from same-sex couples the right
    to use the official designation and enjoy the status of
    ‘marriage’—a legitimate interest that suffices to overcome the
    “inevitable inference” of animus to which Proposition 8’s dis-
    criminatory effects otherwise give rise.
    D
    We first consider four possible reasons offered by Propo-
    nents or amici to explain why Proposition 8 might have been
    enacted: (1) furthering California’s interest in childrearing
    and responsible procreation, (2) proceeding with caution
    before making significant changes to marriage, (3) protecting
    religious freedom, and (4) preventing children from being
    taught about same-sex marriage in schools. To be credited,
    these rationales “must find some footing in the realities of the
    subject addressed by the legislation.” Heller v. Doe, 
    509 U.S. 312
    , 321 (1993). They are, conversely, not to be credited if
    they “could not reasonably be conceived to be true by the
    governmental decisionmaker.” Vance v. Bradley, 
    440 U.S. 93
    ,
    111 (1979).19 Because Proposition 8 did not further any of
    these interests, we conclude that they cannot have been ratio-
    nal bases for this measure, whether or not they are legitimate
    state interests.
    1
    The primary rationale Proponents offer for Proposition 8 is
    that it advances California’s interest in responsible procre-
    ation and childrearing. Proponents’ Br. 77-93. This rationale
    appears to comprise two distinct elements. The first is that
    children are better off when raised by two biological parents
    19
    As we have noted, we need not consider whether any form of height-
    ened scrutiny is necessary or appropriate in order to reach the result we
    do. See supra note 13.
    PERRY v. BROWN                      1627
    and that society can increase the likelihood of that family
    structure by allowing only potential biological parents—one
    man and one woman—to marry. The second is that marriage
    reduces the threat of “irresponsible procreation”—that is,
    unintended pregnancies out of wedlock—by providing an
    incentive for couples engaged in potentially procreative sex-
    ual activity to form stable family units. Because same-sex
    couples are not at risk of “irresponsible procreation” as a mat-
    ter of biology, Proponents argue, there is simply no need to
    offer such couples the same incentives. Proposition 8 is not
    rationally related, however, to either of these purported inter-
    ests, whether or not the interests would be legitimate under
    other circumstances.
    [11] We need not decide whether there is any merit to the
    sociological premise of Proponents’ first argument—that fam-
    ilies headed by two biological parents are the best environ-
    ments in which to raise children—because even if Proponents
    are correct, Proposition 8 had absolutely no effect on the abil-
    ity of same-sex couples to become parents or the manner in
    which children are raised in California. As we have explained,
    Proposition 8 in no way modified the state’s laws governing
    parentage, which are distinct from its laws governing mar-
    riage. See Strauss, 207 P.3d at 61. Both before and after Prop-
    osition 8, committed opposite-sex couples (“spouses”) and
    same-sex couples (“domestic partners”) had identical rights
    with regard to forming families and raising children. See 
    Cal. Fam. Code § 297.5
    (d) (“The rights and obligations of regis-
    tered domestic partners with respect to a child of either of
    them shall be the same as those of spouses.”). Similarly, Prop-
    osition 8 did not alter the California adoption or presumed-
    parentage laws, which continue to apply equally to same-sex
    couples. Cf. Elisa B., 
    117 P.3d at 667-71
     (applying the pre-
    sumed parentage statutes to a lesbian couple); Sharon S. v.
    Super. Ct., 
    73 P.3d 554
    , 570 (Cal. 2003) (applying the adop-
    tion laws to a lesbian couple). In order to be rationally related
    to the purpose of funneling more childrearing into families led
    1628                         PERRY v. BROWN
    by two biological parents, Proposition 8 would have had to
    modify these laws in some way. It did not do so.20
    Moreover, California’s “current policies and conduct . . .
    recognize that gay individuals are fully capable of . . . respon-
    sibly caring for and raising children.” Marriage Cases, 183
    P.3d at 428. And California law actually prefers a non-
    biological parent who has a parental relationship with a child
    to a biological parent who does not; in California, the parent-
    age statutes place a premium on the “social relationship,” not
    the “biological relationship,” between a parent and a child.
    See, e.g., Susan H. v. Jack S., 
    30 Cal. App. 4th 1435
    , 1442-43
    (1994). California thus has demonstrated through its laws that
    Proponents’ first rationale cannot “reasonably be conceived to
    be true by the governmental decisionmaker,” Vance, 
    440 U.S. at 111
    . We will not credit a justification for Proposition 8 that
    is totally inconsistent with the measure’s actual effect and
    with the operation of California’s family laws both before and
    after its enactment.
    Proponents’ second argument is that there is no need to
    hold out the designation of ‘marriage’ as an encouragement
    for same-sex couples to engage in responsible procreation,
    20
    For the reasons explained above, Citizens for Equal Protection v. Bru-
    ning, 
    455 F.3d 859
     (8th Cir. 2006), is not applicable here. As our dissent-
    ing colleague states, the fact that Proposition 8 left intact California’s laws
    concerning family formation and childrearing by same-sex couples distin-
    guishes this case from Citizens. See Dissent at 1669 (“Unlike the Nebraska
    constitutional amendment, which prohibited the recognition of both mar-
    riages by same-sex couples and other same-sex relationships, Proposition
    8 left California’s existing domestic partnership laws intact. . . . Thus, it
    cannot be said that Proposition 8 ‘confer[s] the inducements of marital . . .
    benefits on opposite-sex couples . . . , but not on same-sex couples . . . .
    ’ ” (all but first alteration in original)).
    We also note that the Nebraska constitutional amendment at issue in
    Citizens did not withdraw an existing right from same-sex couples as did
    Proposition 8. Cf. Dissent at 1660 n.2. (“[W]hile the withdrawal of a right
    may not be analytically significant for rational basis review, it may still
    be factually significant.”).
    PERRY v. BROWN                          1629
    because unlike opposite-sex couples, same-sex couples pose
    no risk of procreating accidentally. Proponents contend that
    California need not extend marriage to same-sex couples
    when the State’s interest in responsible procreation would not
    be advanced by doing so, even if the interest would not be
    harmed, either. See Johnson v. Robison, 
    415 U.S. 361
    , 383
    (1974) (“When . . . the inclusion of one group promotes a
    legitimate governmental purpose, and the addition of other
    groups would not, we cannot say that the statute’s classifica-
    tion of beneficiaries and nonbeneficiaries is invidiously dis-
    criminatory.”). But Plaintiffs do not ask that marriage be
    extended to anyone. As we have by now made clear, the ques-
    tion is whether there is a legitimate governmental interest in
    withdrawing access to marriage from same-sex couples. We
    therefore need not decide whether, under Johnson, California
    would be justified in not extending the designation of ‘mar-
    riage’ to same-sex couples; that is not what Proposition 8 did.
    Johnson concerns decisions not to add to a legislative scheme
    a group that is unnecessary to the purposes of that scheme, but
    Proposition 8 subtracted a disfavored group from a scheme of
    which it already was a part.21
    Under Romer, it is no justification for taking something
    away to say that there was no need to provide it in the first
    place; instead, there must be some legitimate reason for the
    act of taking it away, a reason that overcomes the “inevitable
    inference that the disadvantage imposed is born of animosity
    toward the class of persons affected.” Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 634
    .
    In order to explain how rescinding access to the designation
    of ‘marriage’ is rationally related to the State’s interest in
    responsible procreation, Proponents would have had to argue
    that opposite-sex couples were more likely to procreate acci-
    dentally or irresponsibly when same-sex couples were
    21
    Moreover, Johnson did not involve a dignitary benefit that was with-
    drawn from one group, such as an official and meaningful state designa-
    tion that established the societal status of the members of the group; it
    concerned only a specific form of government assistance.
    1630                    PERRY v. BROWN
    allowed access to the designation of ‘marriage.’ We are aware
    of no basis on which this argument would be even conceiv-
    ably plausible. There is no rational reason to think that taking
    away the designation of ‘marriage’ from same-sex couples
    would advance the goal of encouraging California’s opposite-
    sex couples to procreate more responsibly. The Johnson argu-
    ment, to put it mildly, does not help Proponents’ cause.
    Given the realities of California law, and of human nature,
    both parts of Proponents’ primary rationale simply “find [no]
    footing in the realities of the subject addressed by the legisla-
    tion,” and thus cannot be credited as rational. Heller, 
    509 U.S. at 321
    . Whatever sense there may be in preferring biological
    parents over other couples—and we need not decide whether
    there is any—California law clearly does not recognize such
    a preference, and Proposition 8 did nothing to change that cir-
    cumstance. The same is true for Proponents’ argument that it
    is unnecessary to extend the right to use the designation of
    ‘marriage’ to couples who cannot procreate, because the pur-
    pose of the designation is to reward couples who procreate
    responsibly or to encourage couples who wish to procreate to
    marry first. Whatever merit this argument may have—and
    again, we need not decide whether it has any—the argument
    is addressed to a failure to afford the use of the designation
    of ‘marriage’ to same-sex couples in the first place; it is irrel-
    evant to a measure withdrawing from them, and only them,
    use of that designation.
    The same analysis applies to the arguments of some amici
    curiae that Proposition 8 not only promotes responsible pro-
    creation and childrearing as a general matter but promotes the
    single best family structure for such activities. See, e.g., Br.
    Amicus Curiae of High Impact Leadership Coalition, et al. 14
    (“Society has a compelling interest in preserving the institu-
    tion that best advances the social interests in responsible pro-
    creation, and that connects procreation to responsible child-
    rearing.”); Br. Amicus Curiae of Am. Coll. of Pediatricians 15
    (“[T]he State has a legitimate interest in promoting the family
    PERRY v. BROWN                             1631
    structure that has proven most likely to foster an optimal envi-
    ronment for the rearing of children.”). As discussed above,
    Proposition 8 in no way alters the state laws that govern child-
    rearing and procreation. It makes no change with respect to
    the laws regarding family structure. As before Proposition 8,
    those laws apply in the same way to same-sex couples in
    domestic partnerships and to married couples. Only the desig-
    nation of ‘marriage’ is withdrawn and only from one group of
    individuals.
    [12] We in no way mean to suggest that Proposition 8
    would be constitutional if only it had gone further—for exam-
    ple, by also repealing same-sex couples’ equal parental rights
    or their rights to share community property or enjoy hospital
    visitation privileges. Only if Proposition 8 had actually had
    any effect on childrearing or “responsible procreation” would
    it be necessary or appropriate for us to consider the legitimacy
    of Proponents’ primary rationale for the measure.22 Here,
    given all other pertinent aspects of California law, Proposition
    8 simply could not have the effect on procreation or child-
    22
    The difference between what Proposition 8 did take away—only the
    name ‘marriage’—and what it might also have taken away—any of the
    substantive “incidents of marriage” that same-sex couples still enjoy—
    influenced the underlying politics of Proposition 8 and shapes the basic
    issues in this case. The official argument in favor of Proposition 8, pub-
    lished in the Voter Information Guide, emphasized this distinction: “Prop-
    osition 8 doesn’t take away any rights or benefits of gay or lesbian
    domestic partnerships. Under California law, ‘domestic partners shall have
    the same rights, protections, and benefits’ as married spouses. (Family
    Code § 297.5.) There are NO exceptions. Proposition 8 WILL NOT
    change this.” Voter Information Guide at 56. Moreover, Strauss observed
    “that an alternative, much more sweeping initiative measure—proposing
    the addition of a new constitutional section that would have provided not
    only that ‘[o]nly marriage between one man and one woman is valid or
    recognized in California,’ but also that ‘[n]either the Legislature nor any
    court, government institution, government agency, initiative statute, local
    government, or government official shall . . . bestow statutory rights, inci-
    dents, or employee benefits of marriage on unmarried individuals’—was
    circulated for signature at the same time as Proposition 8, but did not
    obtain sufficient signatures to qualify for the ballot.” 207 P.3d at 76 n.8.
    1632                        PERRY v. BROWN
    bearing that Proponents claim it might have been intended to
    have. Accordingly, an interest in responsible procreation and
    childbearing cannot provide a rational basis for the measure.
    We add one final note. To the extent that it has been argued
    that withdrawing from same-sex couples access to the desig-
    nation of ‘marriage’—without in any way altering the sub-
    stantive laws concerning their rights regarding childrearing or
    family formation—will encourage heterosexual couples to
    enter into matrimony, or will strengthen their matrimonial
    bonds, we believe that the People of California “could not
    reasonably” have “conceived” such an argument “to be true.”
    Vance, 440 U.S. at 111. It is implausible to think that denying
    two men or two women the right to call themselves married
    could somehow bolster the stability of families headed by one
    man and one woman. While deferential, the rational-basis
    standard “is not a toothless one.” Mathews v. Lucas, 
    427 U.S. 495
    , 510 (1976). “[E]ven the standard of rationality . . . must
    find some footing in the realities of the subject addressed by
    the legislation.” Heller, 
    509 U.S. at 321
    . Here, the argument
    that withdrawing the designation of ‘marriage’ from same-sex
    couples could on its own promote the strength or stability of
    opposite-sex marital relationships lacks any such footing in
    reality.
    2
    [13] Proponents offer an alternative justification for Propo-
    sition 8: that it advances California’s interest in “proceed[ing]
    with caution” when considering changes to the definition of
    marriage. Proponents’ Br. 93. But this rationale, too, bears no
    connection to the reality of Proposition 8. The amendment
    was enacted after the State had provided same-sex couples the
    right to marry and after more than 18,000 couples had mar-
    ried (and remain married even after Proposition 8, Strauss,
    207 P.3d at 122).23
    23
    The over 18,000 couples that did marry represented more than one-
    third of all couples that had entered into registered domestic partnerships
    PERRY v. BROWN                            1633
    Perhaps what Proponents mean is that California had an
    interest in pausing at 18,000 married same-sex couples to
    evaluate whether same-sex couples should continue to be
    allowed to marry, or whether the same-sex marriages that had
    already occurred were having any adverse impact on society.
    Even if that were so, there could be no rational connection
    between the asserted purpose of “proceeding with caution”
    and the enactment of an absolute ban, unlimited in time, on
    same-sex marriage in the state constitution.24 To enact a con-
    stitutional prohibition is to adopt a fundamental barrier: it
    means that the legislative process, by which incremental poli-
    cymaking would normally proceed, is completely foreclosed.
    Cf. Williamson v. Lee Optical of Okla., Inc., 
    348 U.S. 483
    ,
    489 (1955) (observing that legislatures may rationally reform
    policy “one step at a time”). Once Proposition 8 was enacted,
    any future steps forward, however cautious, would require
    “enlisting the citizenry of [California] to amend the State
    Constitution” once again. Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 631
    .
    Had Proposition 8 imposed not a total ban but a time-
    specific moratorium on same-sex marriages, during which the
    Legislature would have been authorized to consider the ques-
    tion in detail or at the end of which the People would have
    had to vote again to renew the ban, the amendment might
    plausibly have been designed to “proceed with caution.” In
    that case, we would have had to consider whether the objec-
    tive of “proceed[ing] with caution” was a legitimate one. But
    that is not what Proposition 8 did. The amendment superseded
    the Marriage Cases and then went further, by prohibiting the
    in California at the time. See Gary J. Gates et al., The Williams Institute,
    Marriage, Registration and Dissolution by Same-Sex Couples in the U.S.
    5 (July 2008) (noting that there were 48,157 registered domestic partner-
    ships in California as of Spring 2008).
    24
    When the Eighteenth Amendment was ratified, the Nation was simi-
    larly not interested in “proceeding with caution” in reallocating grain from
    wartime rations to alcohol production. It meant, instead, to effect a perma-
    nent ban on alcohol.
    1634                       PERRY v. BROWN
    Legislature or even the People (except by constitutional
    amendment) from choosing to make the designation of ‘mar-
    riage’ available to same-sex couples in the future. Such a per-
    manent ban cannot be rationally related to an interest in
    proceeding with caution.
    [14] In any event, in light of the express purpose of Propo-
    sition 8 and the campaign to enact it, it is not credible to sug-
    gest that “proceed[ing] with caution” was the reason the
    voters adopted the measure. The purpose and effect of Propo-
    sition 8 was “to eliminate the right of same-sex couples to
    marry in California”—not to “suspend” or “study” that right.
    Voter Information Guide at 54 (Proposition 8, Official Title
    and Summary) (emphasis added).25 The voters were told that
    Proposition 8 would “overturn[ ]” the Marriage Cases “to
    RESTORE the meaning of marriage.” Id. at 56 (Argument in
    Favor of Proposition 8). The avowed purpose of Proposition
    8 was to return with haste to a time when same-sex couples
    were barred from using the official designation of ‘marriage,’
    not to study the matter further before deciding whether to
    make the designation more equally available.
    3
    [15] We briefly consider two other potential rationales for
    Proposition 8, not raised by Proponents but offered by amici
    curiae. First is the argument that Proposition 8 advanced the
    State’s interest in protecting religious liberty. See, e.g., Br.
    Amicus Curiae of the Becket Fund for Religious Liberty
    (Becket Br.) 2. There is no dispute that even before Proposi-
    tion 8, “no religion [was] required to change its religious poli-
    cies or practices with regard to same-sex couples, and no
    religious officiant [was] required to solemnize a marriage in
    25
    In California, “[b]allot summaries . . . in the ‘Voter Information
    Guide’ are recognized sources for determining the voters’ intent.” People
    v. Garrett, 
    92 Cal. App. 4th 1417
    , 1426 (2001) (citing Hodges v. Super.
    Ct., 
    980 P.2d 433
    , 438-39 (Cal. 1999)).
    PERRY v. BROWN                      1635
    contravention of his or her religious beliefs.” Marriage Cases,
    183 P.3d at 451-52; see Becket Br. 4-5 (acknowledging this
    point). Rather, the religious-liberty interest that Proposition 8
    supposedly promoted was to decrease the likelihood that reli-
    gious organizations would be penalized, under California’s
    antidiscrimination laws and other government policies con-
    cerning sexual orientation, for refusing to provide services to
    families headed by same-sex spouses. But Proposition 8 did
    nothing to affect those laws. To the extent that California’s
    antidiscrimination laws apply to various activities of religious
    organizations, their protections apply in the same way as
    before. Amicus’s argument is thus more properly read as an
    appeal to the Legislature, seeking reform of the State’s
    antidiscrimination laws to include greater accommodations
    for religious organizations. See, e.g., Becket Br. 8 n.6
    (“Unlike many other states, California has no religious
    exemptions to its statutory bans on gender, marital status, and
    sexual orientation discrimination in public accommoda-
    tions.”). This argument is in no way addressed by Proposition
    8 and could not have been the reason for Proposition 8.
    [16] Second is the argument, prominent during the cam-
    paign to pass Proposition 8, that it would “protect[ ] our chil-
    dren from being taught in public schools that ‘same-sex
    marriage’ is the same as traditional marriage.” Perry IV, 
    704 F. Supp. 2d at 930, 989-90
     (quoting the Voter Information
    Guide at 56) (emphasis omitted); see Br. Amicus Curiae for
    the Hausvater Project 13-15. Yet again, California law belies
    the premise of this justification. Both before and after Propo-
    sition 8, schools have not been required to teach anything
    about same-sex marriage. They “may . . . elect[ ] to offer
    comprehensive sexual health education”; only then might they
    be required to “teach respect for marriage and committed rela-
    tionships.” 
    Cal. Educ. Code § 51933
    (a)-(b), (b)(7). Both
    before and after Proposition 8, schools have retained control
    over the content of such lessons. And both before and after
    Proposition 8, schools and individual teachers have been pro-
    hibited from giving any instruction that discriminates on the
    1636                     PERRY v. BROWN
    basis of sexual orientation; now as before, students could not
    be taught the superiority or inferiority of either same- or
    opposite-sex marriage or other “committed relationships.”
    
    Cal. Educ. Code §§ 51500
    , 51933(b)(4). The Marriage Cases
    therefore did not weaken, and Proposition 8 did not
    strengthen, the rights of schools to control their curricula and
    of parents to control their children’s education.
    There is a limited sense in which the extension of the desig-
    nation ‘marriage’ to same-sex partnerships might alter the
    content of the lessons that schools choose to teach. Schools
    teach about the world as it is; when the world changes, les-
    sons change. A shift in the State’s marriage law may therefore
    affect the content of classroom instruction just as would the
    election of a new governor, the discovery of a new chemical
    element, or the adoption of a new law permitting no-fault
    divorce: students learn about these as empirical facts of the
    world around them. But to protest the teaching of these facts
    is little different from protesting their very existence; it is like
    opposing the election of a particular governor on the ground
    that students would learn about his holding office, or oppos-
    ing the legitimation of no-fault divorce because a teacher
    might allude to that fact if a course in societal structure were
    taught to graduating seniors. The prospect of children learning
    about the laws of the State and society’s assessment of the
    legal rights of its members does not provide an independent
    reason for stripping members of a disfavored group of those
    rights they presently enjoy.
    4
    Proposition 8’s only effect, we have explained, was to
    withdraw from gays and lesbians the right to employ the des-
    ignation of ‘marriage’ to describe their committed relation-
    ships and thus to deprive them of a societal status that affords
    dignity to those relationships. Proposition 8 could not have
    reasonably been enacted to promote childrearing by biological
    parents, to encourage responsible procreation, to proceed with
    PERRY v. BROWN                       1637
    caution in social change, to protect religious liberty, or to con-
    trol the education of schoolchildren. Simply taking away the
    designation of ‘marriage,’ while leaving in place all the sub-
    stantive rights and responsibilities of same-sex partners, did
    not do any of the things its Proponents now suggest were its
    purposes. Proposition 8 “is so far removed from these particu-
    lar justifications that we find it impossible to credit them.”
    Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 635
    . We therefore need not, and do not,
    decide whether any of these purported rationales for the law
    would be “legitimate,” 
    id. at 632
    , or would suffice to justify
    Proposition 8 if the amendment actually served to further
    them.
    E
    1
    We are left to consider why else the People of California
    might have enacted a constitutional amendment that takes
    away from gays and lesbians the right to use the designation
    of ‘marriage.’ One explanation is the desire to revert to the
    way things were prior to the Marriage Cases, when ‘mar-
    riage’ was available only to opposite-sex couples, as had been
    the case since the founding of the State and in other jurisdic-
    tions long before that. This purpose is one that Proposition 8
    actually did accomplish: it “restore[d] the traditional defini-
    tion of marriage as referring to a union between a man and a
    woman.” Strauss, 207 P.3d at 76. But tradition alone is not a
    justification for taking away a right that had already been
    granted, even though that grant was in derogation of tradition.
    In Romer, it did not matter that at common law, gays and les-
    bians were afforded no protection from discrimination in the
    private sphere; Amendment 2 could not be justified on the
    basis that it simply repealed positive law and restored the “tra-
    ditional” state of affairs. 
    517 U.S. at 627-29
    . Precisely the
    same is true here.
    Laws may be repealed and new rights taken away if they
    have had unintended consequences or if there is some con-
    1638                     PERRY v. BROWN
    ceivable affirmative good that revocation would produce, cf.
    Crawford, 
    458 U.S. at 539-40
    , but new rights may not be
    stripped away solely because they are new. Tradition is a
    legitimate consideration in policymaking, of course, but it
    cannot be an end unto itself. Cf. Williams v. Illinois, 
    399 U.S. 235
    , 239-40 (1970). “[T]he fact that the governing majority in
    a State has traditionally viewed a particular practice as
    immoral is not a sufficient reason for upholding a law prohib-
    iting the practice; neither history nor tradition could save a
    law prohibiting miscegenation from constitutional attack.”
    Lawrence v. Texas, 
    539 U.S. 558
    , 577-78 (2003); see Loving
    v. Virginia, 
    388 U.S. 1
     (1967) (noting the historical pedigree
    of bans on interracial marriage but not even considering tradi-
    tion as a possible justification for Virginia’s law). If tradition
    alone is insufficient to justify maintaining a prohibition with
    a discriminatory effect, then it is necessarily insufficient to
    justify changing the law to revert to a previous state. A prefer-
    ence for the way things were before same-sex couples were
    allowed to marry, without any identifiable good that a return
    to the past would produce, amounts to an impermissible pref-
    erence against same-sex couples themselves, as well as their
    families.
    [17] Absent any legitimate purpose for Proposition 8, we
    are left with “the inevitable inference that the disadvantage
    imposed is born of animosity toward,” or, as is more likely
    with respect to Californians who voted for the Proposition,
    mere disapproval of, “the class of persons affected.” Romer,
    
    517 U.S. at 634
    . We do not mean to suggest that Proposition
    8 is the result of ill will on the part of the voters of California.
    “Prejudice, we are beginning to understand, rises not from
    malice or hostile animus alone.” Bd. of Trustees of Univ. of
    Ala. v. Garrett, 
    531 U.S. 356
    , 374 (2001) (Kennedy, J., con-
    curring). Disapproval may also be the product of longstand-
    ing, sincerely held private beliefs. Still, while “[p]rivate
    biases may be outside the reach of the law, . . . the law cannot,
    directly or indirectly, give them effect.” Palmore v. Sidoti,
    
    466 U.S. 429
    , 433 (1984). Ultimately, the “inevitable infer-
    PERRY v. BROWN                       1639
    ence” we must draw in this circumstance is not one of ill will,
    but rather one of disapproval of gays and lesbians as a class.
    “[L]aws singling out a certain class of citizens for disfavored
    legal status or general hardships are rare.” Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 633
    . Under Romer, we must infer from Proposition 8’s effect
    on California law that the People took away from gays and
    lesbians the right to use the official designation of ‘marriage’
    —and the societal status that accompanies it—because they
    disapproved of these individuals as a class and did not wish
    them to receive the same official recognition and societal
    approval of their committed relationships that the State makes
    available to opposite-sex couples.
    [18] It will not do to say that Proposition 8 was intended
    only to disapprove of same-sex marriage, rather than to pass
    judgment on same-sex couples as people. Just as the criminal-
    ization of “homosexual conduct . . . is an invitation to subject
    homosexual persons to discrimination both in the public and
    in the private spheres,” Lawrence, 
    539 U.S. at 575
    , so too
    does the elimination of the right to use the official designation
    of ‘marriage’ for the relationships of committed same-sex
    couples send a message that gays and lesbians are of lesser
    worth as a class—that they enjoy a lesser societal status.
    Indeed, because laws affecting gays and lesbians’ rights often
    regulate individual conduct—what sexual activity people may
    undertake in the privacy of their own homes, or who is per-
    mitted to marry whom—as much as they regulate status, the
    Supreme Court has “declined to distinguish between status
    and conduct in [the] context” of sexual orientation. Christian
    Legal Soc’y v. Martinez, 
    130 S. Ct. 2971
    , 2990 (2010). By
    withdrawing the availability of the recognized designation of
    ‘marriage,’ Proposition 8 enacts nothing more or less than a
    judgment about the worth and dignity of gays and lesbians as
    a class.
    [19] Just as a “desire to harm . . . cannot constitute a legiti-
    mate governmental interest,” Moreno, 
    413 U.S. at 534
    , nei-
    ther can a more basic disapproval of a class of people. Romer,
    1640                        PERRY v. BROWN
    
    517 U.S. at 633-35
    . “The issue is whether the majority may
    use the power of the State to enforce these views on the whole
    society” through a law that abridges minority individuals’
    rights. Lawrence, 
    539 U.S. at 571
    . It may not. Without more,
    “[m]oral disapproval of [a] group, like a bare desire to harm
    the group, is an interest that is insufficient to satisfy rational
    basis review under the Equal Protection Clause.” 
    Id. at 582
    (O’Connor, J., concurring). Society does sometimes draw
    classifications that likely are rooted partially in disapproval,
    such as a law that grants educational benefits to veterans but
    denies them to conscientious objectors who engaged in alter-
    native civilian service. See Johnson, 
    415 U.S. at 362-64
    .
    Those classifications will not be invalidated so long as they
    can be justified by reference to some independent purpose
    they serve; in Johnson, they could provide an incentive for
    military service and direct assistance to those who needed the
    most help in readjusting to post-war life, see 
    id. at 376-83
    .
    Enacting a rule into law based solely on the disapproval of a
    group, however, “is a classification of persons undertaken for
    its own sake, something the Equal Protection Clause does not
    permit.” Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 635
    . Like Amendment 2, Propo-
    sition 8 is a classification of gays and lesbians undertaken for
    its own sake.
    2
    The “inference” that Proposition 8 was born of disapproval
    of gays and lesbians is heightened by evidence of the context
    in which the measure was passed.26 The district court found
    that “[t]he campaign to pass Proposition 8 relied on stereo-
    26
    A contextual evaluation is both useful and appropriate as part of the
    “careful consideration” in which courts must engage when faced with
    “[d]iscriminations of an unusual character.” Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 633
     (inter-
    nal quotation marks omitted); see Moreno, 
    413 U.S. at 533-38
    . When a
    law is enacted by ballot initiative, we look to objective indicators of the
    voters’ motivations, such as campaign materials, to shed light on the “his-
    torical context.” S. Alameda Spanish Speaking Org. v. Union City, 
    424 F.2d 291
    , 295 (9th Cir. 1970); see, e.g., Washington, 
    458 U.S. at 463
    .
    PERRY v. BROWN                      1641
    types to show that same-sex relationships are inferior to
    opposite-sex relationships.” Perry IV, 
    704 F. Supp. 2d at 990
    .
    Television and print advertisements “focused on . . . the con-
    cern that people of faith and religious groups would somehow
    be harmed by the recognition of gay marriage” and “conveyed
    a message that gay people and relationships are inferior, that
    homosexuality is undesirable and that children need to be pro-
    tected from exposure to gay people and their relationships.”
    
    Id.
     These messages were not crafted accidentally. The strate-
    gists responsible for the campaign in favor of Proposition 8
    later explained their approach: “ ‘[T]here were limits to the
    degree of tolerance Californians would afford the gay com-
    munity. They would entertain allowing gay marriage, but not
    if doing so had significant implications for the rest of soci-
    ety,’ ” such as what children would be taught in school. 
    Id. at 988
     (quoting Frank Schubert & Jeff Flint, Passing Prop 8,
    Politics, Feb. 2009, at 45-47). Nor were these messages new;
    for decades, ballot measures regarding homosexuality have
    been presented to voters in terms designed to appeal to stereo-
    types of gays and lesbians as predators, threats to children,
    and practitioners of a deviant “lifestyle.” See Br. Amicus
    Curiae of Constitutional Law Professors at 2-8. The messages
    presented here mimic those presented to Colorado voters in
    support of Amendment 2, such as, “Homosexual indoctrina-
    tion in the schools? IT’S HAPPENING IN COLORADO!”
    Colorado for Family Values, Equal Rights—Not Special
    Rights, at 2 (1992), reprinted in Robert Nagel, Playing
    Defense, 
    6 Wm. & Mary Bill Rts. J. 167
    , 193 (1997).
    [20] When directly enacted legislation “singl[es] out a cer-
    tain class of citizens for disfavored legal status,” we must “in-
    sist on knowing the relation between the classification
    adopted and the object to be attained,” so that we may ensure
    that the law exists “to further a proper legislative end” rather
    than “to make the[ ] [class] unequal to everyone else.” Romer,
    
    517 U.S. at 632-33, 635
    . Proposition 8 fails this test. Its sole
    purpose and effect is “to eliminate the right of same-sex cou-
    ples to marry in California”—to dishonor a disfavored group
    1642                    PERRY v. BROWN
    by taking away the official designation of approval of their
    committed relationships and the accompanying societal status,
    and nothing more. Voter Information Guide at 54. “It is at
    once too narrow and too broad,” for it changes the law far too
    little to have any of the effects it purportedly was intended to
    yield, yet it dramatically reduces the societal standing of gays
    and lesbians and diminishes their dignity. Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 633
    . Proposition 8 did not result from a legitimate “Kultur-
    kampf” concerning the structure of families in California,
    because it had no effect on family structure, but in order to
    strike it down, we need not go so far as to find that it was
    enacted in “a fit of spite.” 
    Id. at 636
     (Scalia, J., dissenting).
    It is enough to say that Proposition 8 operates with no appar-
    ent purpose but to impose on gays and lesbians, through the
    public law, a majority’s private disapproval of them and their
    relationships, by taking away from them the official designa-
    tion of ‘marriage,’ with its societally recognized status. Prop-
    osition 8 therefore violates the Equal Protection Clause.
    VI
    Finally, we address Proponents’ motion to vacate the dis-
    trict court’s judgment. On April 6, 2011, after resigning from
    the bench, former Chief Judge Walker disclosed that he was
    gay and that he had for the past ten years been in a relation-
    ship with another man. Proponents moved shortly thereafter
    to vacate the judgment on the basis that 
    28 U.S.C. § 455
    (b)(4)
    obligated Chief Judge Walker to recuse himself, because he
    had an “interest that could be substantially affected by the
    outcome of the proceeding,” and that 
    28 U.S.C. § 455
    (a) obli-
    gated him either to recuse himself or to disclose his potential
    conflict, because “his impartiality might reasonably be ques-
    tioned.” Chief Judge Ware, to whom this case was assigned
    after Chief Judge Walker’s retirement, denied the motion after
    receiving briefs and hearing argument.
    The district court properly held that it had jurisdiction to
    hear and deny the motion under Fed. R. Civ. P. 62.1(a), that
    PERRY v. BROWN                      1643
    the motion was timely, and that Chief Judge Walker had no
    obligation to recuse himself under either § 455(b)(4) or
    § 455(a) or to disclose any potential conflict. As Chief Judge
    Ware explained, the fact that a judge “could be affected by the
    outcome of a proceeding[,] in the same way that other mem-
    bers of the general public would be affected, is not a basis for
    either recusal or disqualification under Section 455(b)(4).”
    Perry v. Schwarzenegger, 
    790 F. Supp. 2d 1119
    , 1122 (N.D.
    Cal. 2011); see In re City of Houston, 
    745 F.2d 925
    , 929-30
    (5th Cir. 1984) (“We recognize that ‘an interest which a judge
    has in common with many others in a public matter is not suf-
    ficient to disqualify him.’ ”). Nor could it possibly be “reason-
    able to presume,” for the purposes of § 455(a), “that a judge
    is incapable of making an impartial decision about the consti-
    tutionality of a law, solely because, as a citizen, the judge
    could be affected by the proceeding.” 
    790 F. Supp. 2d at 1122
    ; see United States v. Alabama, 
    828 F.2d 1532
    , 1541-42
    (11th Cir. 1987). To hold otherwise would demonstrate a lack
    of respect for the integrity of our federal courts.
    [21] The denial of the motion to vacate was premised on
    Chief Judge Ware’s finding that Chief Judge Walker was not
    obligated to recuse himself. “We review the district court’s
    denial of a motion to vacate the judgment for an abuse of dis-
    cretion.” Jeff D. v. Kempthorne, 
    365 F.3d 844
    , 850 (9th Cir.
    2004). Our standard for abuse of discretion requires us to (1)
    “look to whether the trial court identified and applied the cor-
    rect legal rule to the relief requested”; and, if the trial court
    applied the correct legal rule, to (2) “look to whether the trial
    court’s resolution . . . resulted from a factual finding that was
    illogical, implausible, or without support in inferences that
    may be drawn from the facts in the record.” United States v.
    Hinkson, 
    585 F.3d 1247
    , 1263 (9th Cir. 2009) (en banc).
    Here, Chief Judge Ware did not incorrectly apply the law. He
    identified and applied § 455(b)(4) and § 455(a), the correct
    legal rules, as well as the relevant precedents. His application
    of the law, determining whether Chief Judge Walker was obli-
    gated to recuse himself, was discretionary. See United States
    1644                    PERRY v. BROWN
    v. Johnson, 
    610 F.3d 1138
    , 1147-48 (9th Cir. 2010). His reso-
    lution of the issue on the basis of the facts was not illogical,
    implausible, or without support in inferences that may be
    drawn from the facts in the record. Thus, we affirm Chief
    Judge Ware’s decision not to grant the motion to vacate.
    VII
    By using their initiative power to target a minority group
    and withdraw a right that it possessed, without a legitimate
    reason for doing so, the People of California violated the
    Equal Protection Clause. We hold Proposition 8 to be uncon-
    stitutional on this ground. We do not doubt the importance of
    the more general questions presented to us concerning the
    rights of same-sex couples to marry, nor do we doubt that
    these questions will likely be resolved in other states, and for
    the nation as a whole, by other courts. For now, it suffices to
    conclude that the People of California may not, consistent
    with the Federal Constitution, add to their state constitution a
    provision that has no more practical effect than to strip gays
    and lesbians of their right to use the official designation that
    the State and society give to committed relationships, thereby
    adversely affecting the status and dignity of the members of
    a disfavored class. The judgment of the district court is
    AFFIRMED.27
    27
    The stay pending appeal issued by this court on August 16, 2010
    remains in effect pending issuance of the mandate.
    PERRY v. BROWN                     1645
    N.R. SMITH, Circuit Judge, concurring in part and dissenting
    in part:
    I agree with the majority’s analysis and decisions in parts
    III and VI of its opinion, determining that (1) the Proponents
    have standing to bring this appeal; and (2) the Motion to
    Vacate the Judgment should be denied. Because I do not
    agree with the majority’s analysis of other topics regarding
    the constitutionality of Proposition 8, I have chosen to write
    separately. Ultimately, I am not convinced that Proposition 8
    is not rationally related to a legitimate governmental interest.
    I must therefore respectfully dissent.
    Before addressing the issues now presented before our
    panel, I want to emphasize a distinguishing point in my analy-
    sis from what may be anticipated by the reader. Similar to the
    California Supreme Court in its prior opinion concerning
    Proposition 8, our panel was not tasked with determining
    whether this constitutional amendment “is wise or sound as a
    matter of policy or whether we, as individuals, believe it
    should be a part of the California Constitution.” Strauss v.
    Horton, 
    207 P.3d 48
    , 59 (Cal. 2009). Our personal views
    regarding the political and sociological debate on marriage
    equality are irrelevant to our task. Instead, we are only asked
    to consider the constitutional validity of Proposition 8 under
    the federal Constitution. The California Supreme Court has
    already interpreted and applied “the principles and rules
    embodied in the California Constitution” to Proposition 8 and
    found it valid. Strauss, 
    207 P.3d 48
    .
    I.
    Proponents and their supporting amici (hereinafter Propo-
    nents) argue that the United States Supreme Court’s summary
    dismissal in Baker v. Nelson, 
    409 U.S. 810
     (1972) (mem.),
    “mandates reversal of the district court’s ruling.” According
    to Proponents, the claims raised here are the same as those
    rejected in Baker, and the claims are therefore foreclosed by
    1646                     PERRY v. BROWN
    that decision. The majority dispenses with Baker in a foot-
    note. However, other federal courts have indicated that Baker,
    if it is not controlling, at least stands for exercising “restraint”
    when it comes to addressing due process and equal protection
    challenges against laws prohibiting marriage by same-sex
    couples. Citizens for Equal Protection v. Bruning, 
    455 F.3d 859
    , 870 (8th Cir. 2006); see also Wilson v. Ake, 
    354 F. Supp. 2d 1298
    , 1305 (M.D. Fla. 2005) (“Baker v. Nelson is binding
    precedent upon this Court . . . .”). But see In re Kandu, 
    315 B.R. 123
    , 138 (Bankr. W.D. Wash. 2004) (concluding that
    “Baker is not binding precedent on the issues presented”
    because the case centered on federal Defense of Marriage Act
    and because “doctrinal developments” indicated Baker was no
    longer binding). Because Baker is binding United States
    Supreme Court precedent and may foreclose Plaintiffs’
    claims, one must follow it or distinguish it.
    A.
    In Baker v. Nelson, two men were denied a marriage
    license by a Minnesota county clerk. 
    191 N.W.2d 185
    , 185
    (Minn. 1971). Because they were denied the license, the two
    men filed suit asking that the court force the clerk to grant the
    license. 
    Id.
     In Minnesota Statutes c. 517, the Minnesota state
    legislature had codified that the state “d[id] not authorize mar-
    riage between persons of the same sex. . . .” Id. at 186. On
    appeal, the Minnesota Supreme Court addressed several
    issues, including whether the Minnesota statutes prohibiting
    marriage by same-sex couples denied the petitioners “the
    equal protection of the laws” as guaranteed by the Fourteenth
    Amendment. Id. The Minnesota Supreme Court held that
    “[t]he equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment
    . . . is not offended by the state’s classification of persons
    authorized to marry.” Id. at 187. On appeal to the United
    States Supreme Court, the Court summarily dismissed the
    appeal “for want of a substantial federal question.” Baker v.
    Nelson, 
    409 U.S. 810
    .
    PERRY v. BROWN                        1647
    Though not stated in the summary dismissal in Baker, the
    Supreme Court decision has long standing precedent support-
    ing it. Throughout our nation’s history, the States have had
    “the absolute right to prescribe the conditions upon which the
    marriage relation between its own citizens shall be credited
    . . . .” Pennoyer v. Neff, 
    95 U.S. 714
    , 734-35 (1878), reaf-
    firmed in Sosna v. Iowa, 
    419 U.S. 393
    , 404 (1975).
    Marriage, as creating the most important relation in
    life, as having more to do with the morals and civili-
    zation of a people than any other institution, has
    always been subject to the control of the legislature.
    That body prescribes the age at which parties may
    contract to marry, the procedure or form essential to
    constitute marriage, the duties and obligations it
    creates, its effects upon the property rights of both,
    present and prospective, and the acts which may
    constitute grounds for its dissolution.
    Maynard v. Hill, 
    125 U.S. 190
    , 205 (1888).
    As Justice Stewart opined in his concurrence in Zablocki v.
    Redhail, a State
    may in many circumstances absolutely prohibit
    [marriage]. Surely, for example, a State may legiti-
    mately say that no one can marry his or her sibling,
    that no one can marry who is not at least 14 years
    old, that no one can marry without first passing an
    examination for venereal disease, or that no one can
    marry who has a living husband or wife.
    
    434 U.S. 374
    , 392 (1978) (Stewart, J., concurring).
    The summary dismissal of an appeal for want of a substan-
    tial federal question is a decision on the merits. Hicks v.
    Miranda, 
    422 U.S. 332
    , 344 (1975). “[U]nless and until the
    Supreme Court should instruct otherwise, inferior federal
    1648                    PERRY v. BROWN
    courts had best adhere to the view that if the Court has
    branded a question as unsubstantial, it remains so except
    when doctrinal developments indicate otherwise . . . .” 
    Id.
    (internal quotation marks omitted). “[L]ower courts are bound
    by summary decisions by [the Supreme] Court until such time
    as the Court informs (them) that (they) are not.” 
    Id. at 344-45
    (internal quotation marks omitted). “Summary . . . dismissals
    for want of a substantial federal question . . . reject the spe-
    cific challenges presented in the statement of jurisdiction and
    do leave undisturbed the judgment appealed from. They do
    prevent lower courts from coming to opposite conclusions on
    the precise issues presented and necessarily decided by those
    actions.” Mandel v. Bradley, 
    432 U.S. 173
    , 176 (1977) (per
    curiam). Thus, “[a] summary disposition affirms only the
    judgment of the court below, and no more may be read into
    [the] action than was essential to sustain that judgment.” Ill.
    State Bd. of Elections v. Socialist Workers Party, 
    440 U.S. 173
    , 182-83 (1979) (citation omitted). “Questions which
    ‘merely lurk in the record’ are not resolved, and no resolution
    of them may be inferred.” 
    Id. at 183
     (citation omitted).
    The jurisdictional statements presented to the United States
    Supreme Court in Baker v. Nelson were as follows:
    1. Whether appellee’s refusal to sanctify appel-
    lants’ marriage deprives appellants of their liberty to
    marry and of their property without due process of
    law under the Fourteenth Amendment.
    2. Whether appellee’s refusal, pursuant to Minne-
    sota marriage statutes, to sanctify appellants’ mar-
    riage because both are of the male sex violates their
    rights under the equal protection clause of the Four-
    teenth Amendment.
    3. Whether appellee’s refusal to sanctify appel-
    lants’ marriage deprives appellants of their right to
    PERRY v. BROWN                      1649
    privacy under the Ninth and Fourteenth Amend-
    ments.
    See In re Kandu, 
    315 B.R. at 137
    .
    B.
    Here, we must address whether the question before us
    involves “the precise issues presented and necessarily decided
    by” Baker v. Nelson, such that the Supreme Court’s summary
    dismissal would have precedential effect here. Alternatively,
    the question before us could be one that “merely lurk[ed] in
    the record” of Baker, and the present case would not be
    resolved by the Supreme Court’s summary dismissal.
    In this case, the following issues were presented for review:
    1. Whether [Proponents] have standing to appeal
    the district court’s judgment.
    2. Whether Proposition 8 violates the Due Process
    Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to the United
    States Constitution.
    3. Whether Proposition 8 violates the Equal Pro-
    tection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to the
    United States Constitution.
    Plaintiff-Intervenor City and County of San Francisco (here-
    inafter San Francisco) presented the following additional
    issue for review:
    1. Whether Proposition 8, a constitutional amend-
    ment adopted after a plebiscite campaign that played
    on fears and prejudices about lesbians and gay men,
    violates the Equal Protection Clause of the federal
    Constitution where its effect is to remove the hon-
    ored title “marriage” but not the incidents of mar-
    1650                        PERRY v. BROWN
    riage from same-sex couples, and its purpose is to
    remove the taint that its supporters believed the
    inclusion of lesbian and gay couples worked on the
    institution of marriage.
    The equal protection question raised in this case seems to
    be distinguishable from the precise issues presented and nec-
    essarily decided in Baker, especially when the equal protec-
    tion issue is framed as San Francisco advocates.1 The equal
    protection issue decided in Baker rested on whether Minneso-
    ta’s “refusal, pursuant to Minnesota marriage statutes, to sanc-
    tify appellants’ marriage . . . violates their rights under the
    equal protection clause . . . .” In re Kandu, 
    315 B.R. at 137
    .
    Here, San Francisco presents the issue of whether Proposition
    8’s effect of “remov[ing] the honored title ‘marriage’ but not
    the incident of marriage from same-sex couples” violates
    equal protection. This Proposition 8 issue may have “merely
    lurk[ed] in the record” of Baker. Unlike Minnesota, California
    granted same-sex couples rights to both the designation and
    the incidents of marriage, before withdrawing the right of
    access to the designation through Proposition 8. Therefore,
    1
    Whether prohibiting marriage by same-sex couples violates due pro-
    cess was an issue presented and decided in Baker v. Nelson. In this case,
    the district court determined that “plaintiffs seek to exercise their funda-
    mental right to marry under the Due Process Clause,” Perry v. Schwar-
    zenegger, 
    704 F. Supp. 2d 921
    , 993 (N.D. Cal. 2010), and that Proposition
    8 violated the Due Process Clause, because it denied Plaintiffs this funda-
    mental right and did not withstand strict scrutiny. 
    Id. at 994-95
    . But in
    Baker, the Minnesota Supreme Court determined that prohibiting marriage
    by same-sex couples did not offend the Due Process Clause. 191 N.W.3d
    at 186-87. Because the United States Supreme Court “branded [that] ques-
    tion as unsubstantial” in its summary dismissal, the due process issue “re-
    mains so except when doctrinal developments indicate otherwise.” Hicks
    v. Miranda, 
    422 U.S. at 344
     (internal quotation marks omitted). The
    United States Supreme Court cases following Baker do not suggest any
    such doctrinal developments have occurred. See, e.g., Lawrence v. Texas,
    
    539 U.S. 558
    , 578 (2003) (“[This case] does not involve whether the gov-
    ernment must give formal recognition to any relationship that homosexual
    persons seek to enter.” (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    PERRY v. BROWN                      1651
    the constitutionality of withdrawing from same-sex couples
    the right of access to the designation of marriage does not
    seem to be among the “specific challenges” raised in Baker.
    If so, though the precedential effect of Baker v. Nelson is not
    challenged by this decision, such precedent is distinguishable
    from the decision of the district court here.
    II.
    In deciding this case, one should be mindful that generally
    state governance over marriage is not challenged easily. How-
    ever, while “marriage is a social relation subject to the State’s
    police power,” this does not mean that the State’s “powers to
    regulate marriage are unlimited notwithstanding the com-
    mands of the Fourteenth Amendment.” Loving v. Virginia,
    
    388 U.S. 1
    , 7 (1967). A marriage regulation “containing racial
    classifications,” such as the one at issue in Loving, is subject
    to “the very heavy burden of justification which the Four-
    teenth Amendment has traditionally required of state statutes
    drawn according to race.” 
    Id. at 9
    . However, not “every state
    regulation which relates in any way to the incidents of or pre-
    requisites for marriage must be subjected to rigorous scruti-
    ny.” Zablocki, 
    434 U.S. at 386
     (majority opinion). Proposition
    8 does not involve such a suspect classification and therefore
    should not be analyzed under any heightened scrutiny, but we
    must still ask “whether there is any rational foundation for the
    discrimination[ ] . . . .” See Loving, 
    388 U.S. at 9
    .
    A.
    The Plaintiffs, San Francisco, and their supporting amici
    (hereinafter Plaintiffs) challenge Proposition 8 under the
    Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. How-
    ever, because Proposition 8 is “a classification neither involv-
    ing fundamental rights nor proceeding along suspect lines,”
    Heller v. Doe, 
    509 U.S. 312
    , 319 (1993), I do not address the
    application of strict scrutiny review to Proposition 8. Under
    strict scrutiny review, the government would need to establish
    1652                    PERRY v. BROWN
    that the classification is necessary to achieve a compelling
    governmental interest, and there must not be a less onerous
    available alternative. The United States Supreme Court has
    not recognized that the fundamental right to marry includes a
    fundamental right to gay marriage. See Lawrence, 
    539 U.S. at 578
    . Gays and lesbians are not a suspect or quasi-suspect
    class. High Tech Gays v. Def. Indus. Sec. Clearance Office,
    
    895 F.2d 563
    , 573 (9th Cir. 1990).
    I also do not address intermediate scrutiny because
    Supreme Court precedent thus far has never held that sexual
    orientation is a “quasi-suspect classification.” See City of Cle-
    burne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., 
    473 U.S. 432
    , 441-42 (1985).
    Under that standard of review, generally applied in illegiti-
    macy and gender cases, the government would need to estab-
    lish that the classification is substantially related to an
    important governmental interest. See 
    id. at 441
    .
    Thus, Proposition 8 is subject to rational basis review rather
    than to any heightened scrutiny. See 
    id. at 440-42
    .
    B.
    “The Fourteenth Amendment’s promise that no person
    shall be denied the equal protection of the laws must coexist
    with the practical necessity that most legislation classifies for
    one purpose or another, with resulting disadvantage to various
    groups or persons.” Romer v. Evans, 
    517 U.S. 620
    , 631
    (1996). Thus, when assessing the constitutionality of most
    government measures, we use rational basis review in an
    attempt “to reconcile the principle with the reality.” 
    Id.
     Under
    rational basis review, “we will uphold the legislative classifi-
    cation so long as it bears a rational relation to some legitimate
    end.” 
    Id.
    In equal protection analysis, rational basis review “is not a
    license for courts to judge the wisdom, fairness, or logic of
    legislative choices.” Heller, 
    509 U.S. at 319
     (internal quota-
    PERRY v. BROWN                       1653
    tion marks omitted). A classification “neither involving fun-
    damental rights nor proceeding along suspect lines is
    accorded a strong presumption of validity.” 
    Id.
     “Such a classi-
    fication cannot run afoul of the Equal Protection Clause if
    there is a rational relationship between the disparity of treat-
    ment and some legitimate governmental purpose.” 
    Id. at 320
    .
    The government is not required to “actually articulate at any
    time the purpose or rationale supporting its classification”;
    rather, a classification “must be upheld against equal protec-
    tion challenge if there is any reasonably conceivable state of
    facts that could provide a rational basis for the classification.”
    
    Id.
     (internal quotation marks omitted).
    Additionally, the government “has no obligation to provide
    evidence to sustain the rationality of a statutory classifica-
    tion.” 
    Id.
     The measure at issue “is not subject to courtroom
    factfinding and may be based on rational speculation unsup-
    ported by evidence or empirical data.” 
    Id.
     (internal quotation
    marks omitted). “[T]he burden is on the one attacking the leg-
    islative arrangement to negative every conceivable basis
    which might support it . . . .” 
    Id.
     (internal quotation marks
    omitted). Further, a legislature’s generalizations may pass
    rational basis review “even when there is an imperfect fit
    between means and ends.” 
    Id. at 321
    . In sum, the measure
    need only have “arguable” assumptions underlying its “plau-
    sible rationales” to survive constitutional challenge. 
    Id. at 333
    .
    However, “even the standard of rationality . . . must find
    some footing in the realities of the subject addressed by the
    legislation.” 
    Id. at 321
    . Also, some interests are not legitimate
    governmental interests. E.g., Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 634
     (stating
    that “animosity toward the class of persons affected” is not a
    legitimate governmental interest); Cleburne, 
    473 U.S. at 448
    (stating that “mere negative attitudes, or fear” are not legiti-
    mate governmental interests); U.S. Dep’t of Agric. v. Moreno,
    
    413 U.S. 528
    , 534 (1973) (stating that a “bare . . . desire to
    1654                    PERRY v. BROWN
    harm a politically unpopular group” is not a legitimate gov-
    ernmental interest).
    As a general rule, states may use their police power to regu-
    late the “morals” of their population. See, e.g., Berman v. Par-
    ker, 
    348 U.S. 26
    , 32 (1954). In his dissent in Lawrence, 
    539 U.S. at 589-91
     (Scalia, J., dissenting), Justice Scalia argued
    that “[c]ountless judicial decisions and legislative enactments
    have relied on the ancient proposition that a governing major-
    ity’s belief that certain sexual behavior is ‘immoral and unac-
    ceptable’ constitutes a rational basis for regulation.” 
    Id. at 589
    . He then suggested that the Supreme Court has relied on
    morality as the basis for its decision making and states,
    “[s]tate laws against bigamy, same-sex marriage, adult incest,
    prostitution, masturbation, adultery, fornication, bestiality,
    and obscenity are likewise sustainable only in light of valida-
    tion of laws based on moral choices.” 
    Id. at 590
    .
    However, Justice O’Connor articulated a different perspec-
    tive in determining whether moral disapproval may serve as
    a rational basis for equal protection. She outlined that moral
    disapproval is not a legitimate state interest to justify, by
    itself, a statute that bans homosexual conduct. She stated that
    “[m]oral disapproval of this group, like a bare desire to harm
    the group, is an interest that is insufficient to satisfy rational
    basis review under the Equal Protection Clause.” 
    Id. at 582
    (O’Connor, J., concurring). She continued: “Indeed, we have
    never held that moral disapproval, without any other asserted
    state interest, is a sufficient rationale under the Equal Protec-
    tion Clause to justify a law that discriminates among groups
    of persons.” 
    Id.
     The Lawrence majority opinion seems to have
    implicitly agreed with Justice O’Connor, when it stated that
    a court’s “obligation is to define the liberty of all, not to man-
    date its own moral code.” 
    Id. at 559
     (majority opinion) (inter-
    nal quotation mark omitted).
    Therefore, such interests (e.g., animus, negative attitudes,
    fear, a bare desire to harm, and moral disapproval) alone will
    PERRY v. BROWN                      1655
    not support the constitutionality of a measure, because the
    Equal Protection Clause does not permit a “status-based
    enactment divorced from any factual context from which [the
    courts] could discern a relationship to legitimate state inter-
    ests,” or a “classification of persons undertaken for its own
    sake . . . .” Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 635
    .
    III.
    The majority concludes that “Romer governs our analysis
    notwithstanding the differences between Amendment 2 and
    Proposition 8,” because of the similarities between the mea-
    sures at issue in Romer and in the present case. However, the
    differences between Amendment 2 and Proposition 8 indicate
    that Romer does not directly control our analysis of the consti-
    tutionality of Proposition 8.
    Before comparing Amendment 2 to Proposition 8, I want
    to attempt to clarify the extent of the Plaintiffs’ interest
    asserted here. One must understand the unique manner in
    which California defines this interest. Because the California
    Supreme Court defined and clarified that interest in its Strauss
    v. Horton opinion, I quote liberally from it.
    Proposition 8 “properly must be understood as having a
    considerably narrower scope and more limited effect” than
    what might be the case in other states. Strauss, 207 P.3d at 61.
    “Proposition 8 does not entirely repeal or abrogate the aspect
    of a same-sex couple’s state constitutional right to . . . choose
    one’s life partner and enter with that person into a committed,
    officially recognized, and protected family relationship that
    enjoys all of the constitutionally based incidents of marriage.”
    Id. (internal quotation marks omitted).
    Nor does Proposition 8 fundamentally alter the
    meaning and substance of state constitutional equal
    protection principles . . . . Instead, the measure
    carves out a narrow and limited exception to these
    1656                     PERRY v. BROWN
    state constitutional rights, reserving the official des-
    ignation of the term “marriage” for the union of
    opposite-sex couples as a matter of state constitu-
    tional law, but leaving undisturbed all of the other
    extremely significant substantive aspects of a same-
    sex couple’s state constitutional right to establish an
    officially recognized and protected family relation-
    ship and the guarantee of equal protection of the
    laws.
    Id.
    Further, the California Supreme Court continued, “as a
    qualitative matter, the act of limiting access to the designation
    of marriage to opposite-sex couples [through Proposition 8]
    does not have a substantial or, indeed, even a minimal effect
    on the governmental plan or framework of California that
    existed prior to the amendment.” Id. at 62.
    However, the California Supreme Court was also quick to
    point out that this differentiation did not diminish or minimize
    “the significance of the official designation of ‘marriage,’ ”
    which they characterized as “a vital factor” in their prior deci-
    sion holding that failing to provide access to this designation
    to same-sex couples “impinged upon the privacy and due pro-
    cess rights of same-sex couples and violated those couples’
    right to the equal protection of the laws guaranteed by the
    California Constitution.” Id. at 59, 61.
    Therefore, “Proposition 8 reasonably must be interpreted in
    a limited fashion as eliminating only the right of same-sex
    couples to equal access to the designation of marriage, and as
    not otherwise affecting the constitutional right of those cou-
    ples to establish an officially recognized family relationship.”
    Id. at 76.
    Accordingly, although Proposition 8 eliminates the
    ability of same-sex couples to enter into an official
    PERRY v. BROWN                       1657
    relationship designated “marriage,” in all other
    respects those couples continue to possess, under the
    state constitutional privacy and due process clauses,
    “the core set of basic substantive legal rights and
    attributes traditionally associated with marriage,”
    including, “most fundamentally, the opportunity of
    an individual to establish—with the person with
    whom the individual has chose to share his or her
    life—an officially recognized and protected family
    possessing mutual rights and responsibilities and
    entitled to the same respect and dignity accorded a
    union traditionally designated as marriage.” Like
    opposite-sex couples, same-sex couples enjoy this
    protection not as a matter of legislative grace, but of
    constitutional right.
    Id. at 77 (citation omitted).
    A.
    In Romer, Colorado voters adopted Amendment 2 to the
    State Constitution, which “prohibits all legislative, executive,
    or judicial action at any level of state or local government
    designed to protect . . . gays and lesbians.’ ” 
    517 U.S. at 624
    .
    Amendment 2 was passed in response to municipal ordi-
    nances enacted in various Colorado cities that protected “per-
    sons discriminated against by reason of their sexual
    orientation.” 
    Id.
     The Supreme Court examined Amendment 2
    under rational basis review, where “if a law neither burdens
    a fundamental right nor targets a suspect class, we will uphold
    the legislative classification so long as it bears a rational rela-
    tion to some legitimate end.” 
    Id. at 631
    . The Supreme Court
    held that Amendment 2 failed rational basis review for two
    reasons. 
    Id. at 632
    . “First, the amendment has the peculiar
    property of imposing a broad and undifferentiated disability
    on a single named group, an exceptional and . . . invalid form
    of legislation.” 
    Id.
     “Second, its sheer breadth is so discontinu-
    ous with the reasons offered for it that the amendment seems
    1658                     PERRY v. BROWN
    inexplicable by anything but animus toward the class if
    affects; it lacks a rational relationship to legitimate state inter-
    ests.” 
    Id.
    B.
    There are several ways to distinguish Romer from the pres-
    ent case. First, in Romer, the Supreme Court stated that “[t]he
    change Amendment 2 works in the legal status of gays and
    lesbians in the private sphere is far reaching, both on its own
    terms and when considered in light of the structure and opera-
    tion of modern anti-discrimination laws.” 
    Id. at 627
    . Here,
    “Proposition 8 reasonably must be interpreted in a limited
    fashion as eliminating only the right of same-sex couples to
    equal access to the designation of marriage, and as not other-
    wise affecting the constitutional right of those couples to
    establish an officially recognized family relationship.”
    Strauss, 207 P.3d at 76. Thus, Romer is inapposite, because
    Proposition 8 eliminates the right of access to the designation
    of marriage from same-sex couples, rather than working a far
    reaching change in their legal status.
    Second, Amendment 2’s “sheer breadth is so discontinuous
    with the reasons offered for it that the amendment seems inex-
    plicable by anything but animus toward the class it affects.”
    Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 632
    . Again, Proposition 8 “carves out a
    narrow and limited exception to [the] state constitutional
    rights” of privacy and due process. Strauss, 207 P.3d at 61.
    Proposition 8 therefore lacks the “sheer breadth” that
    prompted the Supreme Court to raise the inference of animus
    in Romer.
    The effect of animus is also unclear. In Romer, the
    Supreme Court stated that “laws of the kind now before us
    raise the inevitable inference that the disadvantage imposed is
    born of animosity towards the class of persons affected.” 
    517 U.S. at 634
    . The Supreme Court indicated that Amendment 2
    was constitutionally invalid, because its only purpose was ani-
    PERRY v. BROWN                     1659
    mus; Amendment 2 was not “directed to any identifiable
    legitimate purpose or discrete objective.” 
    Id. at 635
    . In short,
    Romer was a case where the only basis for the measure at
    issue was animus. However, in a case where the measure at
    issue was prompted both by animus and by some independent
    legitimate purpose, the measure may still be constitutionally
    valid. The Supreme Court has stated that while “negative atti-
    tudes,” “fear” or other biases “may often accompany irratio-
    nal (and therefore unconstitutional) discrimination, their
    presence alone does not a constitutional violation make.” Bd.
    of Trustees of Univ. of Ala. v. Garrett, 
    531 U.S. 356
    , 367
    (2001) (discussing Cleburne, 
    473 U.S. at 448
    ). If “animus” is
    one such bias, its presence alone may not make Proposition
    8 invalid if the measure also rationally relates to a legitimate
    governmental interest.
    Finally, gays and lesbians were burdened by Amendment 2,
    because it “operate[d] to repeal and forbid all laws or policies
    providing specific protection for gays or lesbians from dis-
    crimination by every level of Colorado government.” Romer,
    
    517 U.S. at 629
    . In contrast, “although Proposition 8 elimi-
    nates the ability of same-sex couples to enter into an official
    relationship designated ‘marriage,’ in all other respects those
    couples continue to possess, under the state constitutional pri-
    vacy and due process clauses, the core set of basic substantive
    legal rights and attributes traditionally associated with mar-
    riage . . . .” Strauss, 207 P.3d at 77 (internal quotation marks
    omitted). Put otherwise, Proposition 8 does not burden gays
    and lesbians to the same extent Amendment 2 burdened gays
    and lesbians in Colorado.
    C.
    Proponents argue that the fact that Proposition 8 withdrew
    from same-sex couples the existing right of access to the des-
    ignation of marriage should be significant in our constitu-
    tional analysis. However, Supreme Court equal protection
    cases involving challenges to measures withdrawing an exist-
    1660                         PERRY v. BROWN
    ing right do not indicate that the withdrawal should affect our
    analysis. Instead, it seems that the court has upheld legislation
    that withdraws, rather than reserves, some legal right. E.g.,
    U.S. R.R. Ret. Bd. v. Fritz, 
    449 U.S. 166
    , 176-77 (1980)
    (applying “traditional” principles of rational basis review to
    Congress’s determination “that some of those who in the past
    received full windfall benefits would not continue to do so”);
    City of New Orleans v. Dukes, 
    427 U.S. 297
    , 303-05 (1976)
    (per curiam) (concluding that city’s elimination of rights of
    some pushcart food vendors, but not others, was “not consti-
    tutionally impermissible”). In fact, in its decision in Romer,
    the Supreme Court does not base its decision on this conten-
    tion. Rather, it mentioned withdrawing specific legal protec-
    tions from gays and lesbians only in the context of referring
    to the irrational targeting of that group when compared to the
    sweeping change Amendment 2 created in the law.2 Romer,
    
    517 U.S. at 627
    .
    D.
    The above differences between Amendment 2 and Proposi-
    tion 8 indicate that Romer does not directly control here. In
    Romer, the Supreme Court found that animus alone was the
    purpose behind Amendment 2. Here, the majority backs into
    its inference of animus, first determining that all other bases
    2
    However, while the withdrawal of a right may not be analytically sig-
    nificant for rational basis review, it may still be factually significant. For
    example, the fact that Proposition 8 involves the withdrawal of an existing
    right and not the extension of a previously reserved right suggests that
    Johnson v. Robison, 
    415 U.S. 361
     (1974), is inapposite to the present case.
    In Johnson, the Supreme Court declared that “[w]hen . . . the inclusion of
    one group promotes a legitimate governmental purpose, and the addition
    of other groups would not, we cannot say that the statute’s classification
    of beneficiaries and nonbeneficiaries is invidiously discriminatory.” 
    Id. at 383
    . As the majority argues, the rule from Johnson appears to be inappli-
    cable here, because Proposition 8 involves the withdrawal from same-sex
    couples of the existing right to access the designation of marriage, and not
    the addition of same-sex couples to the group previously reserved the
    right.
    PERRY v. BROWN                     1661
    for Proposition 8 are constitutionally invalid. Assuming ani-
    mus or moral disapproval were one of the purposes of Propo-
    sition 8, the measure would still survive rational basis review
    if there were also a valid rational basis behind Proposition 8.
    Only if there were no other basis would Proposition 8 fail
    rational basis review. Thus, our task is to determine whether
    Proposition 8 rationally relates to any independent legitimate
    governmental interest.
    IV.
    In our case, Proponents argue that Proposition 8, defining
    marriage as the union of one man and one woman, is ratio-
    nally related to a legitimate governmental interest for several
    reasons. Some of those reasons have already been discussed
    in the majority opinion and need no further discussion here.
    However, two of those reasons deserve more discussion,
    because they have been credited by other courts: (1) a respon-
    sible procreation theory, justifying the inducement of marital
    recognition only for opposite-sex couples, because it “steers
    procreation into marriage” because opposite-sex couples are
    the only couples who can procreate children accidentally or
    irresponsibly; and (2) an optimal parenting theory, justifying
    the inducement of marital recognition only for opposite-sex
    couples, because the family structure of two committed bio-
    logical parents—one man and one woman—is the optimal
    partnership for raising children. See, e.g., Citizens for Equal
    Protection, 
    455 F.3d at 867-68
    .
    A.
    Proponents argue that Proposition 8, defining marriage as
    the union of one man and one woman, preserves the funda-
    mental and historical purposes of marriage. They argue that,
    if the definition of marriage between a man and a woman is
    changed, it would fundamentally redefine the term from its
    original and historical procreative purpose. This shift in pur-
    pose would weaken society’s perception of the importance of
    1662                        PERRY v. BROWN
    entering into marriage to have children, which would increase
    the likelihood that couples would choose to cohabitate rather
    than to get married. They also argue that irresponsible procre-
    ation, by accident or willfully in a cohabitation relationship,
    will result in less stable circumstances for children and that
    same-sex couples do not present this threat of irresponsible
    procreation. They argue that, in the case of unintended preg-
    nancies, the question is not whether the child will be raised by
    two opposite-sex parents, but rather whether it will be raised,
    on the one hand by two parents, or on the other hand by its
    mother alone (often with the assistance of the state). “Proposi-
    tion 8 seeks to channel potentially procreative conduct into
    relationships where that conduct is likely to further, rather
    than harm, society’s interest in responsible procreation and
    childrearing.”
    Proponents also argue the “optimal parenting” rationale
    serves as a rational basis for Proposition 8. The optimal par-
    enting rationale posits that Proposition 8 promotes the optimal
    setting for the responsible raising and care of children—by
    their biological parents in a stable marriage relationship. Pro-
    ponents offer many judicial decisions and secondary authori-
    ties supporting both rationales.
    In sum, Proponents argue that Proposition 8 is rationally
    related to legitimate governmental interests.
    B.
    The first requirement of rational basis review is that there
    must be some conceivable legitimate governmental interest
    for the measure at issue.3
    3
    This requirement is easily met, because “[v]irtually any goal that is not
    forbidden by the Constitution will be deemed sufficient to meet the ratio-
    nal basis test.” Erwin Chemerinsky, Constitutional Law: Principles and
    Policies 698 (4th ed. 2011).
    PERRY v. BROWN                          1663
    1.
    The California Supreme Court indicated that responsible
    procreation is a legitimate governmental interest:
    Whether or not the state’s interest in encouraging
    responsible procreation properly can be viewed as a
    reasonably conceivable justification for the statutory
    limitation of marriage to a man and a woman for
    purposes of the rational basis equal protection stan-
    dard, this interest clearly does not provide an appro-
    priate basis for defining or limiting the scope of the
    constitutional right to marry. . . . [A]lthough the state
    undeniably has a legitimate interest in promoting
    “responsible procreation,” that interest cannot be
    viewed as a valid basis for defining or limiting the
    class of persons who may claim the protection of the
    fundamental constitutional right to marry.
    In re Marriage Cases, 
    183 P.3d 384
    , 432 (Cal. 2008) (empha-
    sis added), superseded by constitutional amendment as stated
    in Strauss, 
    207 P.3d 48
    .
    2.
    With regard to the optimal parenting rationale, the Califor-
    nia Supreme Court stated the following about “the state’s
    interest in fostering a favorable environment for the procre-
    ation and raising of children”:
    [A]lthough promoting and facilitating a stable envi-
    ronment for the procreation and raising of children
    is unquestionably one of the vitally important pur-
    poses underlying the institution of marriage and the
    constitutional right to marry, past cases make clear
    that this right is not confined to, or restrictively
    defined by, that purpose alone. As noted above, our
    past cases have recognized that the right to marry is
    1664                         PERRY v. BROWN
    the right to enter into a relationship that is the center
    of the personal affections that ennoble and enrich
    human life—a relationship that is at once the most
    socially productive and individually fulfilling rela-
    tionship that one can enjoy in the course of a life-
    time. The personal enrichment afforded by the right
    to marry may be obtained by a couple whether or not
    they choose to have children, and the right to marry
    never has been limited to those who plan or desire to
    have children. . . . [T]he state constitutional right to
    marry . . . cannot properly be defined by or limited
    to the state’s interest in fostering a favorable envi-
    ronment for the procreation and raising of children.
    Marriage Cases, 183 P.3d at 432 (citations and internal quo-
    tation marks omitted). Thus, the California Supreme Court
    discussed “the state’s interest in fostering a favorable environ-
    ment for the protection and raising of children” without using
    the “legitimate interest” and “for the purposes of the rational
    basis equal protection standard” language used to discuss “re-
    sponsible procreation.” See id.
    a.
    Plaintiffs argue that the optimal parenting rationale cannot
    be a legitimate governmental interest because same-sex cou-
    ples in domestic partnerships have all the substantive parent-
    ing rights opposite-sex couples in marriages enjoy.
    Additionally, California family law does not give any official
    preferences to opposite-sex parents.4 Proposition 8 did not
    4
    For example, “[t]he rights and obligations of registered domestic part-
    ners with respect to a child of either of them shall be the same as those
    of spouses.” 
    Cal. Fam. Code § 297.5
    (d). Also, “[i]t is the policy of this
    state that all persons engaged in providing care and services to foster chil-
    dren . . . shall not be subjected to discrimination or harassment on the
    basis of their clients’ or their own actual or perceived . . . sexual orienta-
    tion . . . .” 
    Cal. Welf. & Inst. Code § 16013
    (a). Further, “[t]he parent and
    PERRY v. BROWN                             1665
    change this factual situation, because it “leav[es] undisturbed
    . . . a same-sex couple’s state constitutional right to establish
    an officially recognized and protected family relationship and
    the guarantee of equal protection of the laws.” Strauss, 207
    P.3d at 61. “This state’s current policies and conduct regard-
    ing homosexuality . . . recognize that gay individuals are fully
    capable of entering into the kind of loving and enduring com-
    mitted relationships that may serve as the foundation of a
    family and of responsibly caring for and raising children.”
    Marriage Cases, 183 P.3d at 428.
    The parties argue about whether this analysis subjects Prop-
    osition 8 to heightened scrutiny rather than rational basis
    review. In my view, while Plaintiffs may give a correct
    accounting of California law, it does not necessarily follow
    that the optimal parenting rationale is an illegitimate govern-
    mental interest, because it contradicts existing laws on parent-
    ing and the family. For example, a posited reason offered by
    one lawmaking body after being rejected by another lawmak-
    ing body can “provide[ ] a conceivable basis” for a measure.
    FCC v. Beach Comm’ns, Inc., 
    508 U.S. 307
    , 318 (1993). In
    Beach Communications, the Supreme Court accepted a pos-
    ited reason for a federal agency regulation, even though Con-
    gress had previously rejected that purpose and the regulation
    presented a conflict in the statutory scheme.5 
    Id.
     Thus, even
    child relationship extends equally to every child and to every parent,
    regardless of the marital status of the parents.” 
    Cal. Fam. Code § 7602
    .
    This legal structure is reinforced by the equal status of gays and lesbians
    in other areas of California’s laws, such as in antidiscrimination protec-
    tions regarding business establishments. E.g., 
    Cal. Civ. Code § 51
    (b) (“All
    persons within the jurisdiction of this state are free and equal, and no mat-
    ter what their . . . sexual orientation are entitled to the full and equal
    accommodations, advantages, facilities, privileges, or services in all busi-
    ness establishments of every kind whatsoever.”).
    5
    See also City of Dallas v. Stanglin, 
    490 U.S. 19
    , 26-28 (1989) (stating
    that a city could rationally impose an age and time restriction on dance
    halls, even if it had not imposed similar restrictions on other premises
    where teenagers and adults congregated together; arguments focusing on
    the inconsistency between the classification and the “interests and objec-
    tives” of the city “misapprehend[ed] the nature of rational-basis scrutiny”).
    1666                    PERRY v. BROWN
    if California’s legislature previously rejected the optimal par-
    enting rationale in its parenting laws (and Proposition 8 is
    inconsistent with its statutory scheme), that does not prevent
    the people of California from adopting Proposition 8 under
    that rationale.
    b.
    In Heller, the Supreme Court stated that “legislative choice
    is not subject to courtroom factfinding and may be based on
    rational speculation unsupported by evidence or empirical
    data.” 
    509 U.S. at 320
     (citations omitted). However, the
    Supreme Court went on to state that “even the standard of
    rationality as we so often have defined it must find some foot-
    ing in the realities of the subject addressed by the legislation.”
    
    Id. at 321
    .
    Under rational basis review, the challenger has the burden
    to “negative every conceivable basis which might support”
    the measure. 
    Id. at 320
    . In light of this burden, Plaintiffs have
    offered many secondary authorities to support their argument
    that the optimal parenting rationale cannot be a legitimate
    governmental interest. “Against [a] background of more than
    100 peer-reviewed studies, the State of California could not
    reasonably accept as a true—or even debatable—statement of
    fact Proponents’ view that only opposite-sex couples can
    create an ‘ideal’ childrearing environment.” Thus, “[i]t is not
    an end that the State rationally could adopt as its own and
    therefore cannot sustain Proposition 8.”
    Although Proponents were not required to put on any evi-
    dence under rational basis review, they also produced evi-
    dence. They argue that their evidence shows that married
    biological parents are the optimal parenting structure. Further,
    they argue “Plaintiffs fail to cite to a single study comparing
    outcomes for the children of married biological parents and
    those of same-sex parents. Thus, Plaintiffs have failed to
    undermine, let alone remove ‘from debate,’ the studies show-
    PERRY v. BROWN                            1667
    ing that married biological parents provide the best structure
    for raising children.”
    After review, both sides offer evidence in support of their
    views on whether the optimal parenting rationale is a legiti-
    mate governmental interest. Both sides also offer evidence to
    undermine the evidence presented by their opponents. How-
    ever, the standard only requires that the optimal parenting
    rationale be based on “rational speculation” about married
    biological parents being the best for children. Heller, 
    509 U.S. at 320
    . Considering “the question is at least debatable,” 
    id. at 326
     (internal quotation marks omitted), the optimal parenting
    rationale could conceivably be a legitimate governmental inter-
    est.6
    C.
    Having a conceivable legitimate governmental interest is,
    alone, not sufficient for rational basis review. To survive
    rational basis review, a measure must also have a rational
    relationship to the posited legitimate governmental interest. In
    determining whether there is a rational relationship, one
    should bear in mind “the nature of rational-basis scrutiny,
    which is the most relaxed and tolerant form of judicial scru-
    6
    In Lawrence v. Texas, 
    539 U.S. 558
    , Justice O’Connor relied on the
    Fourteenth Amendment’s Equal Protection Clause to invalidate a state law
    criminalizing homosexual sodomy. In her concurring opinion, she stated:
    That this law as applied to private, consensual conduct is uncon-
    stitutional under the Equal Protection Clause does not mean that
    other laws distinguishing between heterosexuals and homosexu-
    als would similarly fail under rational basis review. Texas cannot
    assert any legitimate state interest here, such as national security
    or preserving the traditional institution of marriage. Unlike the
    moral disapproval of same-sex relations—the asserted state inter-
    est in this case—other reasons exist to promote the institution of
    marriage beyond mere moral disapproval of an excluded group.
    
    Id. at 585
     (O’Connor, J., concurring).
    1668                         PERRY v. BROWN
    tiny under the Equal Protection Clause.”
    7 Dallas, 490
     U.S. at
    26.
    1.
    The Eighth Circuit credited the responsible procreation and
    optimal parenting rationales in Citizens for Equal Protection,
    where Nebraska had enacted a constitutional amendment pro-
    hibiting recognition of marriages by same-sex couples and
    other official same-sex relationships:
    The State argues that the many laws defining mar-
    riage as the union of one man and one woman and
    extending a variety of benefits to married couples are
    rationally related to the government interest in
    “steering procreation into marriage.” By affording
    legal recognition and a basket of rights and benefits
    to married heterosexual couples, such laws “encour-
    age procreation to take place within the socially rec-
    ognized unit that is best situated for raising
    children.” . . . The argument is based in part on the
    traditional notion that two committed heterosexuals
    are the optimal partnership for raising children,
    which modern-day homosexual parents understand-
    ably decry. But it is also based on a “responsible
    procreation” theory that justifies conferring the
    inducements of marital recognition and benefits on
    opposite-sex couples, who can otherwise produce
    children by accident, but not on same-sex couples,
    who cannot. Whatever our personal views regarding
    this political and sociological debate, we cannot con-
    clude that the State’s justification “lacks a rational
    relationship to legitimate state interests.”
    7
    As explained above, this requirement is not a high bar. Indeed, “the
    classification at issue need not be correlated in fact, even in relation to an
    assumed purpose for which there need not be any evidence.” Robert C.
    Farrell, The Two Versions of Rational-Basis Review and Same-Sex Rela-
    tionships, 
    86 Wash. L. Rev. 281
    , 290 (2011).
    PERRY v. BROWN                      1669
    
    455 F.3d at 867-68
     (citations omitted).
    The factual context in California is distinguishable from the
    one the Eighth Circuit faced in Nebraska. Unlike the
    Nebraska constitutional amendment, which prohibited the rec-
    ognition of both marriages by same-sex couples and other
    same-sex relationships, Proposition 8 left California’s existing
    domestic partnership laws intact. In California, same-sex cou-
    ples in domestic partnerships still enjoy the same substantive
    rights and benefits as opposite-sex couples in marriages.
    Thus, it cannot be said that Proposition 8 “confer[s] the
    inducements of marital . . . benefits on opposite-sex couples
    . . . , but not on same-sex couples . . . .” See 
    id. at 867
    . How-
    ever, this distinction may not be dispositive, because the
    Eighth Circuit was considering both the substantive legal ben-
    efits as well as the designation of marriage.
    2.
    That leaves the question of whether withdrawing from
    same-sex couples the right to access the designation of mar-
    riage, alone, rationally relates to the responsible procreation
    and optimal parenting rationales.
    a.
    Regarding the responsible procreation rationale, Plaintiffs
    argue that Proponents suggest no reason to believe prohibiting
    same-sex couples from entering relationships designated
    “marriage” will make it more likely that opposite-sex couples
    in California will marry. Put differently, Plaintiffs argue that,
    because Proposition 8 does not bestow an honor on opposite-
    sex couples but instead withdraws an honor from same-sex
    couples, the responsible procreation rationale could be cred-
    ited only if it is rational to believe that opposite-sex couples
    will be less likely to raise children in a marital family if the
    stature of marriage is also available to same-sex couples. Fur-
    ther, Plaintiffs argue that Proponents’ failure to describe how
    1670                    PERRY v. BROWN
    Proposition 8 rationally relates to the responsible procreation
    rationale indicates that the rationale lacks the required “foot-
    ing in the realities of the subject addressed by the legislation.”
    Heller, 
    509 U.S. at 321
    .
    In response, Proponents argue that, “[b]ecause only sexual
    relationships between men and woman can produce children,
    such relationships have the potential to further—or harm—
    this interest in a way that other types of relationships do not.”
    Thus, “it follows that the commonsense distinction that our
    law has always drawn between opposite-sex couples, on the
    one hand, and all other types of relationships—including
    same-sex couples—on the other hand, plainly bears a rational
    relationship to the government interest in steering procreation
    into marriage.”
    However, Proposition 8 is not a “distinction that [Califor-
    nia] law has always drawn,” because it “establishes a new
    substantive state constitutional rule that became effective
    once Proposition 8 was approved by the voters.” Strauss, 207
    P.3d at 115. Also,
    [n]one of the past cases discussing the right to marry
    —and identifying this right as one of the fundamen-
    tal elements of personal autonomy and liberty pro-
    tected by our Constitution—contains any suggestion
    that the constitutional right to marry is possessed
    only by individuals who are at risk of producing
    children accidentally, or implies that this constitu-
    tional right is not equally important for and guaran-
    teed to responsible individuals who can be counted
    upon to take appropriate precautions in planning for
    parenthood.
    Marriage Cases, 183 P.3d at 432. In this particular context,
    the fact that Proposition 8 established a new rule, instead of
    continuing a “distinction that [California] law has always
    drawn,” weakens Proponents’ argument that Proposition 8
    PERRY v. BROWN                     1671
    “plainly bears a rational relationship” to the responsible pro-
    creation rationale.
    b.
    Regarding the optimal parenting rationale, Plaintiffs argue
    that, because Proposition 8 does not change California’s sub-
    stantive laws governing childraising, procreation, or the fam-
    ily structure, Proposition 8 cannot be rationally related to the
    optimal parenting rationale. To channel more childrearing into
    families led by married biological parents, they argue that
    Proposition 8 would have had to change those laws somehow.
    Rather, Proposition 8 only singles out gays and lesbians, as a
    group, as inferior.
    Proponents contend that this argument subjects Proposition
    8 to heightened scrutiny review, and that the standard for
    rational basis review does not require the classification be
    substantially related to an important governmental interest.
    Instead, for rational basis review, the classification must only
    (1) serve some conceivable governmental interest; (2) have a
    plausible reason for the enactment; (3) remain debatable; and
    (4) not be totally arbitrary. Their argument continues that, in
    California’s unique context, Proposition 8 only deals with the
    designation of the term “marriage” but leaves undisturbed all
    of the other significant substantive aspects of recognized and
    protected family relationships. Proponents’ theory only
    increases the likelihood that children are born and raised in a
    family structure of biological parents by encouraging such
    parents to marry; the designation of marriage for only that
    union would make it more likely that opposite-sex couples
    will want to enter into marriage and then subsequently raise
    their own biological offspring, rather than implying that any
    other union could not be good parents. Proponents claim this
    interest does not depend on any judgment about the relative
    parenting capabilities of opposite-sex and same-sex couples;
    it only confirms the instinctive, commonsense belief that mar-
    ried biological parents provide the optimal environment for
    1672                         PERRY v. BROWN
    raising children. Lastly, they argue there can be no require-
    ment of narrow tailoring where there would be a perfect fit
    with the governmental interest and the law. If the state denied
    same-sex couples significant benefits under the law, the law
    would be more likely to fail equal protection by denying
    important government rights, thus increasing the burden of
    the test.
    3.
    “[C]ourts are compelled under rational-basis review to
    accept a legislature’s generalizations even when there is an
    imperfect fit between means and ends.” Heller, 
    509 U.S. at 321
    . Here, the people of California might have believed that
    withdrawing from same-sex couples the right to access the
    designation of marriage would, arguably, further the interests
    in promoting responsible procreation and optimal parenting.
    “The assumptions underlying these rationales may be errone-
    ous, but the very fact that they are ‘arguable’ is sufficient, on
    rational-basis review, to ‘immuniz[e]’ the congressional
    choice from constitutional challenge.” Beach Commc’ns, 
    508 U.S. at 320
     (alteration in original).
    Plaintiffs argue that Proposition 8 could only advance the
    offered rationales through encouraging opposite-sex couples
    to marry, who otherwise would not marry because they disap-
    prove of same-sex couples having the right of access to the
    designation of marriage and the stature that comes with the
    designation. Therefore, Proposition 8 impermissibly gives
    effect to those “private biases.” See Palmore v. Sidoti, 
    466 U.S. 429
    , 433 (1984). However, Supreme Court precedent
    does not suggest that a measure is invalid under rational basis
    review simply because the means by which its purpose is
    accomplished rest on such biases.8 Rather, precedent indicates
    8
    In Palmore, the Supreme Court stated that “[p]rivate biases may be
    outside the reach of the law, but the law cannot, directly or indirectly, give
    them effect.” 
    466 U.S. at 433
    . Even if Palmore indicates that giving effect
    PERRY v. BROWN                           1673
    that such biases invalidate a measure if they are the only con-
    ceivable ends for the measure. See, e.g., Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 535
    . Again, in determining whether there is a rational rela-
    tionship, one must bear in mind that rational basis review “is
    the most relaxed and tolerant form of judicial scrutiny under
    the Equal Protection Clause.” Dallas, 
    490 U.S. at 26
    . Thus, I
    cannot conclude that Proposition 8 is “wholly irrelevant” to
    any legitimate governmental interests. Heller, 
    509 U.S. at 324
    (internal quotation marks omitted).
    V.
    Given the presumption of validity accorded Proposition 8
    for rational basis review, I am not convinced that Proposition
    8 lacks a rational relationship to legitimate state interests. Pre-
    cedent evidences extreme judicial restraint in applying ratio-
    nal basis review to equal protection cases.
    Only by faithful adherence to this guiding principle
    of judicial review of legislation is it possible to pre-
    serve to the legislative branch its rightful indepen-
    dence and its ability to function. . . . [R]estraints on
    judicial review have added force where the legisla-
    ture must necessarily engage in a process of line-
    drawing. Defining the class of persons subject . . .
    inevitably requires that some persons who have an
    to private biases through means is illegitimate, it is a case where “ac-
    knowledged racial prejudice [was] invoked to justify [a] racial classifica-
    tion[ ].” 
    Id.
     Thus, the classification came under strict scrutiny. 
    Id. at 432-33
    ; see also City of Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co., 
    488 U.S. 469
    , 520
    (1989) (Scalia, J., concurring in the judgment) (“The benign purpose of
    compensating for social disadvantages . . . can no more be pursued by the
    illegitimate means of racial discrimination than can other assertedly
    benign purposes we have repeatedly rejected.”).
    While the Supreme Court quoted Palmore in Cleburne, it did so in the
    context of rejecting “mere negative attitudes” or “fear” as ends. 
    473 U.S. at 448
    .
    1674                    PERRY v. BROWN
    almost equally strong claim to favored treatment be
    placed on different sides of the line, and the fact that
    the line might have been drawn differently at some
    points is a matter for legislative, rather than judicial,
    consideration.
    Beach Commc’ns, 
    508 U.S. at 315-16
     (alteration, citations,
    and internal quotation marks omitted). Thus, the judiciary
    faces a conspicuous limit on our judicial role in applying
    equal protection to legislative enactments, because
    [t]he Court has held that the Fourteenth Amendment
    permits States a wide scope of discretion in enacting
    laws which affect some groups of citizens differently
    than others. The constitutional safeguard is offended
    only if classification rests on grounds wholly irrele-
    vant to the achievement of the State’s objective.
    State legislatures are presumed to have acted within
    their constitutional power despite the fact that, in
    practice, their laws result in some inequality. A stat-
    utory discrimination will not be set aside if any state
    of facts reasonably may be conceived to justify it.
    McGowan v. Maryland, 
    366 U.S. 420
    , 425-26 (1961). A law
    must be upheld unless the government’s judgment “is ‘clearly
    wrong, a display of arbitrary power, [or] not an exercise of
    judgment.’ ” Mathews v. DeCastro, 
    429 U.S. 181
    , 185 (1976).
    Applying rational basis review in these circumstances also
    requires such restraint. As the Eighth Circuit said, in Citizens
    for Equal Protection, 
    455 F.3d at
    870:
    In the nearly one hundred and fifty years since the
    Fourteenth Amendment was adopted, to our knowl-
    edge no Justice of the Supreme Court has suggested
    that a state statute or constitutional provision codify-
    ing the traditional definition of marriage violates the
    Equal Protection Clause or any other provision of the
    PERRY v. BROWN                        1675
    United States Constitution. Indeed, in Baker v. Nel-
    son, . . . when faced with a Fourteenth Amendment
    challenge to a decision by the Supreme Court of
    Minnesota denying a marriage license to a same-sex
    couple, the United States Supreme Court dismissed
    “for want of a substantial federal question.” There is
    good reason for this restraint.
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 10-16696

Filed Date: 2/7/2012

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 10/14/2015

Authorities (83)

united-states-of-america-john-f-knight-jr-individually-and-on-behalf , 828 F.2d 1532 ( 1987 )

Port Authority Bondholders Protective Committee, Henry W. ... , 387 F.2d 259 ( 1967 )

darcy-ting-individually-and-on-behalf-of-all-others-similarly-situated , 319 F.3d 1126 ( 2003 )

In Re City of Houston , 745 F.2d 925 ( 1984 )

Citizens for Equal Protection v. Jon C. Bruning, Attorney ... , 455 F.3d 859 ( 2006 )

Perry v. Schwarzenegger , 591 F.3d 1147 ( 2010 )

John Marshall v. Grant Sawyer, as Governor of the State of ... , 365 F.2d 105 ( 1966 )

Southern Alameda Spanish Speaking Organization (Also Known ... , 424 F.2d 291 ( 1970 )

Michael Caruso v. Yamhill County, an Oregon Municipal ... , 422 F.3d 848 ( 2005 )

Frances Duchek and Arthur Duchek v. Rudolph Jacobi and Elfi ... , 646 F.2d 415 ( 1981 )

Perry v. Schwarzenegger , 602 F. Supp. 3d 976 ( 2010 )

United States v. Johnson , 610 F.3d 1138 ( 2010 )

Perry v. Proposition 8 Official Proponents , 587 F.3d 947 ( 2009 )

high-tech-gays-timothy-dooling-and-all-others-similarly-situated-joel , 895 F.2d 563 ( 1990 )

Costa v. Superior Court , 39 Cal. Rptr. 3d 470 ( 2006 )

Sharon S. v. Superior Court , 2 Cal. Rptr. 3d 699 ( 2003 )

People v. Kelly , 47 Cal. 4th 1008 ( 2010 )

Crawford v. Board of Education , 17 Cal. 3d 280 ( 1976 )

jeff-d-john-m-paula-e-dusty-r-minors-individually-and-on-behalf-of , 365 F.3d 844 ( 2004 )

los-angeles-county-bar-association-a-non-profit-mutual-benefit-corporation , 979 F.2d 697 ( 1992 )

View All Authorities »