Mark French v. Blair Jones , 876 F.3d 1228 ( 2017 )


Menu:
  •                 FOR PUBLICATION
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT
    MARK FRENCH,                            No. 15-35990
    Plaintiff-Appellant,
    D.C. No.
    v.                     4:14-cv-00057-
    SEH
    BLAIR JONES, in his official capacity
    as Chair of Montana’s Judicial
    Standards Commission; MIKE                OPINION
    MENAHAN, in his official capacity as
    a member of Montana’s Judicial
    Standards Commission; VICTOR
    VALGENTI, in his official capacity as
    a member of Montana’s Judicial
    Standards Commission; JOHN
    MURPHY, in his official capacity as a
    member of Montana’s Judicial
    Standards Commission; BRIANNE
    DUGAN, in her official capacity as a
    member of Montana’s Judicial
    Standards Commission,
    Defendants-Appellees.
    Appeal from the United States District Court
    for the District of Montana
    Sam E. Haddon, Senior District Judge, Presiding
    Argued and Submitted June 16, 2017
    Seattle, Washington
    2                         FRENCH V. JONES
    Filed December 7, 2017
    Before: Jay S. Bybee and Milan D. Smith, Jr., Circuit
    Judges, and Jennifer A. Dorsey,* District Judge.
    Opinion by Judge Bybee
    SUMMARY**
    Civil Rights
    The panel affirmed the district court’s summary judgment
    in an action brought by Mark French, a Montana judicial
    candidate, who alleged that Montana’s campaign-speech rule,
    which prohibits judicial candidates from seeking, accepting,
    or using political endorsements in their election campaigns,
    violated his First Amendment rights.
    The panel held that Montana has compelling interests in
    an impartial and independent judiciary and that Rule
    4.1(A)(7) of the Montana Code of Judicial Conduct was
    narrowly tailored to those interests. The panel held that Rule
    4.1(A)(7) struck an appropriate balance between a candidate’s
    speech and Montana’s interest in an independent and
    impartial judiciary. The panel held that French’s arguments
    to the contrary were foreclosed by the Supreme Court’s
    *
    The Honorable Jennifer A. Dorsey, United States District Judge for
    the District of Nevada, sitting by designation.
    **
    This summary constitutes no part of the opinion of the court. It has
    been prepared by court staff for the convenience of the reader.
    FRENCH V. JONES                        3
    decision in Williams-Yulee v. Florida Bar, 
    135 S. Ct. 1656
    (2015), and this Circuit’s decision in Wolfson v. Concannon,
    
    811 F.3d 1176
     (9th Cir. 2016) (en banc).
    The panel rejected French’s arguments that Rule
    4.1(A)(7) was fatally underinclusive. The panel held that:
    (1) an endorsement from a political party threatened the
    public perception of judicial independence to a greater degree
    than an endorsement from an interest group; (2) Montana
    could reasonably conclude that political endorsements were
    more suggestive of a quid-pro-quo exchange than donations;
    and (3) it made sense for Montana to prohibit the solicitation
    and use of endorsements during a judicial candidate’s
    campaign and to limit those endorsement to political office
    holders and entities. The panel further held that the seeking
    and using of political endorsements was distinct from
    announcing one’s views on certain issues.
    The panel rejected French’s argument that Rule 4.1(A)(7)
    was overinclusive because Montana does not allow the
    candidates’ campaign committees to seek and use political
    endorsements. The panel held that Montana had reasonably
    determined that both candidates and their committees posed
    a threat to its judiciary when they sought, accepted, or used
    political endorsements in their campaigns.
    4                   FRENCH V. JONES
    COUNSEL
    Matthew G. Monforton (argued), Monforton Law Offices
    PLLC, Bozeman, Montana, for Plaintiff-Appellant.
    Dale Schowengerdt (argued), Solicitor General; Mark W.
    Mattioli, Assistant Attorney General; Montana Department of
    Justice, Helena, Montana; for Defendants-Appellees.
    Elizabeth Arias (argued), Corey Collins, and Eugene Lim,
    Law Students; Eugene Volokh (argued), Supervising
    Attorney; Scott & Cyan Banister First Amendment Clinic,
    UCLA School of Law, Los Angeles, California; for Amicus
    Curiae Center for Competitive Politics.
    Igor V. Timofeyev, Adam Weiss, and Danielle R.A. Susanj,
    Paul Hastings LLP, Washington, D.C.; Karl J. Sandstrom and
    David J. Lazarus, Perkins Coie LLP, Washington, D.C.; Keith
    R. Fisher, National Center for State Courts, Arlington,
    Virginia; for Amicus Curiae Conference of Chief Justices.
    FRENCH V. JONES                         5
    OPINION
    BYBEE, Circuit Judge:
    Montanans select their judges through nonpartisan
    popular elections. In an effort to keep those elections
    nonpartisan, Montana has restricted judicial-campaign
    speech. One of those restrictions is before us—a rule that
    prohibits candidates from seeking, accepting, or using
    political endorsements in their campaigns. Mark French, a
    judicial candidate who wishes to seek and use such
    endorsements, claims that Montana’s rule violates his First
    Amendment rights. Montana argues that the rule is narrowly
    tailored to ensuring the impartiality and independence of
    Montana’s judiciary. The district court upheld the statute,
    and we agree. In light of the Supreme Court’s decision in
    Williams-Yulee v. Florida Bar, 
    135 S. Ct. 1656
     (2015), and
    our decision in Wolfson v. Concannon, 
    811 F.3d 1176
     (9th
    Cir. 2016) (en banc), we affirm the judgment.
    I
    Montana has declared that “[a]n independent, fair, and
    impartial judiciary is indispensable to [its] system of justice.”
    Mont. Code of Judicial Conduct, Preamble (2009). Although
    that statement of principle must be universally acknowledged,
    American jurisdictions have chosen different means to secure
    it. See The Federalist No. 78, at 465 (C. Rossiter ed. 1961)
    (A. Hamilton) (arguing for the appointment of judges). Since
    1935, Montana has decided to select its judges through
    nonpartisan popular elections. See 
    Mont. Code Ann. § 13-14
    -
    111. Recognizing that mixing politics with judging could
    lead to injustice, Montana has prohibited all judges and
    candidates for judicial office from “engag[ing] in political or
    6                          FRENCH V. JONES
    campaign activity that is inconsistent with the independence,
    integrity, or impartiality of the judiciary.” Mont. Code of
    Judicial Conduct Canon 4. That broad prohibition applies to
    such activities as holding an office in or making speeches on
    behalf of a political organization, publicly endorsing political
    candidates, publicly identifying oneself as a political
    candidate, and otherwise using the names of political parties
    in judicial campaigns.1 
    Id.
     Rule 4.1; 
    Mont. Code Ann. § 13
    -
    10-602(2).
    Only one restriction is at issue here. Rule 4.1(A)(7) of the
    Montana Code of Judicial Conduct provides: “[A] judge or
    judicial candidate shall not . . . seek, accept, or use
    endorsements from a political organization, or partisan or
    independent non-judicial office-holder or candidate . . . .”2
    Mont. Code of Judicial Conduct Rule 4.1(A)(7). The Code
    defines a “political organization” as “a political party or other
    group sponsored by or affiliated with a political party or
    candidate, the principal purpose of which is to further the
    election or appointment of candidates for political office.” 
    Id.
    Terminology. If a judge or judicial candidate violates this
    endorsement provision, the Montana Judicial Standards
    Commission “shall recommend . . . the censure, suspension,
    1
    Montana is not alone in restricting the political speech of judges and
    judicial candidates. As of 2012, “[t]hirty-nine states have judicial
    elections, and nearly all have enacted laws to treat judicial elections
    differently from political elections.” Sanders Cty. Republican Cent.
    Comm. v. Bullock, 
    698 F.3d 741
    , 750 (9th Cir. 2012) (Schroeder, J.,
    dissenting).
    2
    Montana does not, however, prohibit political parties or
    organizations from endorsing judicial candidates. See Sanders Cty.,
    698 F.3d at 749.
    FRENCH V. JONES                        7
    removal, or disability retirement of the judicial officer.”
    
    Mont. Code Ann. § 3-1-1106
    (3).
    In 2014, Mark French ran as a candidate for justice of the
    peace in Sanders County. The Sanders County Republican
    Central Committee endorsed French’s candidacy, and two
    prominent Republican officeholders were willing to consider
    doing so if French had asked. Afraid of violating Rule
    4.1(A)(7), French refrained from seeking or using these
    endorsements in his campaign. He ultimately lost the
    election, but intends to run again in 2018. Although French
    would like to seek and use political endorsements during the
    next election cycle, he understands that he cannot do so as
    long as Rule 4.1(A)(7) remains in place.
    French filed this action claiming that Rule 4.1(A)(7)
    violates his First Amendment rights and asking that the court
    enjoin its enforcement. The district court rejected French’s
    argument and entered summary judgment against him. We
    review that decision de novo. See McIndoe v. Huntington
    Ingalls Inc., 
    817 F.3d 1170
    , 1173 (9th Cir. 2016).
    II
    The First Amendment, applicable to the states through the
    Fourteenth Amendment, prohibits the government from
    “abridging the freedom of speech.” U.S. Const. amend. I;
    Stromberg v. California, 
    283 U.S. 359
    , 368 (1931)
    (incorporating “the right of free speech” into the Due Process
    Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment). Content-based
    restrictions on judicial-campaign speech are subject to strict
    scrutiny under the First Amendment. See Republican Party
    of Minn. v. White (“White I”), 
    536 U.S. 765
    , 774 (2002)
    (assuming strict scrutiny applies); Wolfson, 811 F.3d at 1180
    8                      FRENCH V. JONES
    (holding that strict scrutiny applies). To survive strict
    scrutiny, the government must show that “the restriction
    ‘furthers a compelling interest and is narrowly tailored to
    achieve that interest.’” Citizens United v. Fed. Election
    Comm’n, 
    558 U.S. 310
    , 340 (2010) (citation omitted). “‘[I]t
    is the rare case’ in which a State demonstrates that a speech
    restriction is narrowly tailored to serve a compelling interest
    . . . . But those cases do arise.” Williams-Yulee, 
    135 S. Ct. at
    1665–66 (citations omitted); see also Adarand Constructors,
    Inc. v. Pena, 
    515 U.S. 200
    , 237 (1995) (“[W]e wish to dispel
    the notion that strict scrutiny is ‘strict in theory, but fatal in
    fact.’” (citation omitted)).
    Before determining whether Rule 4.1(A)(7) is narrowly
    tailored to achieve a compelling state interest, we must
    examine the development of First Amendment law in this
    murky area of judicial-campaign speech. The Supreme Court
    has addressed restrictions similar to Rule 4.1(A)(7) on two
    occasions—in White I and Williams-Yulee—providing mixed
    guidance on the proper analytical framework and producing
    some tension among the lower courts. We have addressed
    that tension in our en banc decision in Wolfson. Despite the
    confusion, we discern a clear shift in favor of state
    regulation—a shift that renders many of French’s and his
    amicus curiae’s arguments no longer persuasive.
    A
    1
    We begin our survey with White I. The Supreme Court
    there reviewed a Minnesota restriction on judicial elections
    that prohibited a candidate from “announc[ing] his or her
    views on disputed legal or political issues,” a prohibition that
    FRENCH V. JONES                         9
    at the very least precluded “a judicial candidate from stating
    his views on any specific nonfanciful legal question within
    the province of the court for which he [was] running.” White
    I, 
    536 U.S. at 768, 773
     (citation omitted). The majority began
    by identifying a potential compelling interest Minnesota
    might have had in imposing the restriction: preserving both
    the actual and perceived impartiality of the state judiciary.
    
    Id.
     at 775–76. The Court warned, however, that speaking of
    the need for an impartial judiciary in general terms would not
    do; instead, it was necessary to pinpoint the precise meaning
    of the term “impartial.” 
    Id. at 775
    . The majority offered
    three definitions. 
    Id.
     at 775–84.
    First, the term could mean a “lack of bias for or against
    either party to the proceeding.” 
    Id. at 775
    . But if that is what
    impartiality meant, the majority reasoned, the restriction was
    not narrowly tailored because it “[did] not restrict speech for
    or against particular parties, but rather speech for or against
    particular issues.” 
    Id. at 776
    . Second, impartiality could
    mean a “lack of preconception in favor of or against a
    particular legal view.” 
    Id. at 777
    . The Court held, however,
    that preserving such impartiality was not a compelling state
    interest because “[p]roof that a Justice’s mind at the time he
    joined the Court was a complete tabula rasa in the area of
    constitutional adjudication would be evidence of lack of
    qualification, not lack of bias.” 
    Id. at 778
     (citation omitted).
    Finally, “[a] third possible meaning of ‘impartiality’ . . .
    might be described as open-mindedness.” 
    Id.
     “This sort of
    impartiality seeks to guarantee each litigant, not an equal
    chance to win the legal points in the case, but at least some
    chance of doing so.” 
    Id.
     While recognizing that the state’s
    desire to ensure the open-mindedness of its judges might be
    compelling, the Court could not accept that Minnesota’s
    restriction was tailored to address this concern because it was
    10                    FRENCH V. JONES
    “so woefully underinclusive.”        
    Id. at 780
    .      Indeed,
    “statements in election campaigns are . . . an infinitesimal
    portion of the public commitments to legal positions that
    judges (or judges-to-be) undertake,” for example, in legal
    opinions, public lectures, law review articles, and books. 
    Id. at 779
    . Because the restriction did not address such other
    public commitments, the Court concluded that the purpose
    behind the restriction was “not openmindedness in the
    judiciary, but the undermining of judicial elections.” 
    Id. at 782
    .
    In the aftermath of White I, few regulations of judicial-
    campaign speech withstood strict scrutiny. One of the most
    important decisions of that period, for our purposes, is the
    Eighth Circuit’s decision on remand from White I regarding
    the validity of a Minnesota restriction that was almost
    identical to Montana’s Rule 4.1(A)(7). See Republican Party
    of Minn. v. White (“White II”), 
    416 F.3d 738
    , 745 (8th Cir.
    2005) (en banc). Minnesota prohibited judges or judicial
    candidates from “identify[ing] themselves as members of a
    political organization,” “attend[ing] political gatherings,” or
    “seek[ing], accept[ing] or us[ing] endorsements from a
    political organization.” 
    Id.
     (quoting 52 Minn. Stat. Ann.,
    Code of Judicial Conduct, Canon 5, subd. (A)(1)). The court
    referred to the restriction as the “partisan-activities” clause.
    
    Id.
    Sitting en banc, a majority of the Eighth Circuit hewed
    closely to White I’s framework, identifying the three
    meanings of judicial impartiality discussed in the Supreme
    Court’s decision and then analyzing whether any of these
    interests justified the restriction. 
    Id.
     at 751–66. As to the
    first two meanings of impartiality—lack of party bias and
    preconception toward a particular legal view—the court
    FRENCH V. JONES                         11
    adopted the Supreme Court’s analysis, reasoning that the
    restriction involved in White I was not all that different from
    a restriction on associating with a particular political group.
    
    Id.
     at 753–56. And as to the third type of impartiality—
    judicial open-mindedness—the court thought that, like the
    restriction in White I, the partisan-activities clause was
    “woefully underinclusive.” Id. at 756. The clause prohibited
    “associative activities with a political party during a
    campaign,” but not at any time before that. Id. at 758. More
    important still, the court continued, “it ma[de] little sense for
    the state to restrict [associational] activity only with political
    parties,” but not with interest groups such as the National
    Rifle Association, the National Organization for Women, and
    the Christian Coalition, which could potentially harm judicial
    open-mindedness to the same extent. Id. at 759. And
    although the court acknowledged that treating political parties
    differently might be “justified given political parties’
    ‘powerful machinery,’ including a large membership, to
    enforce adherence to their views,” it countered that some
    Minnesota parties—such as the Constitution Party, the
    Natural Law Party, and the Green party—have “a more
    limited membership” and focus on “only a few issues.” Id. at
    760–61 n.12 (citation omitted). The court struck the partisan-
    activities clause under the First Amendment. Id. at 766.
    Other courts, including ours, followed the lead of White
    I and II and invalidated similar speech restrictions. In
    Sanders County, we ruled unconstitutional a Montana statute
    that made it a criminal offense for any political party to
    “endorse, contribute to, or make an expenditure to support or
    oppose a judicial candidate.” 698 F.3d at 744 (citing 
    Mont. Code Ann. § 13-35-23
    ). We accepted as true that “Montana
    has a compelling interest in maintaining a fair and
    independent judiciary,” but held that the statute was
    12                        FRENCH V. JONES
    underinclusive because it forbade “judicial endorsements by
    political parties but not by other associations, individuals,
    corporations, special interest groups and the like.” 
    Id.
     at
    746–47 (quoting and relying on White II’s discussion of
    underinclusivity). The panel majority also found no evidence
    that “preventing political parties from endorsing judicial
    candidates is a necessary prerequisite to maintaining a fair
    and independent judiciary,” especially given that many states
    “not only allow party endorsements but require party
    nominations.” Id. at 746. “If Montana were concerned that
    party endorsements might undermine elected judges’
    independence,” the court concluded, “Montana could appoint
    its judges, with a bipartisan and expert panel making
    nominations—a less restrictive alternative currently practiced
    by several states.” Id. at 747.3
    2
    The strict First Amendment framework of White I
    underwent significant changes with the Supreme Court’s
    decision in Williams-Yulee. Before the Court was a challenge
    to Florida’s solicitation restriction, which prohibited judicial
    candidates from personally soliciting funds but allowed them
    to establish committees to do so for them. Williams-Yulee,
    
    135 S. Ct. at 1663
    . The restriction was very similar to those
    invalidated by the Eighth Circuit in White II and the Sixth
    3
    Other circuits used analogous reasoning to strike various restrictions
    on judicial-campaign speech under White I. See Carey v. Wolnitzek,
    
    614 F.3d 189
    , 201–07 (6th Cir. 2010) (invalidating Kentucky’s regulations
    prohibiting judicial candidates from personally soliciting campaign funds
    and identifying themselves as members of political parties); Siefert v.
    Alexander, 
    608 F.3d 974
    , 981–83, 990 (7th Cir. 2010) (striking
    Wisconsin’s statute prohibiting judicial candidates from being members
    of political parties).
    FRENCH V. JONES                                13
    Circuit in Carey v. Wolnitzek, 
    614 F.3d 189
    , 201–07 (6th Cir.
    2010). Employing reasoning that contrasted sharply with
    White I, the Supreme Court upheld the regulation.
    The Court began by “hold[ing] . . . what [it] assumed in
    White: A State may restrict the speech of a judicial candidate
    only if the restriction is narrowly tailored to serve a
    compelling interest.” Id. at 1665 (plurality opinion).4 The
    Court then found that Florida had a compelling interest in
    “protecting the integrity” of its judiciary and “maintaining the
    public’s confidence in an impartial judiciary.” Id. at 1666
    (citation omitted). In contrast to White I, however, the Court
    did not attempt to define precisely what judicial integrity or
    impartiality means. Instead, it emphasized that “[t]he concept
    of public confidence in judicial integrity does not easily
    reduce to precise definition, nor does it lend itself to proof by
    documentary record. But no one denies that it is genuine and
    compelling.” Id. at 1667. “Unlike the executive or the
    legislature, the judiciary ‘has no influence over either the
    sword or the purse . . . .’ The judiciary’s authority therefore
    depends in large measure on the public’s willingness to
    respect and follow its decisions.” Id. at 1666 (quoting The
    Federalist No. 78, at 465).
    After accepting Florida’s general interest in judicial
    impartiality, the Court considered the argument made in
    every case discussed above: the restriction was fatally
    4
    Chief Justice Roberts’s opinion on the point commanded only a
    plurality of the Court. See id. at 1673 (Ginsburg, J., concurring in part and
    concurring in the judgment). The dissenting justices, however, agreed
    with the plurality on this point. Id. at 1676 (Scalia, J., dissenting); see id.
    at 1682 (Kennedy, J., dissenting) (largely agreeing with Justice Scalia’s
    analysis); id. at 1685 (Alito, J., dissenting) (same).
    14                     FRENCH V. JONES
    underinclusive. Id. at 1668. The challenger argued that
    underinclusivity arose because Florida permitted indirect
    solicitations through committees and the writing of thank-you
    notes, which ensured that candidates knew the identity of
    donors. Id. In the pre-Williams-Yulee world, these arguments
    successfully convinced courts to invalidate similar
    solicitation clauses. See Carey, 
    614 F.3d at 205
     (“Although
    the candidate himself may not solicit donations, his campaign
    committee may. . . . That leaves a rule preventing a candidate
    from sending a signed mass mailing to every voter in the
    district but permitting the candidate’s best friend to ask for a
    donation directly from an attorney who frequently practices
    before the court. Are not the risks of coercion and undue
    appearance far less with the first (prohibited) solicitation than
    the second (permitted) one?”); White II, 416 F.3d at 765–66.
    But the Court flatly rejected these arguments. Williams-
    Yulee, 
    135 S. Ct. at 1668
    . “It is always somewhat
    counterintuitive to argue,” the Court reasoned, “that a law
    violates the First Amendment by abridging too little speech.”
    
    Id.
     And although underinclusivity might indicate that the law
    does not advance a compelling state interest, “the First
    Amendment imposes no freestanding ‘underinclusiveness
    limitation.’” 
    Id.
     (citation omitted). “A State need not address
    all aspects of a problem in one fell swoop; policymakers may
    focus on their most pressing concerns.” 
    Id.
     Florida’s
    prohibition on only personal solicitations did precisely that.
    Despite the fact that a candidate’s campaign committee could
    solicit funds on behalf of the candidate, “Florida . . . ha[d]
    reasonably concluded that solicitation by the candidate
    personally creates a categorically different and more severe
    risk of undermining public confidence.” 
    Id. at 1669
    .
    Similarly, while permitting candidates to write thank you
    notes might “heighten[] the likelihood of actual bias by
    FRENCH V. JONES                        15
    ensuring that judicial candidates know who supported their
    campaigns, and ensuring that the supporter knows that the
    candidate knows,” the compelling interest in an impartial
    judiciary “is implicated most directly by the candidate’s
    personal solicitation itself.” 
    Id.
    Having dispensed with the argument that Florida
    prohibited too little speech, the Court turned to whether the
    solicitation provision restricted too much. 
    Id.
     at 1670–71.
    The challenger argued that her method of soliciting
    funds—mass mailing—presented such a small threat to the
    public confidence in the judiciary that Florida’s provision was
    unconstitutionally overinclusive. 
    Id. at 1671
    . Concluding it
    was not, the Court emphasized that the restriction must be
    only narrowly tailored, not “perfectly tailored,” because “the
    First Amendment does not confine a State to addressing evils
    in their most acute form.” 
    Id.
     (citation omitted). The Court
    declined to “wade into [the] swamp” of unworkable line
    drawing, respecting Florida’s conclusion “that all personal
    solicitations by judicial candidates”—no matter what form
    they take—“create a public appearance that undermines
    confidence in the integrity of the judiciary.”               
    Id.
    Accordingly, the Court ruled the solicitation provision a
    16                         FRENCH V. JONES
    permissible restriction under the First Amendment.5 
    Id. at 1673
    .
    Williams-Yulee marked a palpable change in the approach
    to state regulations of judicial-campaign speech—a change
    perhaps best exemplified by our unanimous en banc decision
    in Wolfson. Wolfson involved two Arizona restrictions on
    judicial speech similar to that before us: a prohibition on
    public endorsements of political candidates, via monetary
    contributions or otherwise, and a restriction on political
    campaigning generally. Wolfson, 811 F.3d at 1178–79 &
    nn.2–3. In upholding these provisions, we relied almost
    exclusively on Williams-Yulee. Id. at 1180–86. We first
    identified a broad compelling interest in preserving public
    confidence in the judiciary’s integrity without going through
    the interest analysis conducted in White I. Id. at 1182. We
    then addressed and rejected the challenger’s contention that
    the restrictions were both under- and overinclusive.
    The challenger’s underinclusivity argument was the same
    one accepted by the Eighth Circuit in White II and our court
    in Sanders County: the restriction was not narrowly tailored
    because, among other things, it permitted judicial candidates
    to endorse persons and entities other than political candidates.
    5
    Justice Scalia—the author of White I—wrote the principal dissent.
    He faulted the majority for failing to follow White I by permitting Florida
    “to invoke hazy concerns about judicial impartiality,” which he thought
    were too malleable for a strict scrutiny analysis. Id. at 1677–78 (Scalia,
    J., dissenting). He then questioned whether “allowing personal
    solicitations would imperil public faith in judges,” given the “coexistence
    of judicial elections and personal solicitations for most of our history.” Id.
    at 1678. And even if Florida’s prohibition did improve the public
    reputation of judges, Justice Scalia reasoned that it would still fail strict
    scrutiny because of its under- and overinclusivity. Id. at 1679–82.
    FRENCH V. JONES                        17
    Id. at 1183. But that argument, we held, was no longer
    persuasive in light of Williams-Yulee. Id. Although
    “Williams-Yulee may have been about a prohibition on direct
    candidate solicitations of campaign contributions, . . . the
    Supreme Court’s reasoning was broad enough to encompass
    underinclusivity arguments aimed at other types of judicial
    candidate speech prohibitions such as [the endorsement and
    campaign prohibitions].” Id. There was no need to “question
    whether Arizona could have . . . prohibited more types of
    endorsements or campaign participation” because Arizona
    was entitled to focus on only the most pressing concerns
    associated with “a judicial candidate actively engag[ing] in
    political campaigns.” Id. at 1184.
    As to overinclusivity, we acknowledged that Arizona’s
    restrictions reached actions that were unlikely to have any
    effect on judicial impartiality, such as a judicial candidate’s
    endorsement of the President of the United States. Id. But
    yet again, “Williams-Yulee forclose[d] [this] argument[].” Id.
    Following the lead of the Supreme Court, we declined to
    draw “unworkable and unnecessary line[s].” Id. at 1185. It
    was simply not “our proper role to second-guess Arizona’s
    decision[]” to prohibit judicial candidates from engaging in
    political campaigns, even if that prohibition encompassed
    “political acts [that] present different levels of impropriety in
    different situations.” Id. We therefore held that Arizona’s
    restrictions were narrowly tailored to achieve Arizona’s
    interest in upholding public confidence in the judiciary. Id.
    at 1186.
    3
    This summary evidences a change in the courts’ approach
    to state regulation of nonpartisan judicial elections. Although
    18                    FRENCH V. JONES
    there are several important differences between the cases we
    have described, perhaps the most important one of all, at least
    for our purposes, is the way in which White I, White II, and
    Sanders County, on the one hand, and Williams-Yulee and
    Wolfson, on the other, approached the challengers’
    underinclusivity arguments. And that difference might be
    more fundamental than it seems. According to White I, the
    underinclusivity of Minnesota’s restriction revealed that its
    underlying purpose was not judicial impartiality, “but the
    undermining of judicial elections.” 
    536 U.S. at 782
    ; see also
    Williams-Yulee, 
    135 S. Ct. at 1681
     (Scalia, J., dissenting)
    (“[The Florida restriction’s] scope suggests that it has nothing
    to do with the appearances created by judges’ asking for
    money, and everything to do with hostility toward judicial
    campaigning.”). That is, the problem Minnesota faced
    stemmed from the very scheme of judicial elections, which
    threatened judicial impartiality in and of itself. White I,
    
    536 U.S. at 782
     (“[E]lected judges—regardless of whether
    they have announced any views beforehand—always face the
    pressure of an electorate who might disagree with their
    rulings and therefore vote them off the bench.”). Minnesota’s
    attempts to address the problem without abandoning its
    election scheme served only to deprive voters of relevant
    information while failing to eliminate the underlying source
    of actual or perceived judicial bias. 
    Id. at 788
     (“[T]he greater
    power to dispense with elections altogether does not include
    the lesser power to conduct elections under conditions of
    state-imposed voter ignorance.” (alteration in original)).
    Consequently, after White I, a state was left with limited
    options in regulating its judicial elections because such
    FRENCH V. JONES                               19
    regulations would be almost always underinclusive.6 That is
    why in Sanders County, we considered appointment of judges
    a “less restrictive alternative” able to accomplish the state’s
    goal of judicial impartiality. 698 F.3d at 747.
    But the Williams-Yulee majority viewed things
    differently. It saw a middle ground where “policymakers
    [could] focus on their most pressing concerns” without
    completely eliminating the judicial bias (or perception
    thereof) associated with judicial elections generally.
    Williams-Yulee, 
    135 S. Ct. at 1668
    . In other words, a state
    could both abridge some judicial-campaign speech and
    preserve its election system—“[t]he First Amendment does
    not put a State to [an] all-or-nothing choice.” 
    Id. at 1670
    .
    The Court thus sustained Florida’s prohibition on personal
    solicitations, despite the fact that other methods of solicitation
    might also undermine judicial impartiality, because a
    complete ban would put an end to judicial elections
    altogether. Id.; see also 
    id. at 1681
     (Scalia, J., dissenting)
    (“One cannot have judicial elections without judicial
    campaigns, and judicial campaigns without funds for
    campaigning, and funds for campaigning without asking for
    them.”). As our court in Wolfson held, moreover, this view
    of underinclusivity extends not just to restrictions on
    campaign contributions but also “encompass[es]
    6
    We note that White I “neither assert[ed] nor impl[ied] that the First
    Amendment requires campaigns for judicial office to sound the same as
    those for legislative office.” Id. at 783. But we think it is nonetheless
    clear that White I envisioned as permissible only those regulations that
    targeted threats to impartiality more salient and direct than those inherent
    in a system of judicial elections. For instance, White I thought it plausible
    that campaign promises in particular might pose a “special threat to open-
    mindedness” that could be potentially redressible through regulation. Id.
    at 780–81.
    20                     FRENCH V. JONES
    underinclusivity arguments aimed at other types of judicial
    candidate speech prohibitions.” 811 F.3d at 1183.
    B
    Against this background, we turn to Montana’s Rule
    4.1(A)(7). As we have already mentioned, it prohibits
    judicial candidates like French from “seek[ing], accept[ing],
    or us[ing] endorsements from a political organization, or
    partisan or independent non-judicial office-holder or
    candidate . . . .” Mont. Code of Judicial Conduct Rule
    4.1(A)(7). Because Rule 4.1(A)(7) is a content-based
    restriction on speech, we may uphold it only if it is narrowly-
    tailored to achieve some compelling state interest. Wolfson,
    811 F.3d at 1180–81.
    We discern two such interests here. The first is an interest
    in both actual and perceived judicial impartiality. In
    Williams-Yulee, the Court noted “the regrettable but
    unavoidable appearance that judges who personally ask for
    money may diminish their integrity.” 
    135 S. Ct. at 1667
    .
    Likewise, we note here the regrettable but unavoidable
    consequence that judges who personally ask for political
    endorsements may diminish the public’s faith in the
    impartiality of the judiciary, whether a judge’s actual
    impartiality is affected or not. Seeking and using political
    endorsements may create the appearance that a judge will
    favor certain politicians or political parties and thereby
    “undermine the public’s confidence that judges base rulings
    on law, and not on party affiliation.” Wolfson, 811 F.3d at
    1183, 1186. We need not define Montana’s interest in terms
    more specific than these, for “no one denies that [this interest]
    is genuine and compelling.” Williams-Yulee, 
    135 S. Ct. at 1667
    .
    FRENCH V. JONES                            21
    Rule 4.1(A)(7) furthers a second interest that might be
    more compelling still: a related but distinct interest in a
    structurally independent judiciary. See Wolfson, 811 F.3d at
    1186–88 (Berzon, J., concurring). If judicial candidates,
    including sitting judges running for reelection, regularly
    solicit and use endorsements from political parties, the public
    might view the judiciary as indebted to, dependent on, and in
    the end not different from the political branches. One way to
    preserve the distance between the judiciary and the political
    branches is to place the judiciary on a different footing and do
    so in a way that is visible to the public. The federal system
    insulates the third branch from partisan activities by
    separating judges from the direct-election process. Some
    states have followed the federal model; others have adopted
    an appointment-and-retention-election model; and still others
    have decided on elections.7 These systems have their critics
    and their defenders. It is not for us to choose among these
    systems because the U.S. Constitution does not prescribe any
    particular form for state judicial elections. What is sufficient
    for our purposes is to observe that these various models all
    treat the selection of judges differently from the processes for
    choosing our other public officials. That fact alone separates
    the judicial branch from the political branches. Montana has
    chosen to structure its third branch differently from the
    political branches, and we cannot fault its efforts to reinforce
    that choice in the manner in which it elects its judges. The
    Federalist No. 78 at 466 (“‘[T]here is no liberty, if the power
    of judging be not separated from the legislative and executive
    powers.’” (citation omitted)).
    7
    See Methods of Judicial Selection, NAT’L CTR. FOR ST. CTS.,
    http://www.judicialselection.us/judicial_selection/methods/selection_of
    _judges.cfm?state= (last visited Oct. 17, 2017).
    22                    FRENCH V. JONES
    French and his amicus curiae nonetheless contend that
    Rule 4.1(A)(7) cannot survive strict scrutiny because is
    underinclusive, overinclusive, and otherwise insufficiently
    tailored to any interests Montana might have. Although these
    arguments might have been persuasive in the pre-Williams-
    Yulee era, they no longer carry the day. As we explain below,
    Rule 4.1(A)(7)’s scope is sufficiently narrowly tailored to
    pass muster under the First Amendment.
    1
    French’s primary claim is that Rule 4.1(A)(7) is fatally
    underinclusive. To begin with, French correctly points out
    that the rule prohibits candidates from seeking and using
    endorsements from political organizations but does not forbid
    any interest groups, corporations, and other entities from
    making such endorsements. This same argument persuaded
    the court in White II to invalidate a provision almost identical
    to Rule 4.1(A)(7), 416 F.3d at 758, and was successful in
    convincing our court in Sanders County to strike down a
    different Montana restriction, 698 F.3d at 747. But White II
    and Sanders County were decided before Williams-Yulee
    clarified that “the First Amendment imposes no freestanding
    ‘underinclusiveness limitation’” and that “policymakers may
    focus on their most pressing concerns.” 
    135 S. Ct. at 1668
    (citation omitted). Relying on these pronouncements,
    Wolfson held that an endorsement provision—one that
    prohibited judicial candidates from endorsing individuals
    running for a political office—was not invalid simply because
    it “allow[ed] judicial candidates to endorse public officials
    and non-candidates.” 811 F.3d at 1183. We reached this
    conclusion despite the possibility that “Arizona could have
    . . . prohibited more types of endorsements or campaign
    participation.” Id. at 1184.
    FRENCH V. JONES                       23
    Wolfson’s repudiation of French’s argument aside,
    political parties are simply not the same as interest groups
    and private individuals. Parties have comprehensive
    platforms, take firm positions on a multitude of issues, and
    are capable of exerting more influence in an election than
    most (if not any) interest groups. The Supreme Court
    described the “salient” and “real-world differences between
    political parties and interest groups” in McConnell v. Federal
    Election Commission:
    Interest groups do not select slates of
    candidates for elections. Interest groups do
    not determine who will serve on legislative
    committees, elect congressional leadership, or
    organize legislative caucuses. Political parties
    have influence and power in the Legislature
    that vastly exceeds that of any interest group.
    As a result, it is hardly surprising that party
    affiliation is the primary way by which voters
    identify candidates, or that parties in turn have
    special access to and relationships with
    federal officeholders.
    
    540 U.S. 93
    , 188 (2003), overruled on other grounds by
    Citizens United, 
    558 U.S. 310
    .
    Once we turn to Montana’s interest in judicial
    independence (as opposed to mere judicial impartiality) the
    differences between political parties and interest groups grow
    starker. An endorsement from a political party threatens the
    public perception of judicial independence to a greater degree
    than an endorsement from an interest group. In all cases, an
    endorsement suggests the possibility of a quid-pro-quo
    exchange in which a judge may rule favorably for the
    24                   FRENCH V. JONES
    endorsing entity. But whereas a judge may only infrequently
    encounter litigation implicating an endorsing interest group,
    he or she is likely to often face legislation an endorsing
    political party has either supported or opposed. Dependence
    on an endorsing political party brings into question whether
    a judge will be able to independently interpret and review a
    given piece of legislation and thus goes to the core of the
    separation of powers. For all these reasons, Montana is well
    within its authority to focus its immediate concern on
    endorsements from political parties.
    French next suggests that Rule 4.1(A)(7) is impermissibly
    underinclusive because Montana permits candidates to solicit
    and use political parties’ money but not their endorsements.
    We are not persuaded. Endorsements and campaign
    contributions are different kinds of support. An endorsement
    is a public and easily communicable show of solidarity.
    Although most campaign contributions are also public
    information, see 
    Mont. Code Ann. § 13-37-229
    , they are less
    forceful and less easily communicable. Unlike endorsements,
    information on campaign contributions typically requires
    extra work for voters to access. It would therefore not be
    surprising for judicial candidates to derive more value from
    endorsements from political parties and popular politicians
    (including politicians outside Montana) than from even
    sizeable donations. Montana could reasonably conclude that
    endorsements are more suggestive of a quid-pro-quo
    exchange and pose a greater risk to the public perception of
    its judiciary than donations. Thus, we decline to disturb
    Montana’s determination that monetary donations “present
    markedly different appearance to the public,” Williams-Yulee,
    
    135 S. Ct. at 1669
    , than a candidate’s use of a political
    endorsement.
    FRENCH V. JONES                       25
    French’s remaining reasons for deeming Rule 4.1(A)(7)
    unconstitutionally underinclusive are the weakest. French
    complains that the rule applies only during campaigns and
    only to endorsements from “non-judicial office-holders.” But
    in order to create an impartial and independent judiciary, it
    makes perfect sense for Montana to prohibit the solicitation
    and use of endorsements during (as opposed to before) a
    judicial candidate’s campaign and limit those endorsements
    to political office holders and entities (as opposed to
    nonpartisan judges). It is almost self-evident that the dangers
    of actual and perceived bias and dependence are not nearly as
    great when the candidate is not yet running for office or when
    she uses endorsements from nonpartisan judges. According
    to French, Montana may ban the use of endorsements only if
    it bans the use of all endorsements from any individuals or
    entities at any time. But “[t]he First Amendment does not put
    a State to that all-or-nothing choice.” Williams-Yulee, 
    135 S. Ct. at 1670
    .
    French’s amicus appears to make an additional
    argument—one that was accepted in White II. It goes like
    this: A candidate’s discussion of her endorsements with the
    public is not all that different from a discussion of other
    important issues because a party label is just a “shorthand for
    the [numerous] views the candidate holds.” White II,
    416 F.3d at 754. And because White I made clear that a
    restriction on the candidates’ announcement of views is
    woefully underinclusive, a restriction on the use of political
    endorsements must be as well. We cannot accept this
    argument. The seeking and using of political endorsements
    is nothing like announcing one’s views on certain issues. An
    endorsement is a thing of value: it may attract voters’
    attention, jumpstart a campaign, give assurance that the
    candidate has been vetted, or provide legitimacy to an
    26                     FRENCH V. JONES
    unknown candidate and indicate that he or she is capable of
    mounting a successful campaign. Such things of value are
    usually not given out for free, and even when they are, the
    mere perception of quid pro quo in judicial campaigns might
    undermine the public’s trust in the impartiality and
    independence of its judiciary.
    Along these same lines, French’s amicus suggests that
    Wolfson is distinguishable because the restriction there
    prohibited candidates from speaking about others but not
    themselves. While Wolfson did state that “Arizona’s
    prohibitions do not prevent judicial candidates from
    announcing their views on disputed legal and political
    subjects,” Rule 4.1(A)(7) here does not prohibit candidates
    from “announcing their views on disputed legal and political
    subjects.” 811 F.3d at 1185. Candidates in Montana are still
    free to discuss political issues with their electorate. They can
    speak on abortion, criminal sentencing, healthcare, gun
    control, and dozens of other matters of controversy. What
    they cannot do is tell their electorate that a political party has
    given their candidacy a valuable stamp of approval. That
    restriction is not unconstitutionally underinclusive because it
    addresses a very specific concern present whenever a
    candidate for a nonpartisan office receives something of value
    from a partisan organization.
    2
    French and his amicus next argue that Rule 4.1(A)(7) is
    overinclusive because, unlike the solicitation restriction in
    Williams-Yulee, Montana does not allow even the candidates’
    campaign committees to seek and use political endorsements.
    Mont. Code of Judicial Conduct Rule 4.1(B) (providing that
    “[a] judge or judicial candidate shall take reasonable
    FRENCH V. JONES                        27
    measures to ensure that other persons do not undertake, on
    behalf of the judge or judicial candidate, any activities
    prohibited in paragraph (A)”). But that is hardly a fair
    criticism of Rule 4.1(A)(7). Montana’s interests in an
    impartial and independent judiciary do not diminish simply
    because it is the candidate’s affiliates who go around telling
    voters about the political endorsements the candidate has
    received. The danger lies in the public losing trust in its
    judges from hearing political endorsements; it is irrelevant
    whether the candidate or the candidate’s committee delivers
    the message.
    But even accepting that a committee engaging in
    prohibited conduct threatens judicial impartiality and
    independence to a lesser degree, the Supreme Court has told
    us that “the First Amendment does not confine a State to
    addressing evils in their most acute form.” Williams-Yulee,
    
    135 S. Ct. at 1671
    . Following the lead of Williams-Yulee and
    Wolfson, we decline to draw such arbitrary and unnecessary
    lines. Id.; Wolfson, 811 F.3d at 1185. Montana has
    reasonably determined that both candidates and their
    committees pose a threat to its judiciary when they seek,
    accept, or use political endorsements in their campaigns.
    This “considered judgement[] deserve[s] our respect.”
    Williams-Yulee, 
    135 S. Ct. at 1671
    .
    3
    Finally, French asserts that Rule 4.1(A)(7) is generally not
    narrowly tailored because Montana has presented no evidence
    showing that political endorsements cause harm. Indeed, as
    French rightly notes, several states not only allow but require
    political endorsements because their judicial elections are
    partisan. But neither of these two points defeats Rule
    28                    FRENCH V. JONES
    4.1(A)(7); the Court has not treated judicial elections as an
    either/or proposition, requiring any state that chooses to have
    judicial elections to conduct them like all other elections. As
    to the lack of evidence, the Supreme Court has flatly stated
    that “[t]he concept of public confidence in judicial integrity
    . . . does [not] lend itself to proof by documentary record.”
    
    Id. at 1667
    . Montana need not present empirical evidence of
    something as abstract as a decrease in actual or perceived
    judicial impartiality and independence for its rule to survive
    strict scrutiny. And as to the point regarding states with
    partisan judicial elections, neither Williams-Yulee nor
    Wolfson so much as thought about invalidating restrictions
    designed to preserve nonpartisanship in judicial elections
    simply because there are some states that have partisan
    elections and appear to be doing just fine. If that fact alone
    were sufficient to invalidate a restriction on judicial-
    campaign speech, then nonpartisan judicial elections could be
    themselves deemed unconstitutional. We decline to reach
    such a result.
    Although French suggests that eliminating judicial
    elections altogether would be a less restrictive means to
    accomplishing Montana’s stated goals, Williams-Yulee and
    Wolfson foreclose that suggestion. Those cases confirm that
    the states have every right to devise and regulate a system of
    nonpartisan judicial elections. Williams-Yulee, 
    135 S. Ct. at 1671
    ; Wolfson, 811 F.3d at 1185. The Constitution does not
    demand that the states follow the federal model and appoint
    their judges, and if it permits the states to hold partisan
    judicial elections, we see no impediment to the states
    adopting nonpartisan judicial elections, as Montana has done.
    *       *       *
    FRENCH V. JONES                      29
    We hold that Montana has compelling interests in an
    impartial and independent judiciary. Rule 4.1(A)(7) is
    narrowly tailored to those interests because it strikes an
    appropriate balance between a candidate’s speech and
    Montana’s interest in an independent and impartial judiciary.
    French’s arguments to the contrary are foreclosed by the
    Supreme Court’s decision in Williams-Yulee and our decision
    in Wolfson.
    AFFIRMED.