Alan Philipp v. Federal Republic of Germany (ORDER IN SLIP OPINION FORMAT) , 925 F.3d 1349 ( 2019 )


Menu:
  • United States Court of Appeals
    FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA CIRCUIT
    Filed On: June 18, 2019
    No. 17-7064
    ALAN PHILIPP, ET AL.,
    APPELLEES
    v.
    FEDERAL REPUBLIC OF GERMANY, A FOREIGN STATE AND
    STIFTUNG PREUSSISCHER KULTURBESITZ,
    APPELLANTS
    Consolidated with 17-7117
    Appeals from the United States District Court
    for the District of Columbia
    (No. 1:15-cv-00266)
    On Petition for Rehearing En Banc
    Before: GARLAND, Chief Judge; HENDERSON,
    ROGERS, TATEL, GRIFFITH, SRINIVASAN, MILLETT, PILLARD,
    WILKINS, KATSAS**, AND RAO*, Circuit Judges.
    ORDER
    Appellants’ petition for rehearing en banc, the
    response thereto, and the amicus curiae brief in
    2
    support of rehearing en banc were circulated to the full court,
    and a vote was requested. Thereafter, a majority of the judges
    eligible to participate did not vote in favor of the petition.
    Upon consideration of the foregoing, it is
    ORDERED that the petition be denied.
    Per Curiam
    FOR THE COURT:
    Mark J. Langer, Clerk
    BY:     /s/
    Ken R. Meadows
    Deputy Clerk
    * Circuit Judge Rao did not participate in this matter
    ** A statement by Circuit Judge Katsas, dissenting from the
    denial of rehearing en banc, is attached.
    KATSAS, Circuit Judge, dissenting from the denial of
    rehearing en banc:
    The panel decision in this case, together with Simon v.
    Republic of Hungary, 
    812 F.3d 127
    (D.C. Cir. 2016) (Simon I),
    and Simon v. Republic of Hungary, 
    911 F.3d 1172
    (D.C. Cir.
    2018) (Simon II), makes the district court sit as a war crimes
    tribunal to adjudicate claims of genocide arising in Europe
    during World War II. The basis for these decisions is not any
    federal statute authorizing a private right of action for victims
    of foreign genocide, nor even any statute punishing foreign
    genocide under United States law. Rather, these decisions rest
    on a statute abrogating the jurisdictional immunity of foreign
    sovereigns from claims for unlawful takings of property. As a
    result, the district court must hear genocide claims against
    foreign sovereigns, but only to determine whether it has
    subject-matter jurisdiction over common-law tort claims for
    conversion and the like. Moreover, the plaintiffs bringing these
    genocide-based takings claims may recover neither for killings
    nor even for personal injuries, but only for the loss of their
    property. And the district court must adjudicate these claims—
    and thus effectively determine the scope of a genocide—
    without first affording the foreign sovereign an opportunity to
    provide redress, whether for genocide or conversion.
    Before allowing this remarkable scheme to proceed
    further, we should reconsider it en banc. In this case, Philipp
    v. Federal Republic of Germany, 
    894 F.3d 406
    (D.C. Cir.
    2018), and in Simon II, we rejected any defense of exhaustion
    or comity-based abstention for claims under the Foreign
    Sovereign Immunities Act (FSIA). These decisions create a
    clear split with the Seventh Circuit, are in tension with
    decisions from the Ninth and Eleventh Circuits, disregard the
    views of the Executive Branch on a matter of obvious foreign-
    policy sensitivity, and make the FSIA more amenable to
    human-rights litigation against foreign sovereigns than the
    Alien Tort Statute (ATS) is to human-rights litigation against
    2
    private defendants abetting the sovereigns. Moreover, they
    clear the way for a wide range of litigation against foreign
    sovereigns for public acts committed within their own
    territories. This includes claims not only for genocide, but also
    for the violation of most other norms of international human-
    rights law. The consequences of Simon I and its progeny are
    thus dramatic, while their foundations are shaky.
    I
    The FSIA provides that “a foreign state shall be immune
    from the jurisdiction of the courts of the United States and of
    the States except as provided” in the FSIA itself. 28 U.S.C.
    § 1604. It then provides that a “foreign state shall not be
    immune from the jurisdiction of courts of the United States or
    of the States” when certain exceptions apply. 
    Id. § 1605.
    The
    exception at issue here, commonly called the “expropriation
    exception,” applies to any case
    in which rights in property taken in violation of
    international law are in issue and that property or any
    property exchanged for such property is present in the
    United States in connection with a commercial
    activity carried on in the United States by the foreign
    state; or that property or any property exchanged for
    such property is owned or operated by an agency or
    instrumentality of the foreign state and that agency or
    instrumentality is engaged in a commercial activity in
    the United States.
    
    Id. § 1605(a)(3).
    In Simon I, this Court held that the expropriation exception
    covers property taken as part of a genocide. We reasoned that
    genocide includes deliberately inflicting on a protected group
    3
    “conditions of life calculated to bring about its physical
    
    destruction.” 812 F.3d at 143
    (quotation marks omitted). We
    held that the complaint at issue, which described the experience
    of Jews in Hungary between 1941 and 1944, adequately alleged
    “the requisite genocidal acts and intent,” including a
    “systematic, ‘wholesale plunder of Jewish property’” that
    “aimed to deprive Hungarian Jews of the resources needed to
    survive as a people.” 
    Id. at 143–44
    (citation omitted). We
    recognized that the international law of expropriation applies
    only to takings by one sovereign of property owned by
    nationals of another. 
    Id. at 144.
    But we distinguished the
    prohibition against genocide, which encompasses acts
    committed by a sovereign “against its own nationals.” 
    Id. at 145.
        We also acknowledged that, for genocide-based
    expropriation claims, the jurisdictional and merits inquiries
    diverge: Genocide must be established to create subject-matter
    jurisdiction, but the merits involve “garden-variety common-
    law causes of action such as conversion, unjust enrichment, and
    restitution.” 
    Id. at 141.
    As to damages, we noted that another
    FSIA exception covers claims “for personal injury or death,”
    but only for losses “occurring in the United States.” 28 U.S.C.
    § 1605(a)(5). So, we construed the expropriation exception to
    permit plaintiffs claiming genocide to “seek compensation for
    taken property but not for taken 
    lives.” 812 F.3d at 146
    (quotation marks omitted).
    In Philipp and Simon II, this Court rejected exhaustion,
    abstention, and forum non conveniens defenses to the
    genocide-based expropriation claims recognized in Simon I. In
    Philipp, the panel held that the FSIA, by comprehensively
    codifying rules for foreign sovereign immunity, foreclosed any
    requirement that plaintiffs exhaust remedies available in the
    courts of the defendant 
    sovereign. 894 F.3d at 414
    –16. Simon
    II reaffirmed that holding. There, we stated that, unlike other
    common-law defenses preserved by the FSIA, exhaustion
    4
    “lacks any pedigree in domestic or international common 
    law.” 911 F.3d at 1181
    . We further reasoned that, if an exhaustion
    requirement would preclude the plaintiffs from returning to
    federal court (as would a comity-based abstention
    requirement), that would only make exhaustion more like
    immunity. 
    Id. at 1180.
    Then, we held that the district court
    abused its discretion in dismissing the claims on forum non
    conveniens grounds, even though they involved acts
    perpetrated by the Hungarian government against Hungarian
    nationals in Hungary. 
    Id. at 1181–90.
    II
    A
    The expropriation exception applies to claims for
    “property taken in violation of international law.” 28 U.S.C.
    § 1605(a)(3). Simon I held that this provision encompasses
    property taken in violation of the international-law prohibition
    against genocide. In my judgment, it encompasses only
    property taken in violation of international takings law. The
    literal language could bear either meaning, but statutes must be
    construed in context. See, e.g., Nat’l Ass’n of Home Builders
    v. Defs. of Wildlife, 
    551 U.S. 644
    , 666 (2007). Here, several
    contextual considerations support the narrower reading.
    To begin, genocide is not about the taking of property.
    Rather, it involves the attempted extermination of a national,
    ethnic, racial, or religious group. A United Nations convention
    defines genocide as:
    any of the following acts committed with intent to
    destroy, in whole or in part, a national, ethnical, racial,
    or religious group, as such: (a) Killing members of
    the group; (b) Causing serious bodily or mental harm
    5
    to members of the group; (c) Deliberately inflicting on
    the group conditions of life calculated to bring about
    its physical destruction in whole or in part.
    Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of
    Genocide art. 2, Dec. 9, 1948, 78 U.N.T.S. 277. Simon I
    reasoned that takings may have a genocidal intent, and thus
    meet the last prong of this 
    definition. 812 F.3d at 143
    –44. But
    they still must be intended to cause the “physical destruction”
    of a group—what matters is the attempted mass murder. And
    if genocide involves attempted mass murder, a provision keyed
    to “property taken” would be a remarkably elliptical way of
    addressing it. See, e.g., Whitman v. Am. Trucking Ass’ns, 
    531 U.S. 457
    , 468 (2001).
    It would be even stranger for Congress to address genocide
    as exclusively a property offense. The FSIA’s expropriation
    exception encompasses only claims for “property,” 28 U.S.C.
    § 1605(a)(3), whereas its separate tort exception, which
    encompasses claims “for personal injury or death,” covers only
    harms “occurring in the United States,” 
    id. § 1605(a)(5).
    So,
    Simon I approved an exceedingly odd type of genocide claim—
    one for property harms but not for personal injury or death.
    Moreover, the expropriation exception requires a connection
    between the property taken and commercial activity in the
    United States: the property or its proceeds must either be
    “present in the United States in connection with a commercial
    activity carried on in the United States by the foreign state,” or
    “owned or operated by an agency or instrumentality of the
    foreign state” that is itself “engaged in a commercial activity in
    the United States.” 
    Id. § 1605(a)(3).
    These requirements
    would make little sense in a provision addressed to human-
    rights abuses such as genocide, rather than to purely economic
    wrongdoing.
    6
    As strange is the mismatch between jurisdiction and
    merits. Simon I requires proof of genocide to abrogate
    sovereign immunity—which must be determined at the outset.
    See Bolivarian Republic of Venezuela v. Helmerich & Payne
    Int’l Drilling Co., 
    137 S. Ct. 1312
    , 1318–24 (2017). But
    abrogating immunity does not create a private right of action,
    Cicippio-Puleo v. Islamic Republic of Iran, 
    353 F.3d 1024
    ,
    1033 (D.C. Cir. 2004), and there is no common-law right of
    action for genocide. Instead, the merits here involve “‘garden-
    variety common-law’ claims,” such as “replevin, conversion,
    unjust enrichment, and bailment.” 
    Philipp, 894 F.3d at 410
    –11
    (citation omitted); see also Simon 
    I, 812 F.3d at 141
    . This
    scheme oddly matches the jurisdictional equivalent of a
    thermonuclear weapon (determining the scope of a genocide)
    to the merits equivalent of swatting a fly (determining whether
    there was a common-law conversion). And it is in marked
    contrast to the FSIA’s terrorism exception, which applies to
    claims for various specified acts, 28 U.S.C. § 1605A(a)(1), and
    which creates a cause of action for those acts, 
    id. § 1605A(c).
    Broader statutory context creates further difficulties. The
    FSIA’s other primary exceptions are narrow ones covering
    waiver, commercial activity in the United States, rights to
    property in the United States, torts causing injury in the United
    States, and arbitration. 28 U.S.C. § 1605(a)(1)–(6). The
    Supreme Court has described these exceptions as collectively
    codifying the pre-FSIA “restrictive” theory of foreign
    sovereign immunity, which covers a sovereign’s “public acts”
    but not its commercial ones. See Helmerich & Payne, 137 S.
    Ct. at 1320–21; Verlinden B.V. v. Cent. Bank of Nigeria, 
    461 U.S. 480
    , 486–89 (1983). In a case specifically involving the
    expropriation exception, the Court “found nothing in the
    history of the statute that suggests Congress intended a radical
    departure from these basic principles.” Helmerich & 
    Payne, 137 S. Ct. at 1320
    . Abrogating immunity for public acts
    7
    committed by a foreign sovereign against its own nationals
    within its own territory would be just such a radical departure.
    The international law of foreign sovereign immunity cuts
    in the same direction. Here is its “Basic Rule”: “Under
    international law, a state or state instrumentality is immune
    from the jurisdiction of the courts of another state, except with
    respect to claims arising out of activities of the kind that may
    be carried on by private persons.” Restatement (Third) of the
    Foreign Relations Law of the United States § 451 (1987) (Third
    Restatement). Like the FSIA, international law provides
    narrow exceptions to immunity for claims arising out of
    commercial activity, 
    id. § 453(1);
    torts causing injuries within
    the forum state, 
    id. § 454(1);
    property claims involving
    commercial activities, gifts, or immovable property in the
    forum state, 
    id. § 455(1);
    and waiver, 
    id. § 456(1).
    None of
    these exceptions covers the genocide-based takings claims
    recognized in Simon I. So, Simon I construes the FSIA to
    conflict with international law—which is to be avoided if
    possible. See Murray v. Schooner Charming Betsy, 6 U.S. (2
    Cranch) 64, 118 (1804). Of course, none of this suggests that
    genocide or other violations of international human-rights law
    should go unremedied; but such violations typically are
    addressed either through diplomacy or in international
    tribunals, rather than in the domestic tribunals of another
    sovereign. See Third Restatement § 906 & cmt. b.
    Consistent with these principles, the courts have rejected
    attempts to shoehorn modern human-rights law into the FSIA
    exceptions. For example, in Saudi Arabia v. Nelson, 
    507 U.S. 349
    (1993), the Supreme Court held that the commercial-
    activity exception did not cover claims that Saudi Arabia
    illegally detained and tortured a United States citizen employed
    by a Saudi government hospital. The Court construed the
    exception to track the restrictive theory of sovereign immunity:
    8
    [T]he intentional conduct alleged here (the Saudi
    Government’s wrongful arrest, imprisonment, and
    torture of Nelson) could not qualify as commercial
    under the restrictive theory. The conduct boils down
    to abuse of the power of its police by the Saudi
    Government, and however monstrous such abuse
    undoubtedly may be, a foreign state’s exercise of the
    power of its police has long been understood for
    purposes of the restrictive theory as peculiarly
    sovereign in nature.
    
    Id. at 361.
    In Princz v. Federal Republic of Germany, 
    26 F.3d 1166
    (D.C. Cir. 1994), we likewise construed the FSIA’s
    waiver exception, which includes waivers “by implication,” 28
    U.S.C. § 1605(a)(1), to track the restrictive theory. We held
    that Germany did not impliedly waive its foreign sovereign
    immunity by using slave labor during the Nazi 
    era. 26 F.3d at 1173
    . And we did so despite recognizing that slavery—like
    genocide—violates a jus cogens norm of international human-
    rights law, i.e., “a norm from which no derogation is
    permitted.” 
    Id. (quotation marks
    omitted).
    The only deviation from this pattern is the FSIA’s
    terrorism exception, which covers a significant class of cases
    involving the public acts of a foreign sovereign. But the
    differences between the terrorism and expropriation exceptions
    are striking: The terrorism exception meticulously describes
    and limits the possible plaintiffs (United States nationals,
    members of the United States armed forces, and United States
    employees or contractors), 28 U.S.C. § 1605A(a)(2)(A)(ii); the
    possible defendants (generally, foreign states formally
    designated as sponsors of terrorism), 
    id. § 1605A(a)(2)(A)(i);
    the acts triggering the exception (“torture, extrajudicial killing,
    aircraft sabotage, hostage taking, or the provision of material
    support or resources for such an act”), 
    id. § 1605A(a)(1);
    the
    9
    associated private cause of action (covering the same parties
    and acts), 
    id. § 1605A(c);
    and the damages available (for
    personal injury, death, or foreseeable property loss), 
    id. § 1605A(a)(1),
    (d). This carefully reticulated framework is far
    different from a provision keyed only to “property taken in
    violation of international law.” 
    Id. § 1605(a)(3).
    B
    The grave consequences of Simon I bear not only on its
    correctness, but also on the appropriateness of en banc review.
    Most obviously, Simon I requires federal courts to
    determine the scope of genocide committed by various foreign
    countries during World War II. We suggested that this
    determination may sometimes be straightforward—as in the
    case of Hungarian Jews in the early 1940s. 
    See 812 F.3d at 142
    –44. Even so, each individual plaintiff must prove not only
    that there was a genocide, but also that he or she (or a decedent)
    was subjected to a genocidal taking. Sometimes, this will be
    far from clear. For example, the Philipp panel concluded that
    a coerced sale of art in 1935, for “barely 35% of its actual
    value,” could be an act of 
    genocide. 894 F.3d at 409
    , 413–14
    (quotation marks omitted). Germany objected that the
    plaintiffs’ theory would transform into genocide any
    “‘transaction from 1933–45 between’ a Nazi-allied
    government and ‘an individual from a group that suffered Nazi
    persecution.’” 
    Id. at 414.
    The panel envisioned something
    only slightly less concerning—case-by-case adjudications of
    which commercial transactions were sufficiently coercive,
    unfair, and improperly motivated to be genocide. 
    Id. Such claims
    could be made against a number of European nations.
    See, e.g., Republic of Austria v. Altmann, 
    541 U.S. 677
    (2004);
    Cassirer v. Kingdom of Spain, 
    616 F.3d 1019
    (9th Cir. 2010)
    (en banc); Alperin v. Vatican Bank, 
    410 F.3d 532
    (9th Cir.
    10
    2005); Freund v. Republic of France, 
    592 F. Supp. 2d 540
    (S.D.N.Y. 2008). And they would create massive exposure.
    For example, in a case that, like Simon, involved Jews who lost
    property in the Hungarian Holocaust, the damages sought were
    some $75 billion—“nearly 40 percent of Hungary’s annual
    gross domestic product in 2011.” Abelesz v. Magyar Nemzeti
    Bank, 
    692 F.3d 661
    , 682 (7th Cir. 2012).
    Moreover, the reasoning of Simon I cannot be limited to
    genocide. International law sharply distinguishes between the
    law of expropriation, which restricts only the takings by one
    sovereign of property belonging to the nationals of another, see
    Third Restatement § 712, and human-rights law, which now
    governs one sovereign’s treatment of its own nationals within
    its own borders, 
    id. § 701.
    Under the latter,
    A state violates international law if, as a matter of state
    policy, it practices, encourages, or condones
    (a) genocide, (b) slavery or slave trade, (c) the murder
    or causing the disappearance of individuals,
    (d) torture or other cruel, inhuman, or degrading
    treatment or punishment, (e) prolonged arbitrary
    detention, (f) systematic racial discrimination, or (g) a
    consistent pattern of gross violations of
    internationally recognized human rights.
    
    Id. § 702.
    The first six of these seven categories are jus cogens
    norms—the most serious ones, which are binding even in the
    face of an international agreement to the contrary. 
    Id. cmt. n.
    Most of them—including not only genocide, but also slavery,
    murder, degrading treatment, and systemic racial
    discrimination—can involve harms to property. Under the
    reasoning of Simon I, all of these could be the subject of
    litigation through the expropriation exception.
    11
    To appreciate the gravity of this, consider if the shoe were
    on the other foot. Imagine the United States’ reaction if a
    European trial court undertook to adjudicate a claim for tens of
    billions of dollars for property losses suffered by a class of
    American victims of slavery or systemic racial discrimination.
    Yet that is a precise mirror image of Simon. Given the stakes,
    what we once said about the waiver exception rings true here:
    We think that something more nearly express is
    wanted before we impute to the Congress an intention
    that the federal courts assume jurisdiction over the
    countless human rights cases that might well be
    brought by the victims of all the ruthless military
    juntas, presidents-for-life, and murderous dictators of
    the world, from Idi Amin to Mao Zedong. Such an
    expansive reading of § 1605(a)(1) would likely place
    an enormous strain not only upon our courts but, more
    to the immediate point, upon our country’s diplomatic
    relations with any number of foreign nations. In many
    if not most cases the outlaw regime would no longer
    even be in power and our Government could have
    normal relations with the government of the day—
    unless disrupted by our courts, that is.
    
    Princz, 26 F.3d at 1175
    n.1.
    III
    Philipp and Simon II magnify the concerns about Simon I
    and come with their own analytical difficulties.
    A
    On the merits, Philipp and Simon II held that the FSIA
    forecloses any exhaustion or comity-based abstention 
    defense. 894 F.3d at 414
    –16; 911 F.3d at 1180–81. But far from
    12
    foreclosing these defenses, the FSIA affirmatively
    accommodates them. It provides that, for any claim falling
    within an immunity exception, “the foreign state shall be liable
    in the same manner and to the same extent as a private
    individual under like circumstances.” 28 U.S.C. § 1606. A
    “private individual” under “like circumstances” would be one
    facing claims for aiding and abetting violations of international
    human-rights law. Such claims would be brought under the
    ATS, which provides that “[t]he district courts shall have
    original jurisdiction of any civil action by an alien for a tort
    only, committed in violation of the law of nations or a treaty of
    the United States.” 28 U.S.C. § 1350. Another like
    circumstance might involve private individuals sued for
    wrongful death, battery, or conversion. In either instance,
    exhaustion and abstention defenses would likely be available.
    The Supreme Court has at least hinted that an ATS
    plaintiff must exhaust local remedies before litigating an
    international-law tort claim in federal district court. In Sosa v.
    Alvarez-Machain, 
    542 U.S. 692
    (2004), the Court explained:
    the European Commission argues … that basic
    principles of international law require that before
    asserting a claim in a foreign forum, the claimant must
    have exhausted any remedies available in the
    domestic legal system, and perhaps in other forums
    such as international claims tribunals. We would
    certainly consider this requirement in an appropriate
    case.
    
    Id. at 733
    n.21 (citations omitted). Four justices have embraced
    exhaustion more definitively—without provoking any
    disagreement. See Jesner v. Arab Bank, PLC, 
    138 S. Ct. 1386
    ,
    1430–31 (2018) (Sotomayor, J., dissenting); Kiobel v. Royal
    Dutch Petroleum Co., 
    569 U.S. 108
    , 133 (2013) (Breyer, J.,
    13
    concurring in the judgment). The Ninth Circuit has held that
    exhaustion is required in ATS cases if local remedies are
    adequate. See Sarei v. Rio Tinto, PLC, 
    550 F.3d 822
    , 828–32
    (9th Cir. 2008) (en banc) (plurality opinion); 
    id. at 833–37
    (Bea, J., concurring); 
    id. at 840–41
    (Kleinfeld, J., concurring).
    Private defendants also may seek comity-based abstention.
    For example, Mujica v. AirScan, Inc., 
    771 F.3d 580
    (9th Cir.
    2014), involved ATS and state-law claims against defendants
    alleged to have abetted the bombing of a Colombian village by
    the Colombian government. See 
    id. at 584.
    After dismissing
    the ATS claims as impermissibly extraterritorial, the Ninth
    Circuit dismissed the state-law claims “based on the doctrine
    of international comity.” 
    Id. at 596–97.
    As the court explained,
    “[i]nternational comity is a doctrine of prudential abstention,
    one that ‘counsels voluntary forbearance when a sovereign
    which has a legitimate claim to jurisdiction concludes that a
    second sovereign also has a legitimate claim to jurisdiction
    under principles of international law.’” 
    Id. at 598
    (citation
    omitted). Likewise, in Ungaro-Benages v. Dresdner Bank AG,
    
    379 F.3d 1227
    (11th Cir. 2004), the Eleventh Circuit dismissed
    on comity-based abstention grounds a claim by an American
    citizen that two German banks, during the 1930s and early
    1940s, had stolen her family property “through the Nazi
    Regime’s program of ‘Aryanization.’” 
    Id. at 1229,
    1237–40.
    Comity interests are heightened where, as here, the claims
    “arise from events of historical and political significance” to
    the foreign sovereign. Republic of Philippines v. Pimentel, 
    553 U.S. 851
    , 866 (2008).          Like exhaustion, comity-based
    abstention presupposes an adequate forum in the offending
    country. See, e.g., 
    Mujica, 771 F.3d at 603
    –04. But Philipp
    and Simon II rejected exhaustion and abstention defenses as
    categorically unavailable in FSIA cases, not on the narrower
    ground that fora in Germany and Hungary were inadequate.
    14
    The Philipp panel reasoned that because the FSIA
    comprehensively sets forth immunity defenses, Republic of
    Argentina v. NML Capital, Ltd., 
    573 U.S. 134
    , 141–42 (2014),
    but does not expressly provide for exhaustion or abstention
    defenses, it must implicitly have foreclosed those 
    defenses. 894 F.3d at 415
    –16. But foreign sovereign immunity—which
    eliminates subject-matter jurisdiction—is distinct from non-
    jurisdictional defenses such as exhaustion and abstention. As
    shown above, these defenses are available to private defendants
    no less than to foreign sovereigns. In that critical respect, the
    defenses are less akin to immunity than to generally applicable,
    judge-made defenses such as forum non conveniens, the act-of-
    state doctrine, and the political-question doctrine—none of
    which is mentioned in the text of the FSIA, but all of which
    survived its enactment. See, e.g., Agudas Chasidei Chabad v.
    Russian Federation, 
    528 F.3d 934
    , 951 (D.C. Cir. 2008);
    Hwang Geum Joo v. Japan, 
    413 F.3d 45
    , 48 (D.C. Cir. 2005).
    Exhaustion and abstention are also different from arbitration.
    So, the inclusion of an arbitration requirement in the terrorism
    exception, 28 U.S.C. § 1605A(a)(2)(A)(iii); see 
    Philipp, 894 F.3d at 415
    , says nothing about exhaustion or abstention.
    Simon II further reasoned that exhaustion “lacks any
    pedigree in domestic or international common 
    law.” 911 F.3d at 1181
    . But international law requires an individual “claiming
    to be a victim of a human rights violation” to “exhaust[ ]
    available remedies under the domestic law of the accused state”
    before another state may espouse his claim. See Third
    Restatement § 703 cmt. d. Likewise, individual victims
    generally have international remedies only as provided by
    agreement, see 
    id. cmt. c,
    and international agreements “also
    generally require that the individual first exhaust domestic
    remedies,” 
    id. cmt. d.
    To be sure, the Third Restatement does
    not expressly apply the same rule to instances where the victim
    seeks redress in the courts of a foreign sovereign. See Philipp,
    
    15 894 F.3d at 416
    . But the drafters would have had no occasion
    to address exhaustion in that specific circumstance, given the
    overwhelming likelihood that, under international standards,
    sovereign immunity would have barred the claims. See Third
    Restatement §§ 451–56. Moreover, the logic for requiring
    exhaustion is even stronger in the context of actions filed in
    domestic courts; “if exhaustion is considered essential to the
    smooth operation of international tribunals whose jurisdiction
    is established only through explicit consent from other
    sovereigns, then it is all the more significant in the absence of
    such explicit consent to jurisdiction.” 
    Sarei, 550 F.3d at 830
    (plurality opinion). As for domestic exhaustion rules, federal
    courts have crafted them for over a century, out of respect for
    other sovereigns such as states or Indian tribes. See, e.g., Iowa
    Mut. Ins. Co. v. LaPlante, 
    480 U.S. 9
    , 14–15 (1987); Ex parte
    Royall, 
    117 U.S. 241
    , 251 (1886).
    Finally, Simon II reasoned that exhaustion might, by
    operation of res judicata, bar plaintiffs from ever bringing
    claims in the United 
    States. 911 F.3d at 1180
    . That is not
    necessarily true, at least if the plaintiff reserves the right to
    litigate international claims in the United States after pursuing
    domestic tort claims elsewhere. Cf. England v. La. State Bd. of
    Med. Exam’rs, 
    375 U.S. 411
    , 413–19 (1964). In any event,
    there is nothing anomalous with exhaustion triggering
    preclusion. See, e.g., Iowa 
    Mut., 480 U.S. at 19
    . Moreover,
    the same objection would apply to exhaustion under the ATS,
    yet the Ninth Circuit still adopted it. Comity-based abstention
    does prevent a plaintiff from litigating in a United States forum,
    yet the courts have applied it to cases involving private
    defendants facing foreign-centered human-rights claims. The
    FSIA makes the same defenses also available to foreign
    sovereigns.
    16
    B
    Philipp and Simon II warrant rehearing en banc for several
    reasons. First, they create a circuit split on a sensitive foreign-
    policy question. The Seventh Circuit has required Hungarian
    Holocaust survivors to exhaust remedies in Hungary before
    seeking to litigate under the FSIA’s expropriation exception.
    Fischer v. Magyar Államvasutak Zrt., 
    777 F.3d 847
    , 856–66
    (7th Cir. 2015); 
    Abelesz, 692 F.3d at 678
    –85. After describing
    the nearly existential threat of a $75 billion lawsuit, the Seventh
    Circuit held that “Hungary, a modern republic and member of
    the European Union, deserves a chance to address these
    claims.” 
    Abelesz, 692 F.3d at 682
    . The Philipp panel
    acknowledged creating a circuit 
    split. 894 F.3d at 416
    .
    Second, Philipp rejected the position advanced by the
    United States. 
    See 894 F.3d at 416
    . In Simon II, the United
    States argued at length that “[d]ismissal on international comity
    grounds” was consistent with the FSIA and “can play a critical
    role in ensuring that litigation in U.S. courts does not conflict
    with or cause harm to the foreign policy of the United States.”
    Br. for Amicus Curiae United States at 14–15, Simon v.
    Republic of Hungary (No. 17-7146); see also 
    id. at 14–24.
    The
    United States again took the same position in supporting
    rehearing en banc in Philipp. Br. for United States as Amicus
    Curiae in Support of Rehearing En Banc at 3–14. Given the
    Executive Branch’s “vast share of responsibility for the
    conduct of our foreign relations,” Am. Ins. Ass’n v. Garamendi,
    
    539 U.S. 396
    , 414 (2003) (quotation marks omitted), we should
    consider its views on this issue with special care.
    Third, by eliminating various defenses, these decisions
    heighten concern about Simon I. Two important defenses—
    exhaustion and abstention—are now foreclosed. And if it was
    an abuse of discretion to dismiss on forum non conveniens
    17
    grounds the foreign-cubed claims in Simon II, 
    see 911 F.3d at 1182
    , then few of these human-rights cases will qualify for that
    defense. Other possible doctrines for limiting the expropriation
    exception, see 
    Altmann, 541 U.S. at 713
    (Breyer, J.,
    concurring), are also unlikely to have much effect: Personal
    jurisdiction requirements do not apply to foreign sovereigns.
    Price v. Socialist People’s Libyan Arab Jamahiriya, 
    294 F.3d 82
    , 96 (D.C. Cir. 2002). Venue is always proper in the District
    of Columbia for actions “brought against a foreign state or
    political subdivision thereof.” 28 U.S.C. § 1391(f)(4). The
    act-of-state doctrine may not apply to Nazi-era claims, see First
    Nat’l City Bank v. Banco Nacional de Cuba, 
    406 U.S. 759
    , 764
    (1972) (plurality opinion); Bernstein v. N.V. Nederlandsche-
    Amerikaansche Stoomvaart-Maatschappij, 
    210 F.2d 375
    (2d
    Cir. 1954) (per curiam), and generally does not apply to
    expropriation claims arising after January 1, 1959, see 22
    U.S.C. § 2370(e)(2). Statutes of limitation may bar some
    claims arising from World War II, despite inevitable tolling or
    concealment arguments, but they will have no effect on claims
    arising from recent alleged human-rights abuses. Finally,
    Simon I itself held that the political-question doctrine does not
    bar the claims that it approved. 
    See 812 F.3d at 149
    –51.
    Fourth, these decisions make the FSIA more receptive to
    human-rights litigation than is the ATS. Under Simon I’s broad
    interpretation of the expropriation exception, most modern
    ATS claims could be recast as FSIA ones. And after Philipp,
    recasting has significant advantages. For example, ATS claims
    that a defendant had abetted crimes against humanity by Papua
    New Guinea must be exhausted. See 
    Sarei, 550 F.3d at 824
    (plurality opinion). Yet under Philipp, the same lawsuit would
    face no exhaustion requirement if filed directly against Papua
    New Guinea. ATS claims of abetting atrocities committed by
    a foreign sovereign within its own territory are impermissibly
    extraterritorial. See 
    Kiobel, 569 U.S. at 111
    –12, 124–25. Yet
    18
    under Philipp, the same lawsuits, if filed directly against the
    foreign sovereigns, might survive on the theory that common-
    law tort claims have no territorial limit. Compare 
    Mujica, 771 F.3d at 591
    –96 (dismissing ATS claims as extraterritorial),
    with 
    id. at 596–615
    (dismissing state-law claims only on
    comity grounds). Such results are perverse, for FSIA actions
    against foreign sovereigns raise even greater foreign-policy
    concerns than do ATS actions against private parties who may
    abet them.
    Finally, the mismatch noted above between jurisdictional
    and merits issues under Simon I makes exhaustion even more
    important. If the federal courts must resolve the scope of a
    genocide in order to decide garden-variety conversion claims,
    then so much the better if the foreign sovereign can perhaps
    resolve the claims by addressing only the merits.
    * * * *
    For these reasons, I would grant rehearing en banc to
    reconsider the approach to the FSIA’s expropriation exception
    set forth in Simon I, Philipp, and Simon II.