Matthew Grace v. DC ( 2017 )


Menu:
  •  United States Court of Appeals
    FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA CIRCUIT
    Argued September 20, 2016               Decided July 25, 2017
    No. 16-7025
    BRIAN WRENN, ET AL.,
    APPELLANTS
    v.
    DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA, ET AL.,
    APPELLEES
    Appeal from the United States District Court
    for the District of Columbia
    (No. 1:15-cv-00162)
    Alan Gura argued the cause and filed the briefs for
    appellants.
    Herbert W. Titus, Robert J. Olson, William J. Olson,
    Jeremiah L. Morgan, and John S. Miles were on the brief for
    amici curiae Gun Owners of America, Inc., et al. in support of
    appellants.
    Holly M. Johnson, Assistant Attorney General, Office of
    the Attorney General for the District of Columbia, argued the
    cause for appellees. With her on the brief were Karl A. Racine,
    Attorney General, Todd S. Kim, Solicitor General, and Loren
    2
    L. AliKhan, Deputy Solicitor General. Richard S. Love,
    Assistant Attorney General, entered an appearance.
    Adam K. Levin and Jonathan E. Lowy were on the brief for
    amicus curiae The Brady Center to Prevent Gun Violence in
    support of appellees District of Columbia and Cathy L. Lanier.
    Brian E. Frosh, Attorney General, Office of the Attorney
    General for the State of Maryland, Joshua N. Auerbach,
    Assistant Attorney General, Maura Healey, Attorney General,
    Office of the Attorney General for the Commonwealth of
    Massachusetts, Eric T. Schneiderman, Attorney General,
    Office of the Attorney General for the State of New York, Ellen
    F. Rosenblum, Attorney General, Office of the Attorney
    General for the State of Oregon, Robert W. Ferguson, Attorney
    General, Office of the Attorney General for the State of
    Washington, Kamala D. Harris, Attorney General, Office of
    the Attorney General for the State of California, George
    Jepsen, Attorney General, Office of the Attorney General for
    the State of Connecticut, Douglas S. Chin, Attorney General,
    Office of the Attorney General for the State of Hawaii, Lisa
    Madigan, Attorney General, Office of the Attorney General for
    the State of Illinois, and Tom Miller, Attorney General, Office
    of the Attorney General for the State of Iowa, were on the brief
    for amici curiae States of Maryland, California, Connecticut,
    Hawaii, Illinois, Iowa, Massachusetts, New York, Oregon, and
    Washington in support of appellees.
    Paul R.Q. Wolfson and Walter A. Smith, Jr. were on the
    brief for amici curiae DC Appleseed Center for Law & Justice,
    et al. in support of defendants-appellees.
    Deepak Gupta was on the brief for amicus curiae
    Everytown For Gun Safety in support of appellees.
    3
    No. 16-7067
    MATTHEW GRACE AND PINK PISTOLS,
    APPELLEES
    v.
    DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA AND PETER NEWSHAM, IN HIS
    OFFICIAL CAPACITY AS CHIEF OF POLICE FOR THE
    METROPOLITAN POLICE DEPARTMENT,
    APPELLANTS
    Appeal from the United States District Court
    for the District of Columbia
    (No. 1:15-cv-02234)
    Loren L. AliKhan, Deputy Solicitor General, Office of the
    Attorney General for the District of Columbia, argued the cause
    for appellants. With her on the briefs were Karl A. Racine,
    Attorney General, Todd S. Kim, Solicitor General, and Holly
    M. Johnson, Assistant Attorney General.
    Brian E. Frosh, Attorney General, Office of the Attorney
    General for the State of Maryland, Joshua N. Auerbach,
    Assistant Attorney General, Maura Healey, Attorney General,
    Office of the Attorney General for the Commonwealth of
    Massachusetts, Eric T. Schneiderman, Attorney General,
    Office of the Attorney General for the State of New York, Ellen
    F. Rosenblum, Attorney General, Office of the Attorney
    General for the State of Oregon, Robert W. Ferguson, Attorney
    General, Office of the Attorney General for the State of
    Washington, Kamala D. Harris, Attorney General, Office of
    4
    the Attorney General for the State of California, George
    Jepsen, Attorney General, Office of the Attorney General for
    the State of Connecticut, Douglas S. Chin, Attorney General,
    Office of the Attorney General for the State of Hawaii, Lisa
    Madigan, Attorney General, Office of the Attorney General for
    the State of Illinois, and Tom Miller, Attorney General, Office
    of the Attorney General for the State of Iowa, were on the brief
    for Maryland, California, Connecticut, Hawaii, Illinois, Iowa,
    Massachusetts, New York, Oregon, and Washington in support
    of appellants.
    Paul R.Q. Wolfson and Walter A. Smith, Jr. were on the
    brief for amici curiae DC Appleseed Center for Law & Justice,
    et al. in support of defendants-appellants.
    Deepak Gupta was on the brief for amicus curiae
    Everytown for Gun Safety in support of defendants-appellants.
    Adam K. Levin and Jonathan Lowy were on the brief for
    amicus curiae Brady Center to Prevent Gun Violence in
    support of appellants District of Columbia and Cathy L. Lanier.
    David H. Thompson argued the cause for appellees. With
    him on the brief was Charles J. Cooper, Howard C. Nielson,
    Jr., Peter A. Patterson, and John D. Ohlendorf.
    Mark Brnovich, Attorney General, Office of the Attorney
    General for the State of Arizona, John R. Lopez, IV, Solicitor
    General, Keith Miller, Assistant Solicitor General, Alan
    Wilson, Attorney General, Office of the Attorney General for
    the State of South Carolina, Marty J. Jackley, Attorney
    General, Office of the Attorney General for the State of South
    Dakota, Ken Paxton, Attorney General, Office of the Attorney
    General for the State of Texas, Sean D. Reyes, Attorney
    General, Office of the Attorney General for the State of Utah,
    5
    Patrick Morrisey, Attorney General, Office of the Attorney
    General for the State of West Virginia, Brad D. Schimel,
    Attorney General, Office of the Attorney General for the State
    of Wisconsin, Peter K. Michael, Attorney General, Office of
    the Attorney General for the State of Wyoming, Luther
    Strange, Attorney General, Office of the Attorney General for
    the State of Alabama, Leslie Rutledge, Attorney General,
    Office of the Attorney General for the State of Arkansas,
    Gregory F. Zoeller, Attorney General, Office of the Attorney
    General for the State of Indiana, Chris Koster, Attorney
    General, Office of the Attorney General for the State of
    Missouri, Timothy C. Fox, Attorney General, Office of the
    Attorney General for the State of Montana, Adam Paul Laxalt,
    Attorney General, Office of the Attorney General for the State
    of Nevada, Michael DeWine, Attorney General, Office of the
    Attorney General for the State of Ohio, and E. Scott Pruitt,
    Attorney General, Office of the Attorney General for the State
    of Oklahoma were on the brief for Arizona, Alabama,
    Arkansas, Indiana, Missouri, Montana, Nevada, Ohio,
    Oklahoma, South Carolina, South Dakota, Texas, Utah, West
    Virginia, Wisconsin, and Wyoming in support of plaintiffs-
    appellees.
    Dan M. Peterson and C.D. Michel were on the brief for
    amici curiae Western States Sheriffs’ Association, et al. in
    support of plaintiffs-appellees.
    Paul D. Clement, Erin E. Murphy, and Christopher G.
    Michel were on the brief for amicus curiae National Rifle
    Association of America, Inc. in support of plaintiffs-appellees.
    Herbert W. Titus, Robert J. Olson, William J. Olson,
    Jeremiah L. Morgan, and John S. Miles were on the brief for
    amicus curiae Gun Owners of America, Inc., et al. in support
    of plaintiffs-appellees.
    6
    Opinion for the Court filed by Circuit Judge GRIFFITH.
    Dissenting opinion filed by Circuit Judge HENDERSON.
    Before: HENDERSON and GRIFFITH, Circuit Judges, and
    WILLIAMS, Senior Circuit Judge.
    GRIFFITH, Circuit Judge: Constitutional challenges to gun
    laws create peculiar puzzles for courts. In other areas, after all,
    a law’s validity might turn on the value of its goals and the
    efficiency of its means. But gun laws almost always aim at the
    most compelling goal—saving lives—while evidence of their
    effects is almost always deeply contested. On top of that, the
    Supreme Court has offered little guidance. Its “first in-depth
    examination of the Second Amendment” is younger than the
    first iPhone. District of Columbia v. Heller (Heller I), 
    554 U.S. 570
    , 634 (2008). And by its own admission, that first treatment
    manages to be mute on how to review gun laws in a range of
    other cases. See 
    id. at 634
    . But listening closely to Heller I
    reveals this much at least: the Second Amendment erects some
    absolute barriers that no gun law may breach. This lesson will
    prove crucial as we consider the challenges presented in these
    cases to the District of Columbia’s limits on carrying guns in
    public.
    I
    These cases involve the District’s third major attempt in
    forty years at managing what the D.C. Council sees as the
    tension between public safety and the Second Amendment. In
    1976, the District banned all handgun possession. 
    D.C. Code §§ 7-2502.01
    (a), 7-2502.02(a)(4) (2001). When that ban was
    struck down in Heller I, the Council followed it with a ban on
    carrying. 
    Id.
     § 22-4504 (2009). And when that was struck
    down in Palmer v. District of Columbia, 
    59 F. Supp. 3d 173
    7
    (D.D.C. 2014), the Council responded with the law challenged
    here, which confines carrying a handgun in public to those with
    a special need for self-defense.
    The challenged D.C. Code provisions direct the District’s
    police chief to promulgate regulations limiting licenses for the
    concealed carry of handguns (the only sort of carrying the Code
    allows) to those showing a “good reason to fear injury to [their]
    person or property” or “any other proper reason for carrying a
    pistol.” 
    Id.
     § 22-4506(a)-(b).1 The Code also limits what the
    police chief may count as satisfying these two criteria, in the
    course of promulgating regulations and issuing licenses.
    To receive a license based on the first prong—a “good
    reason to fear injury”—applicants must show a “special need
    for self-protection distinguishable from the general community
    as supported by evidence of specific threats or previous attacks
    that demonstrate a special danger to the applicant’s life.” Id.
    § 7-2509.11(1)(A). The police chief’s regulations further limit
    licenses granted on this basis to those who “allege, in writing,
    serious threats of death or serious bodily harm, any attacks on
    [their] person, or any theft of property from [their] person.”
    D.C. Mun. Regs. tit. 24 § 2333.2-3.
    For those seeking to establish some “other proper reason
    for carrying,” the D.C. Code provides that an applicant’s need
    to carry around cash or valuables as part of her job is sufficient.
    
    D.C. Code § 7-2509.11
    (1)(B). Two regulations implementing
    this criterion also specify that living or working “in a high
    crime area shall not by itself establish a good reason” to carry,
    1
    The District currently allows some very limited carrying even
    without a permit. For example, owners may carry registered
    handguns for lawful recreational purposes and within their homes
    and places of business. 
    D.C. Code § 22-4504.01
    .
    8
    D.C. Mun. Regs. tit. 24 § 2333.4 (emphasis added), but that
    having a close relative who is unable to meet his own special
    need for self-defense does. Id. § 2334.1.
    We will refer to this ensemble of Code provisions and
    police regulations simply as the “good-reason” law or
    regulation. The D.C. Council thought this scheme justified in
    light of studies suggesting that expansive right-to-carry laws
    are associated with higher rates of crime and injury to
    innocents. The Council also cited the District’s status as an
    urban area teeming with officials, diplomats, and major
    landmarks.
    Before us are conflicting rulings in two cases before
    different district judges. Both cases involve plaintiffs denied a
    concealed-carry license solely for failing to show a special
    need for self-defense. Bringing the first case are Brian Wrenn,
    the Second Amendment Foundation, Inc., and two of its other
    members. The second case features Matthew Grace and the
    Pink Pistols, an organization in which Grace and other
    members champion the right of sexual minorities to carry guns
    for self-defense.
    In each case, the plaintiffs sought a preliminary injunction
    barring the District from enforcing the good-reason regulation.
    In March 2016, a district judge denied the Wrenn plaintiffs’
    motion. Two months later, another district judge granted the
    Grace plaintiffs a preliminary injunction barring the District
    from enforcing the good-reason law against anyone. We
    combine the two appeals, over which we have jurisdiction
    under 
    28 U.S.C. § 1292
    (a)(1), and must consider all legal
    issues de novo, see Abdullah v. Obama, 
    753 F.3d 193
    , 197-98
    (D.C. Cir. 2014).
    9
    II
    We begin by asking if Grace and Wrenn have met their
    burden to show their Second Amendment challenges are likely
    to prevail. That question has several components in this case.
    In many areas of constitutional law, regulations that impose on
    rights are subject to one of three tests that are more or less
    stringent depending on the right and the burden at stake. So-
    called rational-basis review requires the challenged law to bear
    a rational link to a legitimate public interest. Intermediate
    scrutiny looks for a substantial link to an important interest.
    And strict scrutiny demands that a law be narrowly tailored to
    a compelling public interest. See generally Richard H. Fallon,
    Jr., Strict Judicial Scrutiny, 54 U.C.L.A. L. Rev. 1267 (2007).
    Whether we need that three-tiered framework here is one
    issue we will address. Grace and Wrenn hope we can consider
    their challenge without bothering to decide which level of
    scrutiny to apply to the District’s regulation. In fact, the District
    shares that hope. For their part, Grace and Wrenn argue that we
    should deem the good-reason regulation invalid without
    applying tiers of scrutiny because this regulation is analogous
    to the “total ban” that the Supreme Court struck down in Heller
    I without pausing to weigh its benefits. The District, by
    contrast, thinks the law warrants no particular scrutiny because
    it does not burden protected rights at all.
    The parties split on what we should do if we ultimately
    decide to apply tiers of scrutiny. Under our precedent, if we
    apply tiers of scrutiny at all, the proper level to apply would
    turn on whether a gun law imposes “substantial[ly]” on the
    Second Amendment’s “core.” Heller v. District of Columbia
    (Heller II), 
    670 F.3d 1244
    , 1257 (D.C. Cir. 2011); see also 
    id. at 1253, 1256-57
    . The plaintiffs say the good-reason law does
    so, thus inviting strict scrutiny. The District would have us
    10
    apply intermediate scrutiny on the ground that the law’s burden
    is not substantial or falls outside the Amendment’s core.
    Whichever path we take, we must determine if the good-
    reason law impinges on a “core” Second Amendment right. So
    we begin there. The District argues that the Amendment’s core
    does not cover public carrying at all, or that it does not protect
    carrying in densely populated areas like D.C., or that it does
    not extend to carrying unless there is a special need for self-
    defense. We take these three arguments in turn before
    considering the analysis of other circuit courts. Having thus
    judged whether the regulation impinges on core Second
    Amendment conduct, we will turn in Part III to determining
    and applying the proper form of review for these cases.
    A
    The “core” or “central component” of the Second
    Amendment right to keep and bear arms protects “individual
    self-defense,” McDonald v. City of Chicago, 
    561 U.S. 742
    ,
    767-78 (2010) (internal quotation marks omitted), by “law-
    abiding, responsible citizens,” Heller I, 
    554 U.S. at
    635—
    though subject to certain “longstanding” regulations that limit
    the Amendment’s scope, such as bans on possession “by felons
    and the mentally ill,” 
    id.
     No one doubts that under Heller I this
    core protection covers the right of a law-abiding citizen to keep
    in the home common firearms for self-defense.
    Our first question is whether the Amendment’s “core”
    extends to publicly carrying guns for self-defense. The District
    argues that it does not, citing Heller I’s observation that “the
    need for defense of self, family, and property is most acute” in
    the home. 
    Id. at 628
    . But the fact that the need for self-defense
    is most pressing in the home doesn’t mean that self-defense at
    home is the only right at the Amendment’s core. After all, the
    11
    Amendment’s “core lawful purpose” is self-defense, 
    id. at 630
    ,
    and the need for that might arise beyond as well as within the
    home. Moreover, the Amendment’s text protects the right to
    “bear” as well as “keep” arms. For both reasons, it’s more
    natural to view the Amendment’s core as including a law-
    abiding citizen’s right to carry common firearms for self-
    defense beyond the home (subject again to relevant
    “longstanding” regulations like bans on carrying “in sensitive
    places”). 
    Id. at 626
    .
    This reading finds support in parts of Heller I that speak
    louder than the Court’s aside about where the need for guns is
    “most acute.” That remark appears when Heller I turns to the
    particular ban on possession at issue there. By then the Court
    has spent over fifty pages giving independent and seemingly
    equal treatments to the right to “keep” and to “bear,” first
    defining those “phrases” and then teasing out their
    implications. See 
    id. at 570-628
    . In that long preliminary
    analysis, the Court elaborates that to “bear” means to “‘wear,
    bear, or carry . . . upon the person or in the clothing or in a
    pocket, for the purpose . . . of being armed and ready for
    offensive or defensive action in a case of conflict with another
    person.’” 
    Id. at 584
     (quoting Muscarello v. United States, 
    524 U.S. 125
    , 143 (1998) (Ginsburg, J., dissenting)). That
    definition shows that the Amendment’s core must span, in the
    Court’s own words, the “right to possess and carry weapons in
    case of confrontation.” Id. at 592 (emphasis added).
    This first gloss on the Amendment’s text and Heller I’s
    reasoning is reinforced by the history that Heller I deems
    essential for tracing the “pre-existing right” embodied by the
    Amendment. Id. at 592. Heller I pores over early sources to
    show that while preventing Congress from eliminating state
    militias was the “purpose that prompted the [Amendment’s]
    codification,” that purpose did not limit the right’s substance,
    12
    which encompassed the personal right to armed self-defense.
    Id. at 599-600. Crucially, Heller I winds its way to this
    conclusion through a parade of early English, Founding-era,
    antebellum, and late-nineteenth century cases and
    commentaries. Those same sources attest that the Second
    Amendment squarely covers carrying beyond the home for
    self-defense.
    Most of the relevant nineteenth-century cases, for
    example, assume the importance of carrying as well as
    possessing. Each puts another crack in the District’s argument
    that carrying was peripheral to the right protected by the
    Amendment. See Heller I, 
    554 U.S. at 611-14
    , 629 (citing State
    v. Reid, 
    1 Ala. 612
    , 616-17 (1840) (allowing restrictions on the
    “manner of bearing arms” but not limits on carrying so severe
    “as to render [arms] wholly useless for the purpose of
    defence”); Nunn v. State, 
    1 Ga. 243
    , 251 (1846) (invalidating a
    ban on carrying insofar as it prohibited “bearing arms openly”);
    State v. Chandler, 
    5 La.Ann. 489
     (1850) (observing that the
    Amendment shields a right to open carry); Johnson v.
    Tompkins, 
    13 F. Cas. 840
    , 852 (C.C. Pa. 1833) (finding in the
    Second Amendment and a state analogue “a right to carry arms
    in defence of [one’s] property or person, and to use them, if . . .
    assailed with such force, numbers, or violence as made it
    necessary for [one’s] protection or safety”); Andrews v. State,
    
    50 Tenn. 165
    , 187 (1871) (invalidating a ban on carrying
    pistols “publicly or privately, without regard to time or place,
    or circumstances”)); see also Peruta v. Cty. of San Diego, 
    742 F.3d 1144
    , 1174 (9th Cir. 2014), vacated, 
    781 F.3d 1155
    , 1156-
    63 (9th Cir. 2015) (citing Bliss v. Commonwealth, 
    12 Ky. (2 Litt.) 90
    , 93 (1822) (striking down a prohibition on “wearing
    concealed arms”); Cockrum v. State, 
    24 Tex. 394
    , 403 (1859)
    (allowing bans on the carrying of “exceeding[ly] destructive
    weapon[s],” but not total bans)). Indeed, the few nineteenth-
    century cases that upheld onerous limits on carrying against
    13
    challenges under the Second Amendment or close analogues
    are sapped of authority by Heller I because each of them
    assumed that the Amendment was only about militias and not
    personal self-defense. So Heller I rejects their crucial premise.
    “And with these cases off the table, the remaining cases speak
    with one voice” on the Amendment’s coverage of carrying as
    well as keeping arms. Peruta, 742 F.3d at 1174. Under Heller
    I’s treatment of these and earlier cases and commentaries,
    history matters, and here it favors the plaintiffs.
    The District retorts that self-defense in public must fall
    outside the Amendment’s core protections because the
    Amendment was codified in order to keep Congress from
    eliminating state militias, a purpose that doesn’t require
    allowing people to carry guns in times of peace. But again, it
    was Heller I’s central holding that the reason for the
    Amendment’s passage did not narrow the sweep of its
    protections. See 
    554 U.S. at 598-600
    . Whatever motivated the
    Amendment, at its core was the right to self-defense. 
    Id. at 630
    .
    Thus, the Amendment’s core generally covers carrying in
    public for self-defense.
    We say “generally” because, as noted, the Supreme Court
    has taught in Heller I that legal regulations of possession or
    carrying that are “longstanding”—including bans on
    possession by felons or bans on carrying near sensitive sites—
    reflect limits to the preexisting right protected by the
    Amendment. 
    Id. at 626, 635
    . The District contends that this
    doctrine rescues the good-reason law. In the District’s telling,
    Anglo-American history reveals two “longstanding” practices
    that so shrank the right later enshrined by the Amendment as to
    leave good-reason laws beyond its reach: so-called
    Northampton laws and surety laws.
    14
    B
    Whatever the right to carry might cover, the District
    contends, it does not protect carrying in densely populated or
    urban areas like Washington, D.C. That is because the English
    right to bear arms had for centuries been fenced in by the
    Statute of Northampton, a law that banned carrying firearms in
    crowded areas. Indeed, Northampton-like laws had migrated to
    some colonies by the late 1700s, and then to several states in
    the mid-to-late 1800s. Thus, the District argues, the preexisting
    right codified by the Second Amendment did not (or did not at
    its core2) cover carrying in densely populated areas like D.C.
    That argument pulls us—and both parties and several
    scholars—into dense historical weeds. The original
    Northampton statute took effect in 1328. Its language will
    faintly remind Anglophiles of studying Canterbury Tales—in
    the original. The rest of us may rest assured that the details of
    the text will matter less here than they did in English Lit:
    [I]t is enacted, that no man . . . of what condition
    soever he be, except the king’s servants in his
    presence, and his ministers . . . and such as be in
    their company assisting them, and also [upon a
    cry made for arms to keep the peace, and the
    same in such places where such acts happen,] be
    so hardy to come before the King’s justices, or
    other of the King’s ministers doing their office,
    with force and arms, nor bring no force in affray
    of the peace, nor to go nor ride armed by night
    nor by day, in fairs, markets, nor in the presence
    2
    It is not clear whether the District believes Northampton laws
    show that carrying in densely populated areas falls outside the
    Amendment’s protection altogether, or merely outside its core.
    15
    of the justices or other ministers, nor in no part
    elsewhere, upon pain to forfeit their armour to
    the King, and their bodies to prison at the King’s
    pleasure.
    S.A. 36. The District argues that by forbidding all but the king’s
    servants and ministers to bring “force in affray of the peace” or
    to “go [or] ride armed by night or by day” in “fairs” or
    “markets,” this statute banned carrying in densely populated
    areas. So carrying in urban areas like D.C., the argument goes,
    falls beyond the Amendment’s perimeter or at least its core.
    The plaintiffs answer that the Supreme Court neutralized
    this argument in Heller I by citing Blackstone’s understanding
    that Northampton banned only the carrying of “dangerous and
    unusual weapons.” 
    554 U.S. at 627
     (internal quotation marks
    omitted); see also 4 William Blackstone, Commentaries on the
    Laws of England *149. Plaintiffs and amici also point to an
    English case suggesting that by the 1600s, Northampton was
    understood to ban only the wielding of arms with evil intent or
    in such a way as “to terrify the King’s subjects.” Sir John
    Knight’s Case, 87 Eng. Rep. 75, 76 (K.B. 1686). The District
    offers its replies, to which the plaintiffs issue sur-replies, and
    on and on, until for every point there is an equal and opposite
    counterpoint.
    Happily, though, the state of the law in Chaucer’s
    England—or for that matter Shakespeare’s or Cromwell’s—is
    not decisive here. Heller I holds that by the time of the
    Founding, the “preexisting right” enshrined by the Amendment
    had ripened to include carrying more broadly than the District
    contends based on its reading of the 14th-century statute.
    For one thing, the history showcased in Heller I
    contradicts the main scholar whose work the District cites for
    16
    the idea that Northampton banned all carrying in crowded areas
    (as opposed to carrying dangerous arms or carrying so as to
    terrify). On that scholar’s view, Northampton so narrowed the
    English right embodied by the Amendment that “individual
    self-defense beyond the home deserves only minimalist
    protection or categorical exclusion.” Patrick J. Charles, The
    Faces of the Second Amendment Outside the Home: History
    Versus Ahistorical Standards of Review, 
    60 Clev. St. L. Rev. 1
    ,
    43 (2012). This view runs headlong into the history cited by the
    Supreme Court to show that the English “right secured in 1689
    . . . was by the time of the founding understood to be an
    individual right protecting against both public and private
    violence,” Heller I, 
    554 U.S. at 594
    , so that the resulting
    Amendment guarantees the right to “possess and carry
    weapons in case of confrontation,” 
    id. at 592
     (emphasis added).
    Early commentators seem to confirm that whatever
    Northampton banned on the shores of England or colonial
    America, the right to bear arms by the time of the Founding
    was thought to protect carrying for self-defense generally.
    Thus, Heller I cites the view of James Wilson—early
    commentator, virtual coauthor of the Constitution, and member
    of the Supreme Court’s first cohort—that Founding-era
    Northampton laws banned only the carrying of “dangerous and
    unusual weapons, in such a manner, as will naturally diffuse a
    terrour among the people.” James Wilson, The Works of the
    Honourable James Wilson 79 (1804); see also Heller I, 
    554 U.S. at 627
    . Even more explicit (if less prominent) is one early
    commentary’s observation that while
    [r]iding or going armed with dangerous or
    unusual weapons, is a crime against the public
    peace, by terrifying the people of the land . . . it
    should be remembered, that in this country the
    constitution guaranties to all persons the right to
    17
    bear arms; then it can only be a crime to exercise
    this right in such a manner, as to terrify the
    people unnecessarily.
    Charles Humphreys, A Compendium of the Common Law in
    Force in Kentucky 482 (Lexington, Ky., William Gibbes Hunt
    1822); see also 1 William Hawkins, A Treatise of the Pleas of
    the Crown 135, ch. 63, § 4, at 135 (1716) (“[N]o wearing of
    arms is within the meaning of this statute, unless it be
    accompanied with such circumstances as are apt to terrify the
    people.”).
    So in light of Heller I, we can sidestep the historical debate
    on how the first Northampton law might have hindered
    Londoners in the Middle Ages. Common-law rights developed
    over time, and American commentaries spell out what early
    cases imply: the mature right captured by the Amendment was
    not hemmed in by longstanding bans on carrying in densely
    populated areas. Its protections today don’t give out inside the
    Beltway.
    C
    The District argues for one other limit to the Amendment:
    that its core excludes carrying absent special self-defense needs
    because carrying was always cabined by English “surety laws.”
    These laws provided that if Oliver carried a pistol and Thomas
    said he reasonably feared that Oliver would injure him or
    breach the peace, Oliver had to post a bond to be used to cover
    any damage he might do, unless he proved he had reason to fear
    injury to his person or family or property. Grace S.A. 21-22.
    The District cites these laws as early precursors of its good-
    reason law to show that the conduct it blocks lies outside the
    Amendment’s core.
    18
    But surety laws did not deny a responsible person carrying
    rights unless he showed a special need for self-defense. They
    only burdened someone reasonably accused of posing a threat.
    And even he could go on carrying without criminal penalty. He
    simply had to post money that would be forfeited if he breached
    the peace or injured others—a requirement from which he was
    exempt if he needed self-defense. Under surety laws, put
    simply, everyone started out with robust carrying rights. Those
    reasonably accused were then burdened. And only then did
    self-defense needs make a difference, by exempting even the
    accused from that burden. A showing of special need did not
    expand carrying for the responsible; it shrank burdens on
    carrying by the (allegedly) reckless.
    More importantly, even if surety laws had made
    responsible citizens’ freedom to carry turn on their need for
    self-defense, these laws would do little for the District’s case.
    The Supreme Court has denied that indirect or purely civil
    burdens shed much light on the historical right embedded by
    the Amendment. In his Heller I dissent, Justice Breyer cited
    several laws to contradict the majority’s reading of the
    Amendment, but the Court set them aside on the ground that
    “[a]ll of them” involved only “a small fine and forfeiture of the
    weapon (or in a few cases a very brief stay in the local jail)”
    rather than “significant criminal penalties.” Such regulations,
    the Court reasoned, are “akin to modern penalties for minor
    public-safety infractions like speeding or jaywalking,” which
    makes them (in the Court’s view) poor evidence of limits on
    the Amendment’s scope. 
    554 U.S. at 633-34
    .
    Reading the Amendment, applying Heller I’s reasoning,
    and crediting key early sources, we conclude: the individual
    right to carry common firearms beyond the home for self-
    defense—even in densely populated areas, even for those
    19
    lacking special self-defense needs—falls within the core of the
    Second Amendment’s protections.
    D
    Other circuits reviewing good-reason regulations have
    disagreed, holding that burdens on carrying trigger only
    intermediate scrutiny because the right to carry merits less
    protection than the right to possess in Heller I. Each circuit
    court justifying this modest review of good-reason laws has
    relied on an inference from the tolerance in American law for
    certain other carrying regulations. But each of these courts has
    also dispensed with the historical digging that would have
    exposed that inference as faulty—digging that Heller I makes
    essential to locating the Amendment’s edge, or at least its core.
    The hasty inference appears in a Second Circuit opinion
    on New York’s good-reason law, where the court reasons that
    the right to bear must count for less than the right to keep arms
    since the former has been regulated more rigorously.
    Kachalsky v. Cty. of Westchester, 
    701 F.3d 81
    , 94-97 (2d Cir.
    2012). 3 The court cites, for example, Heller I’s approval of
    longstanding bans on carrying near sensitive sites. 701 F.3d at
    94. But such traditional limits don’t prove that the right to bear
    arms is weaker in our tradition since the right to keep arms has
    3
    The Second Circuit also finds that carrying outside the home
    matters less based on analogies to other individual rights. Thus, it
    asks: if our law “[t]reat[s] the home as special” when it comes to
    sexual privacy rights, why not when enforcing the right to use a gun?
    Kachalsky, 701 F.3d at 94. But of course, sex is different. In Judge
    Posner’s wry understatement, “the interest in having sex inside one’s
    home is much greater than the interest in having sex on the sidewalk
    in front of one’s home,” while the need to fend off violence might
    arise on sidewalks and in bedrooms alike. Moore v. Madigan, 
    702 F.3d 933
    , 941 (7th Cir. 2012).
    20
    also been subject to longstanding regulations: Heller I itself
    cites bans on possession by felons. 
    554 U.S. at 626
    .
    Kachalsky also notes that while several nineteenth-century
    courts may have struck down total bans on carrying, three
    upheld bans on bearing concealed or concealable weapons. 701
    F.3d at 90, 94. The Fourth Circuit makes a similar point in
    applying intermediate scrutiny to another good-reason law. See
    Woollard v. Gallagher, 
    712 F.3d 865
    , 876 (4th Cir. 2013)
    (quoting United States v. Masciandaro, 
    638 F.3d 458
    , 470-71
    (4th Cir. 2011) for the proposition that “as we move outside the
    home, firearm rights have always been more limited,” as shown
    by court decisions upholding bans on concealed carry).
    There is, however, an easy way to explain the many cases
    tolerating limits on bearing, despite the parity of keeping and
    bearing in the Amendment’s text, in Heller I’s textual analysis,
    in early commentaries, and in most early cases. The rights to
    keep and to bear, to possess and to carry, are equally important
    inasmuch as regulations on each must leave alternative
    channels for both. See Heller II, 
    670 F.3d at 1262
     (analogizing
    certain gun laws deserving modest review to regulations that
    leave “ample alternative channels” for speech). It’s simply that
    traditional carrying restrictions have generally left ample
    opportunities for bearing arms. To address an example cited by
    the Second Circuit, bans on carrying only in small pockets of
    the outside world (e.g., near “sensitive” sites, Heller I, 
    554 U.S. at 626-27
    ) impose only lightly on most people’s right to “bear
    arms” in public. As Judge Posner writes: “[W]hen a state bans
    guns merely in particular places, such as public schools, a
    person can preserve an undiminished right of self-defense by
    not entering those places . . . .” Moore, 702 F.3d at 940. By
    contrast, a ban on owning or storing guns at home leaves no
    alternative channels for keeping arms.
    21
    The idea that the government must leave ample channels
    for keeping and for carrying arms explains much of the analysis
    in Heller I. It explains why Heller I saw no need to bother with
    “any of the [familiar] standards of scrutiny” in reviewing a ban
    on ownership that left no means of defense by handguns at
    home. 
    554 U.S. at 628
    . It explains why the Court favorably
    treated cases allowing bans on concealed carry only so long as
    open carry was allowed. 4 The Court itself highlighted this
    feature of those cases, see 
    id. at 612-13, 629
    , explicitly
    describing one of them as limiting only the “manner” of
    exercising gun rights, 
    id. at 626
    . The “ample alternative
    channels” principle also explains the Court’s approval of bans
    on some types of guns so long as those most useful for self-
    defense remained accessible. 
    Id. at 627
    . Indeed, this same
    principle makes an appearance in Heller II where we cite
    Professor Eugene Volokh’s suggestion that courts applying the
    Second Amendment borrow from the law of “content neutral
    speech,” which looks askance at “restrictions that impose
    severe burdens (because they don’t leave open ample
    alternative channels)” for speech. 
    670 F.3d at 1262
     (quoting
    Eugene Volokh, Implementing the Right to Keep and Bear
    Arms for Self-Defense: An Analytical Framework and a
    Research Agenda, 56 U.C.L.A. L. Rev. 1443, 1471 (2009)).
    4
    See State v. Chandler, 
    5 La.Ann. 489
    , 489-90 (1850)
    (describing a law against the carrying of concealed weapons as one
    that “interfered with no man’s right to carry arms . . . ‘in full view,’
    which places men upon an equality”); Nunn v. State, 
    1 Ga. 243
    , 251
    (1846) (“[S]o far as the act of 1837 seeks to suppress the practice of
    carrying certain weapons secretly, . . . it is valid, inasmuch as it does
    not deprive the citizen of his natural right of self-defence, or of his
    constitutional right to keep and bear arms. But that so much of it, as
    contains a prohibition against bearing arms openly, is in conflict with
    the Constitution, and void . . . .”).
    22
    These points confirm that the rights to keep and bear arms
    are on equal footing—that the law must leave responsible, law-
    abiding citizens some reasonable means of exercising each.
    The prevalence of, say, bans on carrying near sensitive sites
    would prove that the right to bear arms mattered less only if our
    law would reject equally modest burdens on keeping arms (e.g.,
    bans on storing them on open surfaces at home). Neither the
    Second nor the Fourth Circuit has suggested that it would. So
    each was too quick to infer that our legal tradition demotes the
    right to bear arms relative to its Constitutional twin.
    Finally, the Third Circuit relied on the reasoning of the
    Second and Fourth Circuits for its decision to submit good-
    reason laws to intermediate scrutiny. See Drake v. Filko, 
    724 F.3d 426
    , 430 (3d Cir. 2013). The only other circuit to address
    the issue, the Ninth, reasoned that a good-reason limit on
    concealed carry must be lawful since outright bans on
    concealed carry have been upheld. 5 Relying on this whole-
    includes-its-parts reasoning, the Ninth Circuit expressly
    sidestepped our question of “whether the [Amendment]
    protects some ability to carry firearms in public, such as open
    carry.” Peruta v. Cty. of San Diego, 
    824 F.3d 919
    , 927 (9th Cir.
    2016) (en banc).
    Indeed, all of the circuits settling on a level of scrutiny to
    apply to good-reason laws explicitly declined to use Heller I’s
    historical method to determine how rigorously the Amendment
    5
    We do not agree with the Ninth Circuit that a ban on concealed
    carry can be assessed in isolation from the rest of a jurisdiction’s gun
    regulations. As we’ve noted, text and history and precedent urge that
    the Second Amendment requires governments to leave responsible
    citizens ample means for self-defense at home and outside. So a
    regulation’s validity may turn partly on whether surrounding laws
    leave ample options for keeping and carrying.
    23
    applies beyond the home. 6 Each simply assumed for
    argument’s sake that the Amendment covers some carrying.
    Though meant to be generous to the plaintiffs, by granting a
    premise in their favor, this move ultimately weakened the
    plaintiffs’ case. It excused courts from sifting through sources
    pointing to the equal importance of the right to bear:
    [T]he Second, Third, and Fourth Circuits . . .
    declined to undertake a complete historical
    analysis of the scope and nature of the Second
    Amendment right outside the home. . . . As a
    result, they misapprehend both the nature of the
    Second Amendment right and the implications
    of state laws that prevent the vast majority of
    responsible, law-abiding citizens from carrying
    in public for lawful self-defense purposes. . . .
    [They] failed to comprehend that carrying
    weapons in public for the lawful purpose of self
    defense is a central component of the right to
    bear arms.
    Peruta, 742 F.3d at 1173-75. Indeed, that conclusion is shared
    by the only other circuit that has surveyed the relevant history
    through the lens of Heller I: the Seventh. See Moore, 702 F.3d
    at 935-37 (striking down a more widely applicable carrying
    ban).
    So we do not gainsay our sister circuits’ considered
    judgments—only the assumptions that some of them made for
    6
    Drake v. Filko, 
    724 F.3d 426
    , 431 (3d Cir. 2013) (declining to
    “engag[e] in a round of full-blown historical analysis”); Woollard,
    712 F.3d at 874-76 (eschewing “a definitive ruling” on the
    Amendment’s scope); Kachalsky, 701 F.3d at 91 (deciding not to
    plumb “highly ambiguous history and tradition to determine the
    meaning of the Amendment”).
    24
    argument’s sake—when we conclude that (longstanding
    exceptions aside) carrying beyond the home, even in populated
    areas, even without special need, falls within the Amendment’s
    coverage, indeed within its core.
    III
    Having determined that the good-reason law impinges on
    core Second Amendment conduct, we now consider whether
    we should subject it to the tiers of scrutiny familiar from other
    realms of constitutional law. Grace and Wrenn argue that we
    should strike down the good-reason law without applying any
    such analysis, following the Supreme Court’s approach to a
    “total ban” on gun ownership in Heller I. The District thinks
    the good-reason law is rather more mundane—not a total ban
    on carrying but a mere hurdle for individuals to clear before
    getting to carry. Thus, the District argues, we should apply
    intermediate scrutiny under Heller II.
    We begin by revisiting Heller I to see why total bans are
    always invalid and what makes for a total ban in the first place.
    Doing so will make it hard to believe that the Heller I Court—
    which dispensed with tiers of scrutiny in striking down a ban
    on possession by almost everyone—would have gone easier on
    a law banning possession by everyone but that small minority
    with a special need to possess. Since possession and carrying
    are on par with each other, it will follow that the same
    categorical treatment should apply to the District’s ban on
    carrying by all but the few who prove a special reason to carry.
    Recall that under Heller I, the Second Amendment
    protects an individual right of responsible, law-abiding citizens
    to defend themselves. In particular, then, the right to carry is a
    right held by responsible, law-abiding citizens for self-defense.
    But self-defense against what? The most natural answer is that
    25
    the Amendment enables self-defense at least against the level
    of threat generally faced by those covered by the Amendment:
    responsible and law-abiding citizens. Likewise, “responsible”
    must include those who are no more dangerous with a gun than
    law-abiding citizens generally are. Cf. Heller v. District of
    Columbia (Heller III), 
    801 F.3d 264
    , 280 (D.C. Cir. 2015)
    (faulting a cap on gun registrations for trying to reduce gun
    ownership indiscriminately rather than zero in on likely
    abuses). At a minimum, then, the Second Amendment must
    enable armed self-defense by commonly situated citizens:
    those who possess common levels of need and pose only
    common levels of risk.
    This analysis reflects the most sensible way of spelling out
    Second Amendment rights absent contrary clues in the
    Amendment’s history as understood by Heller I: if the
    Amendment is for law-abiding citizens as a rule, then it must
    secure gun access at least for each typical member of that class.
    Indeed, this reading fits naturally with Heller I’s holding about
    the meaning of “arms”: just as the Amendment requires access
    to weapons “in common use,” 
    id. at 627
     (quoting United States
    v. Miller, 
    307 U.S. 174
    , 179 (1939)), including the “most
    popular” self-defense weapon among citizens today, id. at 629,
    so must the Amendment enable defense under the
    circumstances common among citizens today. The reason for
    both points is the same: the early cases cited in Heller I
    envisioned that law-abiding citizens as a general rule would be
    entitled to have and carry arms for self-defense. So the class of
    arms protected must include guns in common use; and the class
    of citizens who can wield them must include those with
    common levels of competence and responsibility—and need.
    Longstanding regulations aside, then, the Amendment
    shields at least the ability to carry common arms in self-defense
    for citizens who are commonly situated in the ways just
    26
    mentioned. Yet the District’s good-reason law bars most
    people from exercising this right at all. To be sure, the good-
    reason law leaves each D.C. resident some remote chance of
    one day carrying in self-defense, but that isn’t the question. The
    Second Amendment doesn’t secure a right to have some chance
    at self-defense. Again, at a minimum the Amendment’s core
    must protect carrying given the risks and needs typical of law-
    abiding citizens. That is a right that most D.C. residents can
    never exercise, by the law’s very design. In this way, the
    District’s regulation completely prohibits most residents from
    exercising the constitutional right to bear arms as viewed in the
    light cast by history and Heller I.
    And under Heller I, “complete prohibition[s]” of Second
    Amendment rights are always invalid. Id. at 629. It’s
    appropriate to strike down such “total ban[s]” without
    bothering to apply tiers of scrutiny because no such analysis
    could ever sanction obliterations of an enumerated
    constitutional right. Id. With this categorical approach to such
    bans, Heller I ensured that judicial tests for implementing gun
    rights would not be misused to swallow those rights whole.
    Heller I essentially held that the right to keep and bear arms
    must mean at an absolute minimum the right to own a gun, so
    any acceptable standard of review would have to accommodate
    that fact. By declining to apply tiers of scrutiny to a total ban
    on ownership, Heller I closed off the possibility that courts
    would erroneously find some benefits weighty enough to
    justify other effective bans on the right to keep common arms.
    We would flout this lesson of Heller I if we proceeded as if
    some benefits could justify laws that necessarily destroy the
    ordinarily situated citizen’s right to bear common arms—a
    right also guaranteed by the Amendment, on the most natural
    reading of Heller I.
    27
    Of course, the good-reason law isn’t a “total ban” for the
    D.C. population as a whole of the right to bear common arms
    under common circumstances. After all, it allows some D.C.
    residents—those with a special need—to defend against threats
    both common to everyone and specific to themselves. But the
    ban on ownership struck down in Heller I also made “minor
    exceptions” for certain sorts of owners, who could then defend
    their homes to the hilt. 
    554 U.S. at
    570 n.1. That made no
    difference to constitutional review of the ban, see 
    id.,
     for a
    simple reason: the point of the Amendment isn’t to ensure that
    some guns would find their way into D.C., but that guns would
    be available to each responsible citizen as a rule (i.e., at least to
    those no more prone to misuse that access than anyone else).
    So if Heller I dictates a certain treatment of “total bans” on
    Second Amendment rights, that treatment must apply to total
    bans on carrying (or possession) by ordinarily situated
    individuals covered by the Amendment.
    This point brings into focus the legally decisive fact: the
    good-reason law is necessarily a total ban on most D.C.
    residents’ right to carry a gun in the face of ordinary self-
    defense needs, where these residents are no more dangerous
    with a gun than the next law-abiding citizen. We say
    “necessarily” because the law destroys the ordinarily situated
    citizen’s right to bear arms not as a side effect of applying
    other, reasonable regulations (like those upheld in Heller II and
    Heller III), but by design: it looks precisely for needs
    “distinguishable” from those of the community. So we needn’t
    pause to apply tiers of scrutiny, as if strong enough showings
    of public benefits could save this destruction of so many
    commonly situated D.C. residents’ constitutional right to bear
    common arms for self-defense in any fashion at all. Bans on
    the ability of most citizens to exercise an enumerated right
    would have to flunk any judicial test that was appropriately
    28
    written and applied, so we strike down the District’s law here
    apart from any particular balancing test.
    Indeed, as noted, it seems highly doubtful that the Heller I
    Court would have acted any differently in reviewing a good-
    reason regulation on possession—one limiting gun ownership
    to that minority of residents with more-than-common needs for
    self-defense at home. Yet possession and carrying—keeping
    and bearing—are on equal footing. So Heller I’s language and
    logic all but dictate that no tiers-of-scrutiny analysis could
    deliver the good-reason law a clean bill of constitutional health.
    Heller I’s categorical approach is appropriate here even
    though our previous cases have always applied tiers of scrutiny
    to gun laws. To be sure, Heller II spoke generally of
    “adopt[ing] . . . a two-step approach” for reviewing “the
    District’s gun laws,” which would “ask first whether a
    particular provision” burdens a Second Amendment right and
    then, “if it does, go on to determine whether the provision
    passes muster under the appropriate level of constitutional
    scrutiny.” 
    670 F.3d at 1252
     (emphasis added). Though
    somewhat open-ended, this language standing alone would
    suggest that we apply only intermediate or strict scrutiny to
    every burdensome gun law we ever review. But another
    passage in Heller II expressly limited the opinion’s framework
    to laws “significantly less severe” than a “total prohibition.” 
    Id. at 1266
    . We believe this caveat—which Heller II offered to
    distinguish Heller I—was in fact required by Heller I’s
    example. So we read this explicit limit in Heller II as
    controlling that decision’s more generic embrace of “level[s]
    of constitutional scrutiny.” 
    670 F.3d at 1252
    ; cf. Gerhardson v.
    Gopher News Co., 
    698 F.2d 1052
    , 1059 (8th Cir. 2012) (“We
    will not interpret our precedent in a way that is inconsistent
    with binding Supreme Court authority.”). True, our gun cases
    have never applied a more categorical approach, but then
    29
    we’ve never been asked to review so much as a “substantial”
    burden on a “core” protected right, to say nothing of a ban. That
    is why we have always relied on the familiar tiers of scrutiny;
    in fact, we’ve never applied more than intermediate scrutiny.
    This is different. Here Heller I’s approach is more fitting.
    Indeed, it fits so tightly that this approach would rarely (if ever)
    apply in cases we can imagine arising in the future. Most other
    regulations won’t deprive even ordinarily situated citizens of
    all means of carrying (or possessing) handguns in self-defense,
    as the good-reason law seems almost engineered to do.
    So our approach, briefed by all the parties, is also urged by
    Heller I and coheres with Heller II. It’s narrower than any other
    basis for decision but not ad hoc. And it would avoid
    suggesting what Heller I implicitly denies: that some public
    benefits could justify preventing people from exercising the
    law-abiding citizen’s right to bear arms for self-defense given
    the risk and needs typical of, well, law-abiding citizens.
    We pause to draw together all the pieces of our analysis:
    At the Second Amendment’s core lies the right of responsible
    citizens to carry firearms for personal self-defense beyond the
    home, subject to longstanding restrictions. These traditional
    limits include, for instance, licensing requirements, but not
    bans on carrying in urban areas like D.C. or bans on carrying
    absent a special need for self-defense. In fact, the
    Amendment’s core at a minimum shields the typically situated
    citizen’s ability to carry common arms generally. The District’s
    good-reason law is necessarily a total ban on exercises of that
    constitutional right for most D.C. residents. That’s enough to
    sink this law under Heller I.
    30
    IV
    Because they sought a preliminary injunction, plaintiffs
    below had the burden to show “that [they are] likely to succeed
    on the merits, that [they are] likely to suffer irreparable harm
    in the absence of preliminary relief, [and] that the balance of
    equities,” including the public interest, “tips in [their] favor.”
    Aamer v. Obama, 
    742 F.3d 1023
    , 1038 (D.C. Cir. 2014). But
    here the merits of the plaintiffs’ challenge are certain and don’t
    turn on disputed facts, so our analysis can stop at the first,
    merits prong of this inquiry. See, e.g., Agency for Int’l Dev. v.
    Alliance for Open Soc’y Int’l, Inc., 
    133 S. Ct. 2321
    , 2332
    (2013) (affirming circuit court’s affirmance of a grant of a
    preliminary injunction based only on the merits of petitioners’
    constitutional challenge).
    Indeed, since our holding at this stage makes a certain
    outcome “inevitable” in these cases, “we have power to dispose
    [of it] ‘as may be just under the circumstances,’” Gross v.
    United States, 
    390 U.S. 62
    , 71 (1968) (quoting 
    28 U.S.C. § 2106
    ), and should do so “to obviate further and entirely
    unnecessary proceedings below,” 
    id. at 72
    ; see also Indep.
    Bankers Ass’n of Am. v. Heimann, 
    613 F.2d 1164
    , 1167 (D.C.
    Cir. 1979) (“Although the case could now be remanded to the
    District Court for a decision on the merits, we have concluded
    that such a course is unnecessary and indeed would be unduly
    wasteful of judicial resources.”) (citing 
    28 U.S.C. § 2106
    ).
    Because the District’s good-reason law merits invalidation
    under Heller I regardless of its precise benefits, we would be
    wasting judicial resources if we remanded for the court to
    develop the records in these cases. Cf. Moore, 702 F.3d at 942
    (reversing denials of preliminary injunctions and remanding
    with instructions to enter declarations of unconstitutionality
    and permanent injunctions).
    31
    ***
    To watch the news for even a week in any major city is to
    give up any illusions about “the problem of handgun violence
    in this country.” Heller I, 
    554 U.S. at 570
    . The District has
    understandably sought to fight this scourge with every legal
    tool at its disposal. For that long struggle against gun violence,
    you might see in today’s decision a defeat; you might see the
    opposite. To say whether it is one or the other is beyond our
    ken here. We are bound to leave the District as much space to
    regulate as the Constitution allows—but no more. Just so, our
    opinion does little more than trace the boundaries laid in 1791
    and flagged in Heller I. And the resulting decision rests on a
    rule so narrow that good-reason laws seem almost uniquely
    designed to defy it: that the law-abiding citizen’s right to bear
    common arms must enable the typical citizen to carry a gun.
    We vacate both orders below and remand with instructions
    to enter permanent injunctions against enforcement of the
    District’s good-reason law.
    So ordered.
    KAREN LECRAFT HENDERSON, Circuit Judge, dissenting:
    My colleagues conclude that the District’s “good reason”
    regulation is categorically barred by the Second Amendment. I
    disagree.1
    Assuming arguendo that the Second Amendment’s
    individual right to keep and bear arms extends beyond the
    home,2 see Drake v. Filko, 
    724 F.3d 426
    , 431 (3d Cir. 2013)
    (declining “to definitively declare that the individual right to
    bear arms for the purpose of self-defense extends beyond the
    home”); Peruta v. Cty. of San Diego, 
    824 F.3d 919
    , 927 (9th
    Cir. 2016) (en banc) (same); Woollard v. Gallagher, 
    712 F.3d 865
    , 876 (4th Cir. 2013) (same); Kachalsky v. Cty. of
    Westchester, 
    701 F.3d 81
    , 89 (2d Cir. 2012) (same), the proper
    standard of review “depends on the nature of the conduct being
    regulated and the degree to which the challenged law burdens
    the right.” Heller v. D.C. (Heller II), 
    670 F.3d 1244
    , 1257
    (D.C. Cir. 2011) (quoting United States v. Chester, 
    628 F.3d 673
    , 682 (4th Cir. 2010)). “Nothing in Heller [I] suggests a
    case involving a restriction significantly less severe than the
    total prohibition of handguns at issue there could or should be
    resolved without reference to one or another of the familiar
    constitutional standards of scrutiny.” Id. at 1266 (internal
    quotation marks omitted). Although “a regulation that imposes
    a substantial burden upon the core right of self-defense
    protected by the Second Amendment must have a strong
    1
    I would affirm the denial of preliminary injunctive relief in
    Wrenn v. District of Columbia, 
    167 F. Supp. 3d 86
     (D.D.C. 2016),
    and reverse the grant of preliminary injunctive relief in Grace v.
    District of Columbia, 
    187 F. Supp. 3d 124
     (D.D.C. 2016).
    2
    Although I assume that the Second Amendment extends to
    some extent beyond the home, I am certain the core Second
    Amendment right does not. The application of strict scrutiny—let
    alone my colleagues’ application of a categorical ban—is, in my
    view, patently off-base.
    2
    justification, . . . a regulation that imposes a less substantial
    burden should be proportionately easier to justify.” 
    Id. at 1257
    .
    The sole Second Amendment “core” right is the right to
    possess arms for self-defense in the home. Drake, 724 F.3d at
    431 (“[T]he individual right to bear arms for the purpose of
    self-defense [in] the home [is] the ‘core’ of the right as
    identified by Heller.”); Kachalsky, 701 F.3d at 89 (“Second
    Amendment guarantees are at their zenith within the home.”);
    United States v. Masciandaro, 
    638 F.3d 458
    , 471 (4th Cir.
    2011) (“[A] lesser showing is necessary with respect to laws
    that burden the right to keep and bear arms outside of the
    home.”). This conclusion is evidenced, first and foremost, by
    the United States Supreme Court’s declarations in District of
    Columbia v. Heller (Heller I) that the “the need for defense of
    self, family, and property is most acute” in the home, 
    554 U.S. 570
    , 628 (2008) (emphasis added), and in McDonald v. City of
    Chicago that “the Second Amendment protects a personal
    right to keep and bear arms for lawful purposes, most notably
    for self-defense within the home,” 
    561 U.S. 742
    , 780 (2010)
    (emphasis added). By characterizing the Second Amendment
    right as most notable and most acute in the home, the Supreme
    Court necessarily implied that that right is less notable and less
    acute outside the home. See Drake, 724 F.3d at 431; Woollard,
    712 F.3d at 876; Kachalsky, 701 F.3d at 89; Masciandaro, 
    638 F.3d at 471
    . A right that is less notable and less acute cannot
    reside at the Second Amendment’s core. My colleagues
    attempt to minimize the Supreme Court’s declarations by
    insisting that the relevant history speaks with “one voice on
    the Amendment’s coverage of carrying as well as keeping
    arms.” Maj. Op. 12-13 (internal quotation marks omitted). But
    their view of history is with blinders on as it is contradicted by
    our sister circuits’ extensive review of the same historical
    3
    record.3 Kachalsky, 701 F.3d at 91 (“History and tradition do
    not speak with one voice here. What history demonstrates is
    that states often disagreed as to the scope of the right to bear
    arms, whether the right was embodied in a state constitution or
    the Second Amendment.”); Drake, 724 F.3d at 431 (same);
    Masciandaro, 
    638 F.3d at 470-71
     (“[A]s we move outside the
    home, firearm rights have always been more limited, because
    public safety interests often outweigh individual interests in
    self-defense.”); cf. Peruta, 824 F.3d at 939 (in U.S. history,
    “the Second Amendment right to keep and bear arms does not
    include, in any degree, the right of a member of the general
    public to carry concealed firearms in public”). I would join
    these circuits and find that the “core” Second Amendment
    right does not extend beyond the home given the history
    upholding “public carry” regulations, a history “enshrined
    with[in] the scope of the Second Amendment when it was
    adopted.” Kachalsky, 701 F.3d at 96 (alteration in original)
    (“The historical prevalence of the regulation of firearms in
    public demonstrates that while the Second Amendment’s core
    concerns are strongest inside hearth and home, states have
    long recognized a countervailing and competing set of
    3
    The majority acknowledges that other circuits have identified
    regulations, including bans, regarding the public bearing of arms
    that were upheld by nineteenth-century courts. See Kachalsky, 701
    F.3d at 94-96; accord Woollard, 712 F.3d at 876 (quoting
    Masciandaro, 
    638 F.3d at 470-71
    ). They then discount those
    decisions as having applied a Second Amendment corollary to the
    First Amendment’s “ample alternative channels” doctrine. Maj. Op.
    20-22. I am not ready to revise history by asserting that nineteenth-
    century courts used reasoning first articulated a century later. See
    Peruta, 824 F.3d at 942.
    4
    concerns with regard to handgun ownership and use in
    public.”). Regulations restricting public carrying are all the
    more compelling in a geographically small but heavily
    populated urban area like the District. See Joseph Blocher,
    Firearm Localism, 123 YALE L.J. 82, 108 (2013) (“American
    cities have traditionally had much more stringent gun control
    than rural areas.”).
    Because the District’s good reason regulation does not
    affect firearm possession within the home and therefore does
    not “impose[] a substantial burden upon the core right of self-
    defense protected by the Second Amendment,” I believe the
    correct standard of review is, at most, intermediate scrutiny.
    Heller II, 
    670 F.3d at 1257
    ; accord Woollard, 712 F.3d at 878
    (recognizing “longstanding out-of-the-home/in-the-home
    distinction bear[ing] directly on the level of scrutiny
    applicable”); Kachalsky, 701 F.3d at 96 (“Because our
    tradition so clearly indicates a substantial role for state
    regulation of the carrying of firearms in public, we conclude
    that intermediate scrutiny is appropriate in this case.”). For the
    District’s challenged licensing regime to pass muster under
    intermediate scrutiny, it must show that the regime is
    “substantially related to an important governmental
    objective.” Heller II, 
    670 F.3d at 1258
     (quoting Clark v. Jeter,
    
    486 U.S. 456
    , 461 (1988)). “That is, the District must establish
    a tight ‘fit’ between the registration requirements and an
    important or substantial governmental interest, a fit ‘that
    employs not necessarily the least restrictive means but . . . a
    means narrowly tailored to achieve the desired objective.’” 
    Id.
    (quoting Bd. of Trs. of State Univ. of N.Y. v. Fox, 
    492 U.S. 469
    ,
    480 (1989)). “It essentially imposes a balancing test: the law
    is constitutional if ‘the governmental interest outweighs the
    burden [on constitutional rights] and cannot be achieved by
    means that do not infringe . . . rights as significantly.’” Heller
    v. D.C. (Heller III), 
    801 F.3d 264
    , 282 (D.C. Cir. 2015)
    5
    (Henderson, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part)
    (quoting Minneapolis Star & Tribune Co. v. Minn. Comm’r of
    Revenue, 
    460 U.S. 575
    , 585 n. 7 (1983)).
    As I have previously written, two additional well-
    grounded principles should guide the intermediate scrutiny
    analysis of the District’s good reason regulation. Id. at 282-84.
    First, “the nature of firearms regulation requires ample
    deference to the legislature.” Id. at 282. Ample deference
    stems from the recognition that gun laws involve a “‘complex
    and dynamic’ issue implicating ‘vast amounts of data’ that the
    legislature is far better equipped to gather and analyze.” Id.
    (quoting Turner Broad. Sys., Inc. v. FCC, 
    512 U.S. 622
    , 662-
    64 (1994)); cf. Holder v. Humanitarian Law Project, 
    561 U.S. 1
    , 34 (2010) (in national security context, “information can be
    difficult to obtain and the impact of certain conduct difficult to
    assess”).
    Second, the District of Columbia is unique. Heller III, 801
    F.3d at 283 (Henderson, J., concurring in part and dissenting
    in part). It is the seat of our national government, “a city full
    of high-level government officials, diplomats, monuments,
    parades, protests and demonstrations and, perhaps most
    pertinent, countless government buildings where citizens are
    almost universally prohibited from possessing firearms.” Id.
    Accordingly, our analysis should reflect an appreciation of
    “the unique challenges that confront the District as it struggles
    to regulate firearms in our Nation’s capital.” Id. (citing City of
    L.A. v. Alameda Books, Inc., 
    535 U.S. 425
    , 439-40 (2002)).
    I believe the District’s good reason regulation passes
    muster under intermediate scrutiny. The District identifies two
    important government objectives underlying its licensing
    regime: the prevention of crime and the promotion of public
    safety. Wrenn Appellee Br. 41. In Heller III, we held,
    unsurprisingly, that “promoting public safety” is indeed a
    6
    substantial government interest.4 Heller III, 801 F.3d at 274.
    The District has provided evidence that its licensing regime
    “promotes [that] substantial governmental interest [in a way]
    that would be achieved less effectively absent the regulation,”
    and, at the same time, is not “substantially broader than
    necessary.” Id. at 272 (quoting Heller II, 
    670 F.3d at 1258
    ).
    Namely, the District highlights the empirical connection
    between a profusion of guns and increased violent crime,
    relying on, inter alia, the studies of leading researchers,
    including the National Research Council, and of the
    legislatures of New York, Maryland and New Jersey—all of
    which have put in place similar licensing regimes. Wrenn
    Appellee Br. 41-45. Moreover, the District points to the expert
    testimony of District Police Chief Cathy Lanier as well as
    commentary from the United States Secret Service and United
    States Capitol Police explaining the District’s special security
    concerns that warrant firearms restrictions. Id. at 44. The
    District’s good reason regulation constitutes its legislature’s
    analysis of a “complex and dynamic” situation, an analysis
    that examines “vast amounts of data” and considers the unique
    needs of the District. Heller III, 801 F.3d at 283 (Henderson,
    J., concurring in part and dissenting in part). The good reason
    regulation that emerged deserves “ample deference,” id. at
    282, that is, a deference that recognizes
    [i]t is the legislature’s job, not ours, to weigh
    conflicting evidence and make policy judgments.
    Indeed, assessing the risks and benefits of handgun
    possession and shaping a licensing scheme to
    maximize the competing public-policy objectives, as
    [the District] did, is precisely the type of
    discretionary judgment that officials in the
    4
    The Supreme Court has also referred to “the significant
    governmental interest in public safety.” Schneck v. Pro-Choice
    Network of W.N.Y., 
    519 U.S. 357
    , 376 (1997).
    7
    legislative and executive       branches    of   state
    government regularly make.
    Kachalsky, 701 F.3d at 99. At bottom, firearms regulation “is
    serious business. We do not wish to be even minutely
    responsible for some unspeakably tragic act of mayhem
    because in the peace of our judicial chambers we
    miscalculated as to Second Amendment rights . . . . If ever
    there was an occasion for restraint, this would seem to be it.”
    Masciandaro, 
    638 F.3d at 475-76
    .
    Accordingly, I respectfully dissent.