People v. Gutierrez , 58 Cal. 4th 1354 ( 2014 )


Menu:
  • Filed 5/5/14
    IN THE SUPREME COURT OF CALIFORNIA
    THE PEOPLE,                          )
    )
    Plaintiff and Respondent, )
    )                               S206365
    v.                        )
    )                         Ct.App. 2/6 B227606
    LUIS ANGEL GUTIERREZ,                )
    )                           Ventura County
    Defendant and Appellant.  )                      Super. Ct. No. 05051378-8
    ____________________________________)
    THE PEOPLE,                          )
    )
    Plaintiff and Respondent, )
    )                               S206771
    v.                        )
    )                         Ct.App. 1/5 A133032
    ANDREW LAWRENCE MOFFETT,             )
    )                        Contra Costa County
    Defendant and Appellant.  )                      Super. Ct. No. 05051378-8
    ____________________________________)
    The two 17-year-old offenders in these cases were convicted of special
    circumstance murder and sentenced to life imprisonment without the possibility of
    parole under Penal Code section 190.5, subdivision (b) (hereafter section
    190.5(b)). Section 190.5(b) provides that the penalty for 16- or 17-year-old
    juveniles who commit special circumstance murder “shall be confinement in the
    state prison for life without the possibility of parole or, at the discretion of the
    court, 25 years to life.” For two decades, since People v. Guinn (1994) 
    28 Cal. App. 4th 1130
    (Guinn), section 190.5(b) has been construed by our Courts of
    Appeal and trial courts as creating a presumption in favor of life without parole as
    the appropriate penalty for juveniles convicted of special circumstance murder.
    After defendants were sentenced, the United States Supreme Court ruled
    that “mandatory life without parole for those under the age of 18 at the time of
    their crimes violates the Eighth Amendment’s prohibition on ‘cruel and unusual
    punishments,’ ” relying extensively on differences between juveniles and adults
    with regard to their culpability and capacity for change. (Miller v. Alabama
    (2012) 567 U.S. __, __ [
    132 S. Ct. 2455
    , 2460] (Miller).) We granted review to
    determine whether a presumption in favor of a sentence of life without parole
    under section 190.5(b) violates the Eighth Amendment to the United States
    Constitution under the principles announced in Miller.
    As explained below, we hold that section 190.5(b), properly construed,
    confers discretion on a trial court to sentence a 16- or 17-year-old juvenile
    convicted of special circumstance murder to life without parole or to 25 years to
    life, with no presumption in favor of life without parole. We further hold that
    Miller requires a trial court, in exercising its sentencing discretion, to consider the
    “distinctive attributes of youth” and how those attributes “diminish the penological
    justifications for imposing the harshest sentences on juvenile offenders” before
    imposing life without parole on a juvenile offender. 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at
    p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2465].) Because the sentencing regime created by section
    190.5(b) authorizes and indeed requires consideration of the distinctive attributes
    of youth highlighted in Miller, we find no constitutional infirmity with section
    190.5(b) once it is understood not to impose a presumption in favor of life without
    parole.
    Because the two defendants here were sentenced before Miller in
    accordance with the interpretation of section 190.5(b) prevailing at the time (see
    2
    
    Guinn, supra
    , 28 Cal.App.4th at p. 1142), we remand for resentencing in light of
    the principles set forth in Miller and this opinion.
    I.
    We consolidated the two cases under review on our own motion. We begin
    with the background of each case.
    A.
    On April 23, 2005, defendant Andrew Lawrence Moffett and codefendant
    Alexander Hamilton robbed a Raley’s supermarket in Pittsburg and a Wells Fargo
    bank located inside the store. At the time, Moffett was 17 years old, and Hamilton
    was 18 years old.
    Moffett enlisted a friend, Elijah Moore, to steal a getaway car in exchange
    for some marijuana. After driving the car to the Raley’s parking lot, Moffett and
    Hamilton entered the store shortly before 5:47 p.m. wearing facial coverings and
    carrying semiautomatic handguns. Moffett approached a checkout stand manned
    by Rima Bosso, pointed his gun at her head, and demanded that she give him the
    money. Flustered, Bosso could not get the register drawer to open. Moffett put
    his gun against her left ear and said, “Come on, bitch. Come on, bitch. You’re
    taking too fucking long.” The drawer eventually opened, and Bosso put about
    $800 in a bag. While Moffett was robbing Bosso, Hamilton approached the
    counter of the Wells Fargo bank, pointed a gun in the direction of the two tellers,
    and demanded money. The tellers put $3,000 in a bag Hamilton was carrying.
    Moffett and Hamilton ran out of the store and attempted to flee in the stolen
    car, but Hamilton soon crashed the vehicle into the back of a pickup truck parked
    on the street. Moffett and Hamilton then got out of the car and started running.
    Moffett told a neighbor who was chasing them, “Stop or I’ll cap you,
    motherfucker.” Moffett and Hamilton continued running through the yards of
    several homes near the Delta de Anza Regional Trail, scaling fences as they went.
    3
    Pittsburg Police Officers John Florance and Larry Lasater arrived at the
    Delta de Anza Regional Trail at 5:58 p.m. Officer Lasater saw a dark figure
    standing by a tree and called out, “Is that someone down there?” The figure
    disappeared into the greenery, and Officer Lasater gave chase. After running for
    some distance, Officer Lasater stopped, drew his weapon, and started walking
    toward where the figure had disappeared. Around this time, Officer Florance
    heard the sound of someone jumping over a fence. He then saw Officer Lasater
    point his gun downward and shout, “Show me your hands.”
    Hamilton, who was lying down in the bushes, fired several shots at Officer
    Lasater. One of the bullets shattered a vertebra in Officer Lasater’s neck, and
    another went through his calf. When additional officers responded to the scene to
    assist Officer Lasater, Hamilton fired shots at them until he ran out of ammunition
    and was taken into custody. The wound to Officer Lasater’s neck proved fatal.
    Meanwhile, Moffett had jumped the fence adjacent to the site of the
    shooting and continued running through the neighborhood. At one point, a woman
    saw him about to enter her garage. She yelled, “no,” and Moffett ran across the
    street. At around 6:35 p.m., officers discovered Moffett lying shirtless in a fetal
    position under a tree where he surrendered, saying, “don’t kill me.”
    Following a joint trial with Hamilton, Moffett was convicted of one count
    of first degree murder, three counts of second degree robbery, and one count of
    driving a stolen vehicle. (Pen. Code, §§ 187, 211; Veh. Code, § 10851.) The jury
    also found true three felony-murder special-circumstance allegations, one killing
    of a peace officer special-circumstance allegation, and firearm use allegations as to
    the murder and robbery counts. (Pen. Code, §§ 190.2, subd. (a)(7) & (17),
    12022.53, subd. (b).) On July 24, 2008, the trial court sentenced Moffett to life
    imprisonment without the possibility of parole on the murder count plus an
    additional 24 years on the remaining charges and enhancements.
    4
    Moffett appealed, and the Court of Appeal reversed the true finding on the
    peace officer special-circumstance allegation because “[t]here was no evidence
    that [Moffett] personally fired his own gun, and the prosecution’s position after
    the close of evidence was that appellant had jumped the fence and fled the area by
    the time Hamilton fired the fatal shot. . . . [N]othing in the record suggests that he
    encouraged Hamilton to fire the shots or assisted him in doing so. . . . [T]here is
    no substantial evidence from which it can be inferred that appellant acted with an
    intent to kill . . . .” The Court of Appeal remanded the case so that the trial court
    could consider whether a sentence of life without parole was appropriate in light
    of the reversal of the peace officer special circumstance. The Court of Appeal also
    directed the trial court to correct sentencing errors on the robbery counts.
    On remand, defense counsel argued that sentencing Moffett to life without
    parole would constitute cruel and unusual punishment because Moffett was a
    juvenile and lacked any intent to kill, and therefore had “twice diminished moral
    culpability.” (Graham v. Florida (2010) 
    560 U.S. 48
    , 69 (Graham).)
    On July 22, 2011, the trial court resentenced Moffett to the same term of
    life without parole plus 24 years. Applying section 190.5(b), the trial court framed
    the issue as whether it should “deviate from the statutory requirement of life
    without the possibility of parole and sentence Mr. Moffett to a determinate term of
    25 years to life.” The trial court declined to “engage in a philosophical discussion
    about [the] merits . . . of the law in California” and observed that the law
    “provides discretion for the trial court in certain limited circumstances such as this
    where the defendant in a capital case was a juvenile tried as an adult.”
    In resentencing Moffett to life without parole, the trial court said: “Mr.
    Moffett was under the age of eighteen by just a few months at the time of this
    incident, thus the court has discretion regarding sentencing. [¶] . . . [¶]
    Sometimes with the passage of time, people tend to forget or minimize the impact
    5
    of incidents such as this. But the impact is just as vivid and continues for the
    victims and the victims’ families and that doesn’t change. [¶] The testimony of
    Rima Bosso, the robbery victim in Count 2, was extremely profound. She testified
    that the individual who was later identified as Mr. Moffett, took his gun, put it to
    her head and threatened to kill her with it. Not only did she see her own death that
    day, but she said for years afterwards and up until and as of the day she testified in
    the trial, she lived in a house where the curtains were pulled shut, the doors were
    locked. She didn’t go out. She was fearful day and night. The trauma damaged
    her relationship with her family. It has changed her life profoundly and forever.
    She will never be the same. The fact that she was not physically harmed does not
    mean that she was not profoundly affected. Her testimony was very compelling.
    [¶] The other two robbery victims described similar experiences. I take all of this
    into account in determining the appropriate sentence.
    “As for Officer Lasater’s family, there’s probably no way to describe in
    words the traumatic effect of this event, nor on the larger community that he was a
    part of. Mr. Moffett was very actively — he very actively participated in a series
    of events, starting with the theft of the car at his request by Elijah Moore; the
    takeover style robbery of the Raley’s store and the bank window; the wild drive
    and crash in a nearby neighborhood; the confrontation of a resident where Mr.
    Moffett told him, ‘Stop or I’ll cap you’; and the shooting of Officer Lasater by Mr.
    Hamilton shortly thereafter. [¶] Mr. Moffett’s role was not a passive role nor was
    he a peripheral player as compared with those factual scenarios described in the
    cases cited by the defense in their sentencing memorandum.
    “I will note that although we don’t know exactly where Mr. Moffett was
    when Mr. Hamilton shot Officer Lasater, the police found gun residue on Mr.
    Moffett’s hands, meaning that even if he did not fire the weapon, he was close to it
    when it was fired; shoe prints matching Mr. Moffett’s ten feet away from where
    6
    Officer Lasater fell; and Mr. Moffett’s cell phone a few feet away from Officer
    Lasater. [¶] The actions taken that day by Mr. Moffett are not those of someone
    who didn’t know what was going on or who was led by others.
    “I’ve also considered Mr. Moffett’s juvenile criminal history. There were
    four entries, including a felony, 245(a)(1) Penal Code, assault with a deadly
    weapon. It was noted that his performance on probation was marginal at best.
    The juvenile justice system has infinitely more resources than the adult system.
    And it appears those resources were not sufficiently taken advantage of to choose
    a different path.
    “The actions taken by Mr. Moffett on the day of this event were not those
    of an irresponsible child. They were the very adult, very violent acts of a young
    man who showed no regard for the impact of his actions on the victim in this case.
    I might add that his actions on that day also have had a profound effect and
    directly affected his own family and loved ones. Although Mr. Moffett was
    slightly under eighteen years old at the time, his actions on that day, coupled with
    his criminal history, do not support, in my opinion, this Court exercising [its]
    discretion and sentencing him to a determinate term of twenty-five years to life. I
    do not find that sentence appropriate in this particular case under the
    circumstances of this case, taking into account everything that is in front of me.
    [¶] On Count 1, I will sentence Mr. Moffett to life without the possibility of
    parole.”
    Moffett again appealed. He argued, among other things, that a sentence of
    life without parole amounted to cruel and unusual punishment because he was not
    the actual shooter, did not intend to kill, and was a juvenile at the time he
    committed his crimes. He also argued that the trial court abused its discretion
    when it declined to impose the lesser sentence of 25 years to life under section
    190.5(b).
    7
    After briefing was complete, the United States Supreme Court issued its
    decision in Miller, holding that mandatory life without parole for juveniles who
    commit murder violates the Eighth Amendment. In a supplemental brief
    discussing the impact of Miller, Moffett argued that the trial court had employed
    an unconstitutional presumption in favor of life without parole when exercising its
    sentencing discretion under section 190.5(b).
    The Court of Appeal vacated Moffett’s sentence and again remanded for
    resentencing. The Court of Appeal acknowledged that “[s]ection 190.5,
    subdivision (b) differs from the mandatory schemes found unconstitutional in
    Miller, because it gives the court the discretion to impose a term that affords the
    possibility of parole in lieu of an LWOP [life without parole] sentence.”
    Nevertheless, the Court of Appeal reasoned, because section 190.5(b) has been
    judicially construed to establish a presumption in favor of life without parole, the
    statute “is contrary to the spirit, if not the letter, of Miller, which cautions that
    LWOP sentences should be ‘uncommon’ given the ‘great difficulty . . . of
    distinguishing at this early age between “the juvenile offender whose crime
    reflects unfortunate yet transient immaturity, and the rare juvenile offender whose
    crime reflects irreparable corruption.” ’ ” “Though Miller did not categorically
    bar LWOP sentences in juvenile homicide cases,” the Court of Appeal observed,
    “it recognizes that juveniles are different from adults in ways that ‘counsel against
    irrevocably sentencing them to a lifetime in prison.’ [Citation.] Treating LWOP
    as the default sentence takes the premise in Miller that such sentences should be
    rarities and turns that premise on its head, instead placing the burden on a youthful
    defendant to affirmatively demonstrate that he or she deserves an opportunity for
    parole.”
    The Court of Appeal remanded the case to allow the trial court to consider
    “the appropriate sentence on the murder count without reference to a presumption
    8
    in favor of LWOP.” Further, the Court of Appeal said, “[o]ther comments by the
    court at the resentencing hearing convince us that remand is appropriate.” The
    Court of Appeal noted that “a juvenile who ‘ “did not kill or intend to kill has a
    twice diminished moral culpability” ’ ” and instructed the trial court to “give
    appropriate weight to the fact that [Moffett] was a non-killer convicted under the
    felony-murder rule.” (Quoting 
    Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at
    p. 2468], quoting 
    Graham, supra
    , 560 U.S. at p. 69.) The Court of Appeal also
    observed that “the trial court placed great reliance on the trauma caused to the
    robbery victims” but cautioned that “the psychological reactions of the robbery
    victims do not say much about [Moffett’s] maturity, prospects for reform, or
    mental state with respect to the homicide itself — the factors paramount under
    Miller.” Finally, the Court of Appeal observed that the trial court, in describing
    Moffett’s criminal history, had “mistakenly characterized a juvenile adjudication
    for assault as a felony, when it was designated a misdemeanor.”
    B.
    On March 16, 2008, defendant Luis Angel Gutierrez was 17 years old and
    lived with relatives in Simi Valley. (In reciting these facts, we refer to members
    of the Gutierrez family, including defendant, by their first names in order to avoid
    confusion. Elsewhere we refer to defendant as Gutierrez.) Around 4:20 a.m.,
    Luis’s uncle, Abel Gutierrez, left for work. Abel’s wife, Josefina Gutierrez, was
    asleep in their bed. Around 6:30 a.m., Abraham Gutierrez, Abel’s nephew, heard
    someone open Josefina’s bedroom door, which was unusual because Josefina
    normally slept late. Abraham got up, walked in the direction of the room, and saw
    Luis in the kitchen. Abraham noticed Luis’s hand was bleeding and asked him
    what had happened. Luis said he had hurt his hand in a fight. Luis left the house
    about five minutes later.
    9
    José Luis Mendoza, Josefina’s brother, later awoke and noticed blood on
    the floor of the living room and in the hallway leading to Abel and Josefina’s
    bedroom. He opened the door and found Josefina’s body lying facedown on the
    floor. A large knife protruded from her back, and there were 28 stab wounds in
    her back, side, stomach, face, neck, and fingers. There were also fresh bruises on
    her face and body. The cause of death was blood loss due to multiple stab
    wounds.
    Luis sustained a severe wound to his hand and was admitted to the hospital
    for treatment. A sexual assault nurse examined Luis and found blood on the head
    of his penis, blood between his toes, and several hairs and fibers adhering to the
    bottom of his feet. Subsequent DNA testing connected Luis to the crime scene
    and to Josefina. A blood pattern analyst who viewed photographs of Josefina’s
    body saw a bloodstain on her back that might have been an imprint or a swipe, and
    it was possible that the shape was consistent with an erect male penis. A sperm
    fraction found on Josefina’s body included a match to her husband, and Luis was
    excluded as a contributor to the sample. But Luis could not be eliminated as a
    contributor to a mixture of nonsperm DNA found on Josefina’s perianal area,
    inner thighs, and buttocks.
    In an interview with police, Luis first denied any involvement in Josefina’s
    death. He eventually acknowledged having a confrontation with Josefina and said
    that she had stabbed him and herself, and that she took off her own nightshirt and
    his pants because she wanted him to have sex with her. Luis told officers that
    after Josefina stabbed him, he stabbed her in the back about three times.
    A jury convicted Luis of first degree murder with a special circumstance
    finding that the murder was committed during the commission of a rape or
    attempted rape. (Pen. Code, §§ 187, subd. (a), 189, 190.2, subd. (a)(17)(C), 261.)
    The jury found true the allegation that defendant personally used a deadly weapon
    10
    (id., § 12022, subd. (b)(1)) and was over 14 years of age at the time of the offense
    (Welf. & Inst. Code, § 602, subd. (b)(1)).
    During the sentencing hearing on August 23, 2010, defense counsel urged
    the trial court to “allow [Luis] a chance at parole after 25 years . . . because of his
    age.” Noting that “25 years would place [Luis] in his late forties,” counsel argued
    that at that point “[t]here would be a very much closer predictability to his
    likelihood of reoffense.” Counsel further argued that a sentence of 25 years to life
    would be adequate to protect society and “to address this horrible thing that he
    did.”
    The trial court sentenced defendant to life without parole plus one year on
    the weapon enhancement. In pronouncing the sentence, the trial court said:
    “[T]he Court has been concerned throughout the trial about the defendant’s age
    and the age [at] which he committed this horrific crime. [¶] And I have considered
    all of the legal options that are limited for the Court with this conviction, but I
    have considered all of them and there are a number of things about the crime itself
    that in my view warrants life without the possibility of parole, notwithstanding the
    defendant’s age. [¶] First and foremost is really just the true horror that was
    involved and the amount of violence that was inflicted on Josefina is really
    inexplicable. And there isn’t, other than the rape special circumstance, there isn’t
    any rational[] explanation as to how the defendant could have found himself in
    this position. [¶] He has devastated this family and her children and her husband,
    and there is really no amount of time that could be imposed as punishment that
    would repay the damage he has caused, not just to her inner circle but to the
    community as well and the community of her family.
    “In addition to the crime itself, I will note, as pointed out in the probation
    officer’s report, that his behavior in custody thus far hasn’t really demonstrated
    that he will do anything but continue to get written up. And the probation officer’s
    11
    report indicates that he has had ten major write-ups in custody for failing to obey
    the rules, deception, possession of contraband, including alcohol, which perhaps
    his substance abuse is perhaps the only thing that I can look to that might possibly
    give some explanation as to why a young man can find himself in such a horrific
    situation, horrific situation.
    “So I thought — I have thought long and hard about what punishment is
    appropriate and I am absolutely convinced at this stage of the proceedings that life
    without the possibility of parole is the only thing that the Court can do that could
    redress the amount of violence that was inflicted in this case.”
    Luis appealed his conviction and sentence. After the high court decided
    Miller, Luis filed supplemental briefing in the Court of Appeal arguing, among
    other things, that his life without parole sentence should be vacated and the case
    remanded for the trial court to resentence him with full consideration of the factors
    deemed relevant in Miller and without adherence to California case law holding
    that life without parole is the “presumed sentence” under section 190.5(b).
    The Court of Appeal held that Luis had forfeited his right to challenge his
    sentence as cruel and unusual punishment by failing to object on that ground in the
    trial court. But, the Court of Appeal continued, even if Luis had raised the issue,
    his claim would still fail because a sentence of life without parole under section
    190.5(b) does not violate the Eighth Amendment as construed by Miller. “Unlike
    Miller,” the Court of Appeal said, “[Luis’s] LWOP sentence was not mandatory.
    [Luis] was sentenced pursuant to section 190.5, subdivision (b), which provides
    that a juvenile defendant 16 years of age or older who is convicted of first degree,
    special circumstance murder may be sentenced to life without possibility of parole.
    [Citation.] The statute does not require a mandatory LWOP sentence and vests
    sentencing courts with the discretion to sentence the defendant to a term of 25
    years to life with possibility of parole.” (Italics in original.) Because the trial
    12
    court was aware of its discretion to sentence Luis to a lesser sentence, the Court of
    Appeal concluded, remanding for resentencing in light of Miller would be futile.
    II.
    We granted review in these cases to determine whether a presumption in
    favor of a sentence of life without parole under section 190.5(b) violates the
    Eighth Amendment under the principles announced in Miller. As an initial matter,
    we reject the Attorney General’s contention that Gutierrez forfeited his Eighth
    Amendment claim by failing to raise it in the trial court. At sentencing, Gutierrez
    did object to the imposition of life without parole and requested a sentence of 25
    years to life. Although he did not mention the Eighth Amendment, this is
    unsurprising because at the time the high court had not yet granted review in
    Miller and no court had even held that a mandatory sentence of life without parole
    for juveniles convicted of homicide was unconstitutional. After Miller was
    decided, Gutierrez promptly asserted his Eighth Amendment claim in the Court of
    Appeal, which fully considered the claim, and he now reasserts that claim in this
    court. Given these circumstances, and because his Eighth Amendment challenge
    involves a question of law, we exercise our discretion to consider it here. (See
    People v. Williams (1998) 
    17 Cal. 4th 148
    , 161, fn. 6.)
    A.
    The parties have asked us to decide a constitutional issue arising from the
    fact that our appellate and trial courts have long construed section 190.5(b) as
    establishing a presumption in favor of life without parole for juveniles convicted
    of special circumstance murder. But we have never examined whether this
    construction of section 190.5(b) is correct as a matter of statutory interpretation.
    “In construing statutes, ‘our fundamental task is “to ascertain the intent of
    the lawmakers so as to effectuate the purpose of the statute.” [Citations.] We
    begin by examining the statutory language because it generally is the most reliable
    13
    indicator of legislative intent. [Citation.] We give the language its usual and
    ordinary meaning, and “[i]f there is no ambiguity, then we presume the lawmakers
    meant what they said, and the plain meaning of the language governs.” [Citation.]
    If, however, the statutory language is ambiguous, “we may resort to extrinsic
    sources, including the ostensible objects to be achieved and the legislative
    history.” [Citation.] Ultimately we choose the construction that comports most
    closely with the apparent intent of the lawmakers, with a view to promoting rather
    than defeating the general purpose of the statute. [Citations.]’ ” (Mays v. City of
    Los Angeles (2008) 
    43 Cal. 4th 313
    , 321.) With these principles in mind, we
    discuss how section 190.5(b) has been interpreted by the Courts of Appeal and
    assess that interpretation in light of the text and history of the statute.
    Section 190.5(b) provides: “The penalty for a defendant found guilty of
    murder in the first degree, in any case in which one or more special circumstances
    enumerated in Section 190.2 or 190.25 has been found to be true under Section
    190.4, who was 16 years of age or older and under the age of 18 years at the time
    of the commission of the crime, shall be confinement in the state prison for life
    without the possibility of parole or, at the discretion of the court, 25 years to life.”
    For two decades, the Courts of Appeal have uniformly interpreted section
    190.5(b) as establishing a presumption in favor of life without parole for juvenile
    offenders who were 16 years of age or older when they committed special
    circumstance murder. The leading case is 
    Guinn, supra
    , 
    28 Cal. App. 4th 1130
    .
    There, after the jury convicted a juvenile offender of first degree murder and found
    true a robbery-murder special circumstance, the trial court sentenced the defendant
    to life without parole pursuant to section 190.5(b). (Guinn, at p. 1140.) On
    appeal, the defendant argued that “in the absence of specific guidelines [under
    section 190.5(b)], LWOP will be arbitrarily and capriciously imposed, in violation
    of the guarantees against cruel and unusual punishment.” (Id. at p. 1141.)
    14
    In rejecting the defendant’s argument, Guinn held that the trial court’s
    sentencing discretion was appropriately circumscribed under section 190.5(b) and
    that life without parole was the presumptive sentence for a juvenile convicted of
    special circumstance murder. The court explained: “We believe Penal Code
    section 190.5 means . . . that 16- or 17-year-olds who commit special circumstance
    murder must be sentenced to LWOP, unless the court, in its discretion, finds good
    reason to choose the less severe sentence of 25 years to life. Our construction is
    based on the ordinary language and structure of the provision; in context, the word
    ‘shall’ appears to be mandatory. In addition, this construction is consistent with
    the history of Penal Code section 190.5, enacted as part of Proposition 115, the
    ‘Crime Victims Justice Reform Act.’ Under the former law, youthful offenders
    were exempted from application of the death penalty provisions. They also were
    excluded from application of the special-circumstance proceedings under Penal
    Code section 190.4, so that murderers under age 18 tried as adults were subject
    neither to the death penalty nor to LWOP. [Citation.] Penal Code section 190.5
    was amended specifically to make youthful offenders, who committed what would
    have been a death-eligible crime for an adult, subject to special circumstances and
    LWOP. The fact that a court might grant leniency in some cases, in recognition
    that some youthful special circumstance murderers might warrant more lenient
    treatment, does not detract from the generally mandatory imposition of LWOP as
    the punishment for a youthful special circumstance murderer. In the first instance,
    therefore, LWOP is the presumptive punishment for 16- or 17-year-old special-
    circumstance murderers, and the court’s discretion is concomitantly circumscribed
    to that extent.” (
    Guinn, supra
    , 28 Cal.App.4th at pp. 1141–1142.)
    The court in Guinn went on to reject the claim that section 190.5(b)
    “authorize[s] the court to act arbitrarily and capriciously, based on the asserted
    lack of guidelines for exercise of the court’s discretion.” (
    Guinn, supra
    , 28
    15
    Cal.App.4th at p. 1142.) Guinn concluded that “the factors stated in section 190.3
    are available, to the extent relevant to an exercise of discretion to grant leniency,
    as guidelines under section 190.5. Because those factors allow the court to take
    into account any mitigating circumstance which extenuates the gravity of the
    crime (factor (k)), by extension the criteria stated under California Rules of Court,
    rule 423 [now rule 4.423], are also available as guidelines for the court’s exercise
    of discretion.” (Id. at pp. 1142–1143.)
    Subsequent cases predating Miller have followed Guinn’s reading of
    section 190.5(b). (See, e.g., People v. Murray (2012) 
    203 Cal. App. 4th 277
    , 282;
    People v. Blackwell (2011) 
    202 Cal. App. 4th 144
    , 159; People v. Ybarra (2008)
    
    166 Cal. App. 4th 1069
    , 1089 (Ybarra).)
    Contrary to Guinn, however, our review of the text and history of section
    190.5(b) does not lead us to conclude that the statute establishes a presumption in
    favor of life without parole. The text of the statute appears ambiguous on this
    point. As noted, section 190.5(b) says the penalty for special circumstance murder
    committed by a 16- or 17-year-old offender “shall be confinement in the state
    prison for life without the possibility of parole or, at the discretion of the court, 25
    years to life.” It is not unreasonable to read this text, as Guinn did, to mean that a
    court “shall” impose life without parole unless “at the discretion of the court” a
    sentence of 25 years to life appears more appropriate. (See 
    Guinn, supra
    , 28
    Cal.App.4th at pp. 1142, 1145.) But it is equally reasonable to read the text to
    mean that a court may select one of the two penalties in the exercise of its
    discretion, with no presumption in favor of one or the other. The latter reading
    accords with common usage. For example, if a teacher informed her students that
    “you must take a final exam or, at your discretion, write a term paper,” it would be
    reasonable for the students to believe they were equally free to pursue either
    16
    option. The text of section 190.5(b) does not clearly indicate whether the statute
    was intended to make life without parole the presumptive sentence.
    In her briefing, the Attorney General contends that a presumption in favor
    of life without parole is the only “logical” interpretation of section 190.5(b)
    because in the context of the penalty scheme applicable to 16 and 17 year olds
    convicted of murder, “LWOP is the only penalty that is available to punish special
    circumstance murderers more harshly than first degree murderers.” But there is
    nothing illogical about making life without parole an available penalty for
    juveniles convicted of special circumstance murder without also making it the
    presumptive penalty. It is reasonable for a policymaker to believe that special
    circumstance murder should expose a juvenile offender to life without parole —
    thereby differentiating such an offender from a juvenile who commits first degree
    murder with no special circumstance — while also believing that imposition of
    that penalty as opposed to 25 years to life, which is the penalty for first degree
    murder (Pen. Code, § 190, subd. (a)), should be decided case by case with no
    default preference. The structure of the penalty scheme, like the text of section
    190.5(b), does not clearly indicate a presumption in favor of life without parole.
    Nor does legislative history resolve the ambiguity. As the Attorney
    General acknowledged at oral argument, nothing in the legislative history supports
    Guinn’s interpretation of section 190.5(b). The statute was enacted in 1990 as part
    of Proposition 115, the Crime Victims Justice Reform Act. (See Ballot Pamp.,
    Primary Elec. (June 5, 1990) text of Prop. 115, p. 33 (Ballot Pamphlet); see also
    People v. Marquez (1992) 
    1 Cal. 4th 553
    , 582 (Marquez).) Before Proposition
    115, juvenile offenders convicted of first degree murder could not be charged with
    special circumstances and thus were not subject either to the death penalty or to
    life without parole. (See Marquez, at p. 582; People v. Spears (1983) 
    33 Cal. 3d 279
    , 280–283; People v. Davis (1981) 
    29 Cal. 3d 814
    , 831; see also Cal. Dept. of
    17
    Justice, 1990 Crime Victims Justice Reform Initiative: Proposition 115 Manual
    (1990), at p. 159.) Although juvenile offenders remain ineligible for the death
    penalty (Pen. Code, § 190.5, subd. (a)), Proposition 115 amended section 190.5 to
    make clear that juvenile offenders convicted of first degree murder can be charged
    with special circumstances and are subject to life without parole if convicted of
    special circumstance murder. (See Sen. Com. on Judiciary, Staff Analysis of
    Crime Victims Justice Initiative (Dec. 11, 1989) pp. 77–78; see also Review of
    Selected 1990 California Legislation—Addendum (1991) 22 Pac. L.J. 1010, 1014
    [reviewing Prop. 115].) The stated purpose of the initiative was to “to restore
    balance to our criminal justice system, to create a system in which justice is swift
    and fair, and to create a system in which violent criminals receive just punishment,
    in which crime victims and witnesses are treated with care and respect, and in
    which society as a whole can be free from the fear of crime in our homes,
    neighborhoods, and schools.” (Ballot Pamphlet, text of Prop. 115, p. 33.)
    Thus, Proposition 115 was intended to toughen penalties for juveniles
    convicted of first degree murder by making them eligible for life without parole
    upon a finding of one or more special circumstances. However, neither the text of
    the initiative, the summary prepared by the Attorney General, the analysis
    prepared by the Senate Office of Research, nor the voters’ pamphlet provides any
    indication whether the initiative was intended to make life without parole the
    presumptive sentence. The analysis by the Senate Office of Research merely
    stated that section 190.5(b) is intended “to provide a sentence of life without
    parole or 25 to Life for a 16–18 year old . . . .” (Sen. Off. of Research, June 1990
    Ballot: Analysis of Propositions (Mar. 1990) p. 46.) Similarly, the ballot pamphlet
    described Proposition 115 as “[a]llow[ing] minors who are 16 or 17 years of age at
    the time of the crime . . . to be punished by life imprisonment without the
    possibility of parole.” (Ballot 
    Pamphlet, supra
    , analysis of Prop. 115 by Legis.
    18
    Analyst, p. 32, italics in original; see also Prop. 115, as approved by voters,
    Primary Elec. (June 5, 1990); Cal. Dept. of Justice, Crime Victims Justice Reform
    Initiative: Proposition 115 
    Manual, supra
    , at pp. 159–160; Ballot Pamphlet,
    argument in favor of Prop. 115, p. 34.) Nothing in the legislative history provides
    a basis to conclude that section 190.5(b) was intended to create a presumption in
    favor of life without parole.
    We conclude that the text and history of section 190.5(b) are ambiguous as
    to whether the statute establishes a presumption in favor of life without parole.
    We turn now to consider whether other principles of statutory interpretation
    resolve the ambiguity.
    B.
    When a question of statutory interpretation implicates constitutional issues,
    we are guided by the precept that “ ‘[i]f a statute is susceptible of two
    constructions, one of which will render it constitutional and the other
    unconstitutional in whole or in part, or raise serious and doubtful constitutional
    questions, the court will adopt the construction which, without doing violence to
    the reasonable meaning of the language used, will render it valid in its entirety, or
    free from doubt as to its constitutionality, even though the other construction is
    equally reasonable.’ ” (Conservatorship of Wendland (2001) 
    26 Cal. 4th 519
    , 548;
    see People v. Leiva (2013) 
    56 Cal. 4th 498
    , 506–507 (Leiva) [“[W]e adhere to ‘the
    precept “that a court, when faced with an ambiguous statute that raises serious
    constitutional questions, should endeavor to construe the statute in a manner which
    avoids any doubt concerning its validity.” ’ ”].) This rule, called the canon of
    constitutional doubt (Scalia & Garner, Reading Law: The Interpretation of Legal
    Texts (2012) p. 249 (Scalia & Garner)), has been described as a “cardinal
    principle” of statutory interpretation that “has for so long been applied . . . that it is
    19
    beyond debate.” (Debartolo Corp. v. Florida Gulf Coast Bldg. & Construction
    Trades Council (1988) 
    485 U.S. 568
    , 575.)
    The canon reflects “a judgment that statutes ought not to tread on
    questionable constitutional grounds unless they do so clearly” as well as “a
    judgment that courts should minimize the occasions on which they confront and
    perhaps contradict the legislative branch.” (Scalia & 
    Garner, supra
    , at p. 249.) It
    applies whenever “the Government’s view would raise serious constitutional
    questions on which precedent is not dispositive” (Jones v. United States (1999)
    
    526 U.S. 227
    , 251 (Jones)) and “whether the cases raising the constitutional doubt
    antedate or postdate a statute’s enactment” (Scalia & Garner, at p. 249). But the
    canon “is qualified by the proposition that ‘avoidance of a difficulty will not be
    pressed to the point of disingenuous evasion.’ ” (Rust v. Sullivan (1991) 
    500 U.S. 173
    , 191.)
    Applying this canon, we have repeatedly construed penal laws, including
    laws enacted by initiative, in a manner that avoids serious constitutional questions.
    (See 
    Leiva, supra
    , 56 Cal.4th at p. 509 [construing probationary period tolling
    provision “to avoid doubts concerning its constitutional validity”]; People v.
    Superior Court (Romero) (1996) 
    13 Cal. 4th 497
    , 509–519 (Romero) [applying the
    canon in interpreting the scope of judges’ power to strike allegations of prior
    convictions under the “Three Strikes” law]; Whitman v. Superior Court (1991) 
    54 Cal. 3d 1063
    , 1074 [declining to construe Prop. 115 as allowing multiple hearsay
    testimony because of “constitutional questions that we can and should avoid”];
    People v. Smith (1983) 
    34 Cal. 3d 251
    , 259–262 [construing Prop. 8’s changes to
    the rules of evidence in criminal trials as applying only to crimes committed after
    its effective date in order to avoid ex post facto concerns]; accord, 
    Jones, supra
    ,
    526 U.S. at pp. 239–240 [applying the canon in holding that facts that increase
    defendants’ sentences under the federal carjacking statute are elements of the
    20
    crime that must be charged and proven beyond a reasonable doubt].) In deciding
    which of two or more reasonable interpretations of a penal statute to adopt, our
    analysis is “necessarily inform[ed]” by constitutional concerns. (Romero, at
    p. 509.) We adopt the less constitutionally problematic interpretation of a penal
    statute so long as that interpretation is “reasonably possible.” (Id. at p. 513.) In
    light of this principle, we must examine whether the Guinn presumption raises a
    serious question under the Eighth Amendment.
    1.
    The Eighth Amendment provides: “Excessive bail shall not be required,
    nor excessive fines imposed, nor cruel and unusual punishments inflicted.” This
    constitutional provision “guarantees individuals the right not to be subjected to
    excessive sanctions.” (Roper v. Simmons (2005) 
    543 U.S. 551
    , 560 (Roper).)
    This right “flows from the basic ‘ “precept of justice that punishment for crime
    should be graduated and proportioned to [the] offense.” ’ ” (Ibid.) To determine
    whether a punishment is cruel and unusual, and thus violative of the Eighth
    Amendment, “courts must look beyond historical conceptions to ‘ “the evolving
    standards of decency that mark the progress of a maturing society.” ’ [Citations].”
    (
    Graham, supra
    , 560 U.S. at p. 58.) “This is because ‘[t]he standard of extreme
    cruelty is not merely descriptive, but necessarily embodies a moral judgment. The
    standard itself remains the same, but its applicability must change as the basic
    mores of society change.’ ” (Kennedy v. Louisiana (2008) 
    554 U.S. 407
    , 419.)
    In Miller, the high court considered whether sentencing schemes mandating
    life without parole for juveniles convicted of homicide offenses violate the Eighth
    Amendment. Each of the two cases in Miller involved a 14-year-old offender who
    was tried as an adult, convicted of murder, and sentenced to life without parole
    pursuant to a state law providing the sentencing authority with no discretion to
    impose a lesser punishment. The constitutionality of mandatory life without
    21
    parole for juvenile homicide offenders, Miller explained, “implicate[s] two strands
    of precedent reflecting our concern with proportionate punishment.” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2463].)
    The first strand of relevant precedent, according to Miller, consists of
    “categorical bans on sentencing practices based on mismatches between the
    culpability of a class of offenders and the severity of a penalty. [Citation.] So, for
    example, we have held that imposing the death penalty for nonhomicide crimes
    against individuals, or imposing it on mentally retarded defendants, violates the
    Eighth Amendment. See Kennedy v. Louisiana, 
    554 U.S. 407
    (2008); Atkins v.
    Virginia, 
    536 U.S. 304
    (2002). Several of the cases in this group have specially
    focused on juvenile offenders, because of their lesser culpability. Thus, Roper
    held that the Eighth Amendment bars capital punishment for children, and
    Graham concluded that the Amendment also prohibits a sentence of life without
    the possibility of parole for a child who committed a nonhomicide offense.”
    
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2463].)
    Focusing extensively on Roper and Graham, the high court in Miller
    explained that those cases “establish that children are constitutionally different
    from adults for purposes of sentencing” in three important ways. 
    (Miller, supra
    ,
    567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2464].) “First, children have a ‘ “lack of
    maturity and an underdeveloped sense of responsibility,” ’ leading to recklessness,
    impulsivity, and heedless risk-taking. [Citation.] Second, children ‘are more
    vulnerable . . . to negative influences and outside pressures,’ including from their
    family and peers; they have limited ‘contro[l] over their own environment’ and
    lack the ability to extricate themselves from horrific, crime-producing settings.
    [Citation.] And third, a child’s character is not as ‘well formed’ as an adult’s; his
    traits are ‘less fixed’ and his actions less likely to be ‘evidence of irretrievabl[e]
    deprav[ity].’ [Citation.]” (Ibid.) For these reasons, “juveniles have diminished
    22
    culpability and greater prospects for reform,” and are thus “ ‘less deserving of the
    most severe punishments.’ [Citation.]” (Ibid.)
    Miller further observed: “Our decisions [in Roper and Graham] rested not
    only on common sense—on what ‘any parent knows’—but on science and social
    science as well. [Citation.] In Roper, we cited studies showing that ‘ “[o]nly a
    relatively small proportion of adolescents” ’ who engage in illegal activity
    ‘ “develop entrenched patterns of problem behavior.” ’ [Citation.] And in
    Graham, we noted that ‘developments in psychology and brain science continue to
    show fundamental differences between juvenile and adult minds’—for example, in
    ‘parts of the brain involved in behavior control.’ [Citation.] We reasoned that
    those findings—of transient rashness, proclivity for risk, and inability to assess
    consequence—both lessened a child’s ‘moral culpability’ and enhanced the
    prospect that, as the years go by and neurological development occurs, his
    ‘ “deficiencies will be reformed.” ’ [Citation.]” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at
    pp. __–__ [132 S.Ct. at pp. 2464–2465, fn. omitted.) “The evidence presented to
    us in these cases indicates that the science and social science supporting Roper’s
    and Graham’s conclusions have become even stronger.” (Miller, at p. __, fn. 5
    [132 S.Ct. at p. 2464, fn. 5]; see 
    ibid. [“ ‘It is
    increasingly clear that adolescent
    brains are not yet fully mature in regions and systems related to higher-order
    executive functions such as impulse control, planning ahead, and risk
    avoidance’ ”], quoting brief for Am. Psychological Assn. et al. as amici curiae,
    p. 4.)
    Miller went on to explain that “the distinctive attributes of youth diminish
    the penological justifications for imposing the harshest sentences on juvenile
    offenders, even when they commit terrible crimes. Because ‘ “[t]he heart of the
    retribution rationale” ’ relates to an offender’s blameworthiness, ‘ “the case for
    retribution is not as strong with a minor as with an adult.” ’ [Citations.] Nor can
    23
    deterrence do the work in this context, because ‘ “the same characteristics that
    render juveniles less culpable than adults” ’—their immaturity, recklessness, and
    impetuosity—make them less likely to consider potential punishment. [Citation.]
    Similarly, incapacitation could not support the life-without-parole sentence in
    Graham: Deciding that a ‘juvenile offender forever will be a danger to society’
    would require ‘mak[ing] a judgment that [he] is incorrigible’—but
    ‘ “incorrigibility is inconsistent with youth.” ’ [Citation.] And for the same
    reason, rehabilitation could not justify that sentence. Life without parole
    ‘forswears altogether the rehabilitative ideal.’ [Citation.] It reflects ‘an
    irrevocable judgment about [an offender’s] value and place in society,’ at odds
    with a child’s capacity for change.” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at
    p. 2465]; see 
    Graham, supra
    , 560 U.S. at p. 79 [“Life in prison without the
    possibility of parole gives no chance for fulfillment outside prison walls, no
    chance for reconciliation with society, no hope. Maturity can lead to that
    considered reflection which is the foundation for remorse, renewal, and
    rehabilitation.”].)
    Further, although Graham addressed whether juveniles could be sentenced
    to life without parole for nonhomicide offenses, “none of what [Graham] said
    about children—about their distinctive (and transitory) mental traits and
    environmental vulnerabilities—is crime-specific. Those features are evident in the
    same way, and to the same degree, when . . . a botched robbery turns into a killing.
    So Graham’s reasoning implicates any life-without-parole sentence imposed on a
    juvenile . . . .” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2465].)
    Miller then turned to the second strand of relevant precedent. Graham, the
    high court observed, “likened life without parole for juveniles to the death penalty
    itself . . . .” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2463].) “Life-
    without-parole terms . . . ‘share some characteristics with death sentences that are
    24
    shared by no other sentences.’ [Citation.] Imprisoning an offender until he dies
    alters the remainder of his life ‘by a forfeiture that is irrevocable.’ [Citation.] And
    this lengthiest possible incarceration is an ‘especially harsh punishment for a
    juvenile,’ because he will almost inevitably serve ‘more years and a greater
    percentage of his life in prison than an adult offender.’ [Citation.] The penalty
    when imposed on a teenager, as compared with an older person, is therefore ‘the
    same . . . in name only.’ ” (Id. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2466].) “Graham’s
    ‘[t]reat[ment] [of] juvenile life sentences as analogous to capital punishment,’ ”
    the high court explained, makes relevant a line of precedent “demanding
    individualized sentencing when imposing the death penalty.” (Id. at p. __ [132
    S.Ct. at p. 2467].)
    Beginning with Woodson v. North Carolina (1976) 
    428 U.S. 280
    , several
    high court decisions “have elaborated on the requirement that capital defendants
    have an opportunity to advance, and the judge or jury a chance to assess, any
    mitigating factors, so that the death penalty is reserved only for the most culpable
    defendants committing the most serious offenses.” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at
    p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2467].) These decisions “insisted . . . that a sentencer have
    the ability to consider the ‘mitigating qualities of youth,’ ” including the
    “ ‘transient’ ” qualities emphasized in Roper and Graham: “immaturity,
    irresponsibility, ‘impetuousness[,] and recklessness,’ ” as well as
    “ ‘susceptib[ility] to influence and to psychological damage.’ ” (Miller, at p. __
    [132 S.Ct. at p. 2467].) “In light of Graham’s reasoning,” Miller said, “these
    decisions too show the flaws of imposing mandatory life-without-parole sentences
    on juvenile homicide offenders. Such mandatory penalties, by their nature,
    preclude a sentencer from taking account of an offender’s age and the wealth of
    characteristics and circumstances attendant to it.” (Ibid.) Just as the failure to
    consider such factors “would be strictly forbidden” in meting out the death
    25
    penalty, “Graham indicates that a similar rule should apply when a juvenile
    confronts a sentence of life (and death) in prison.” (Id. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at
    p. 2468].)
    “To recap: Mandatory life without parole for a juvenile precludes
    consideration of his chronological age and its hallmark features—among them,
    immaturity, impetuosity, and failure to appreciate risks and consequences. It
    prevents taking into account the family and home environment that surrounds
    him—and from which he cannot usually extricate himself—no matter how brutal
    or dysfunctional. It neglects the circumstances of the homicide offense, including
    the extent of his participation in the conduct and the way familial and peer
    pressures may have affected him. Indeed, it ignores that he might have been
    charged and convicted of a lesser offense if not for incompetencies associated with
    youth—for example, his inability to deal with police officers or prosecutors
    (including on a plea agreement) or his incapacity to assist his own attorneys.
    [Citations.] And finally, this mandatory punishment disregards the possibility of
    rehabilitation even when the circumstances most suggest it.” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567
    U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2468].)
    Based on “the confluence of these two lines of precedent” — which
    establish that juvenile offenders are less culpable and more susceptible to reform
    than adults, and that imposition of the harshest punishment on a juvenile requires
    individualized sentencing that takes into account an offender’s “youth (and all that
    accompanies it)” — the high court in Miller held that “the Eighth Amendment
    forbids a sentencing scheme that mandates life in prison without possibility of
    parole for juvenile offenders.” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at pp. __, __ [132 S.Ct. at
    pp. 2464, 2469].)
    Because that holding was sufficient to decide the two cases at issue in
    Miller, the high court did not consider the “alternative argument that the Eighth
    26
    Amendment requires a categorical bar on life without parole for juveniles, or at
    least for those 14 and younger.” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at
    p. 2469].) But Miller concluded with the following caution: “[G]iven all we have
    said in Roper, Graham, and this decision about children’s diminished culpability
    and heightened capacity for change, we think appropriate occasions for sentencing
    juveniles to this harshest possible penalty will be uncommon. That is especially so
    because of the great difficulty we noted in Roper and Graham of distinguishing at
    this early age between ‘the juvenile offender whose crime reflects unfortunate yet
    transient immaturity, and the rare juvenile offender whose crime reflects
    irreparable corruption.’ [Citations.] Although we do not foreclose a sentencer’s
    ability to make that judgment in homicide cases, we require it to take into account
    how children are different, and how those differences counsel against irrevocably
    sentencing them to a lifetime in prison.” (Ibid.)
    We recently applied the principles of Miller and Graham in People v.
    Caballero (2012) 
    55 Cal. 4th 262
    (Caballero) to hold that an aggregate determinate
    sentence of over 100 years violated Graham’s requirement that “a state must
    provide a [nonhomicide] juvenile offender ‘with some realistic opportunity to
    obtain release’ from prison during his or her expected lifetime.” (Caballero, at
    p. 268, quoting 
    Graham, supra
    , 560 U.S. at p. 82.) The Attorney General had
    argued in Caballero that because Graham involved a sentence of life without
    parole, Graham’s reasoning does not apply to a determinate sentence, even when
    the sentence would have the practical effect of keeping a juvenile behind bars
    without the possibility of parole for the rest of his life. We rejected the Attorney
    General’s narrow interpretation of Graham, observing that Miller had “extended
    Graham’s reasoning (but not its categorical ban) to homicide cases, and, in so
    doing, made it clear that Graham’s ‘flat ban’ on life without parole sentences for
    juvenile offenders in nonhomicide cases applies to their sentencing equation
    27
    regardless of intent in the crime’s commission, or how a sentencing court
    structures the life without parole sentence.” (Caballero, at p. 267.) Caballero
    highlighted Miller’s and Graham’s observations concerning the differences
    between children and adults that limit the constitutional validity of life without
    parole for juvenile offenders. (Caballero, at pp. 266, 267, 268, fn. 4.) But
    Caballero “le[ft] Miller’s application in the homicide context to a case that poses
    the issue.” (Id. at p. 268, fn. 4.) That issue is presented here.
    2.
    Under Miller, a state may authorize its courts to impose life without parole
    on a juvenile homicide offender when the penalty is discretionary and when the
    sentencing court’s discretion is properly exercised in accordance with Miller.
    Unlike the sentencing laws at issue in Miller, section 190.5(b) is discretionary and
    does not mandate life without parole for juvenile homicide offenders. California’s
    individualized, discretionary sentencing of juvenile homicide offenders differs in
    significant ways from the mandatory sentencing scheme at issue in Miller.
    Nevertheless, in light of Miller’s reasoning, a sentence of life without parole under
    section 190.5(b) would raise serious constitutional concerns if it were imposed
    pursuant to a statutory presumption in favor of such punishment.
    At the core of Miller’s rationale is the proposition — articulated in Roper,
    amplified in Graham, and further elaborated in Miller itself — that
    constitutionally significant differences between children and adults “diminish the
    penological justifications for imposing the harshest sentences on juvenile
    offenders.” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2465].) The high
    court said in plain terms that because of “children’s diminished culpability and
    heightened capacity for change, we think appropriate occasions for sentencing
    juveniles to this harshest possible penalty will be uncommon.” (Id. at p. __ [132
    S.Ct. at p. 2469].) “That is especially so because of the great difficulty . . . of
    28
    distinguishing at this early age between ‘the juvenile offender whose crime
    reflects unfortunate yet transient immaturity, and the rare juvenile offender whose
    crime reflects irreparable corruption.’ [Citations.]” (Ibid.)
    Reading section 190.5(b) to establish a presumption in favor of life without
    parole — i.e., a rule that “16- or 17-year-olds who commit special circumstance
    murder must be sentenced to LWOP, unless the court, in its discretion, finds good
    reason to choose the less severe sentence of 25 years to life” (
    Guinn, supra
    , 28
    Cal.App.4th at p. 1141, italics in original) — is in serious tension with the
    foregoing statements in Miller. As the Court of Appeal explained in Moffett’s
    case: “Treating [life without parole] as the default sentence takes the premise in
    Miller that such sentences should be rarities and turns that premise on its head,
    instead placing the burden on a youthful defendant to affirmatively demonstrate
    that he or she deserves an opportunity for parole.”
    The Attorney General resists this conclusion on several grounds. First, she
    contends that a presumptive sentence of life without parole under section 190.5(b)
    does not raise constitutional concerns under Miller because the statute limits its
    applicability to 16 and 17 year olds who are convicted of special circumstance
    murder. But neither the limitation to older juveniles nor the limitation to certain
    types of murder, singly or together, eliminates the constitutional concerns raised
    by the Guinn presumption.
    “Drawing the line at 18 years of age is subject, of course, to the objections
    always raised against categorical rules. The qualities that distinguish juveniles
    from adults do not disappear when an individual turns 18. By the same token,
    some under 18 have already attained a level of maturity some adults will never
    reach.” 
    (Roper, supra
    , 543 U.S. at p. 574.) But “[t]he age of 18 is the point where
    society draws the line for many purposes between childhood and adulthood”
    (ibid.), and that is the line the high court has drawn in its Eighth Amendment
    29
    jurisprudence. The high court in Miller, which considered two cases involving 14
    year olds convicted of murder, could have limited its concerns about juveniles’
    lessened culpability and greater capacity for reform to younger juveniles. But
    Miller declined to adopt any such limitation, instead citing evidence that
    developmental immaturity persists through late adolescence. 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567
    U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2464], citing Steinberg & Scott, Less Guilty by
    Reason of Adolescence: Developmental Immaturity, Diminished Responsibility,
    and Juvenile Death Penalty (2003) 58 Am. Psychologist 1009, 1014; see
    
    Caballero, supra
    , 55 Cal.4th at p. 266.) The high court reasoned that persons
    under the age of 18, as a category, have distinctive attributes that typically counsel
    against imposition of life without parole. (Miller, at pp. __–__ [132 S.Ct. at
    pp. 2464–2466].) Of course, a sentencing court has discretion under Miller to
    decide on an individualized basis whether a 16- or 17-year-old offender is a “ ‘rare
    juvenile offender whose crime reflects irreparable corruption.’ ” (Id. at p. __ [132
    S.Ct. at p. 2469]; see 
    id. at p.
    __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2467] [“sentencer” may take
    account of difference between “the 17-year-old and the 14-year-old”].) But to say
    that all 16 or 17 year olds subject to section 190.5(b) presumptively deserve a
    sentence of life without parole is in serious tension with Miller’s categorical
    reasoning about the differences between juveniles and adults.
    Further, Miller made clear that its concerns about juveniles’ lessened
    culpability and greater capacity for reform have force independent of the nature of
    their crimes. Of course, the nature of the crime is a factor for the “sentencer” to
    consider in each case. (See 
    Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2467]
    [“sentencer” may take account of difference between “the shooter and the
    accomplice”].) But Miller said “the distinctive attributes of youth diminish the
    penological justifications for imposing the harshest sentences on juvenile
    offenders, even when they commit terrible crimes.” (Id. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at
    30
    p. 2465], italics added.) And in declining to limit Graham’s reasoning to
    nonhomicide offenses, the high court explained that “none of what [Graham] said
    about children—about their distinctive (and transitory) mental traits and
    environmental vulnerabilities—is crime-specific. Those features are evident in the
    same way, and to the same degree, when . . . a botched robbery turns into a killing.
    So Graham’s reasoning implicates any life-without-parole sentence imposed on a
    juvenile . . . .” (Miller, at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2465], italics added; see
    
    Caballero, supra
    , 55 Cal.4th at p. 267.) Graham and Roper likewise indicated
    that the mitigating features of youth can be dispositively relevant, whether the
    crime is a nonhomicide offense or a heinous murder punishable by death if
    committed by an adult. (See 
    Graham, supra
    , 560 U.S. at p. 78 [“an ‘unacceptable
    likelihood exists that the brutality or cold-blooded nature of any particular crime
    would overpower mitigating arguments based on youth as a matter of course, even
    where the juvenile offender’s objective immaturity, vulnerability, and lack of true
    depravity should require a [lesser] sentence’ ”], quoting 
    Roper, supra
    , 543 U.S. at
    p. 573.) Although section 190.5(b) does not apply to every murder offense, it
    applies to a broad and diverse range of first degree murder offenses. (See Pen.
    Code, §§ 190.2, 190.25.) To presume that all such offenses committed by 16 and
    17 year olds merit a presumptive penalty of life without parole cannot be easily
    reconciled with Miller’s principle that “the distinctive attributes of youth [that]
    diminish the penological justifications for imposing the harshest sentences on
    juvenile offenders” are not “crime-specific.” (Miller, at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at
    p. 2465].)
    In sum, while requiring “factfinders” in individual cases “to take into
    account the differences among defendants and crimes” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at
    p. __, fn. 8 [132 S.Ct. at p. 2469, fn. 8]), Miller nowhere suggested that
    legislatures may presume life without parole to be the proper punishment for entire
    31
    categories of juvenile offenders or offenses. Instead, Miller made clear that its
    concerns about imposing life without parole have applicability whatever the age or
    crime of a juvenile offender. A presumption in favor of life without parole for a
    subgroup of juveniles who commit any one of a subgroup of crimes would raise a
    serious constitutional question under Miller.
    Second, the Attorney General contends that a presumption in favor of life
    without parole under section 190.5(b) presents no constitutional difficulty because
    the statute affords the sentencing court discretion to consider the defendant’s age,
    among other potentially mitigating factors, and to impose a sentence of 25 years to
    life if appropriate. It is true that a presumption in favor of life without parole does
    not eliminate a trial court’s discretion to make an individualized sentencing
    decision. (See 
    Ybarra, supra
    , 166 Cal.App.4th at p. 1089 [§ 190.5(b) “ ‘evidences
    a preference for the LWOP penalty.’ [¶] Despite that statutory preference, section
    190.5, subdivision (b) requires ‘a proper exercise of discretion in choosing
    whether to grant leniency and impose the lesser penalty of 25 years to life for 16-
    or 17-year-old special circumstance murderers.’ ”], quoting 
    Guinn, supra
    , 28
    Cal.App.4th at pp. 1145, 1149.) But Guinn did not simply hold that sentencing
    courts have discretion. It concluded that section 190.5(b) expresses a “preference”
    for the imposition of life without parole; in other words, such a sentence is the
    “generally mandatory” punishment for juveniles convicted of special circumstance
    murder and “the court’s discretion is concomitantly circumscribed to that extent.”
    (
    Guinn, supra
    , 28 Cal.App.4th at p. 1142, italics added.)
    In this context, as in others, how a legal inquiry conceptualizes the default
    rule and burden of persuasion can be dispositive when a court is authorized to
    make an all-things-considered judgment. In the context of California’s Three
    Strikes law, for example, we have held that a court’s discretionary power to strike
    prior felony convictions “in furtherance of justice” (§ 1385) is “carefully
    32
    circumscribe[d]” by a preference in the Three Strikes law against striking prior
    convictions. (People v. Carmony (2004) 
    33 Cal. 4th 367
    , 378.) Because of this
    presumption, we have said that trial courts’ decisions to strike a prior conviction
    should be “ ‘extraordinary.’ ” (Ibid.) Similarly here, it is one thing to say that a
    court, confronting two permissible sentencing options, may impose the harsher
    sentence if it finds that sentence justified by the circumstances. It is quite another
    to say that a court, bound by a presumption in favor of the harsher sentence, must
    impose that sentence unless it finds good reasons not to do so. When the choice
    between two sentences must be made by weighing intangible factors, a
    presumption in favor of one sentence can be decisive in many cases.
    In Graham, the high court construed the Eighth Amendment to prohibit a
    sentence of life without parole for juvenile nonhomicide offenders because “ ‘[t]he
    differences between juvenile and adult offenders are too marked and well
    understood to risk allowing a youthful person to receive’ a sentence of life without
    parole for a nonhomicide crime ‘despite insufficient culpability.’ ” (
    Graham, supra
    , 560 U.S. at p. 78, quoting 
    Roper, supra
    , 543 U.S. at pp. 572–573.) To
    address the same risk in homicide cases, Miller requires sentencing courts to
    undertake a careful individualized inquiry before imposing life without parole on
    juvenile homicide offenders. 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at pp. __, __ [132 S.Ct. at
    pp. 2468, 2469.) Given Miller’s conception of a proper individualized sentencing
    inquiry, a serious constitutional concern would arise if we were to interpret section
    190.5(b) as a rule that “circumscribe[s]” the court’s discretion by presuming “[i]n
    the first instance” that life without parole is the appropriate sentence for special
    circumstance murder committed by a 16- or 17-year-old juvenile. (
    Guinn, supra
    ,
    28 Cal.App.4th at p. 1142.)
    Third, the Attorney General claims that California’s sentencing scheme
    already “makes LWOP terms for minors uncommon in fact” notwithstanding the
    33
    Guinn presumption. In support of this claim, she relies on the following passage
    from a footnote in Miller: “Where mandatory sentencing does not itself account
    for the number of juveniles serving life-without-parole terms, the evidence we
    have of practice supports our holding. Fifteen jurisdictions make life without
    parole discretionary for juveniles. See Alabama Brief 25 (listing 12 States); Cal.
    Penal Code Ann. § 190.5(b) (West 2008); Ind. Code § 35-50-2-3(b) (2011); N.M.
    Stat. §§ 31-18-13(B), 31-18-14, 31-18-15.2 (2010). According to available data,
    only about 15% of all juvenile life-without-parole sentences come from those 15
    jurisdictions, while 85% come from the 29 mandatory ones. [Citations.] That
    figure indicates that when given the choice, sentencers impose life without parole
    on children relatively rarely.” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __, fn. 10 [132 S.Ct.
    at p. 2472, fn. 10], citing Human Rights Watch, State Distribution of Youth
    Offenders Serving Juvenile Life Without Parole (JLWOP) (2009)
     [as of May 5, 2014] (Human Rights Watch
    JLWOP Rep.).)
    As an initial matter, this passage in Miller, while considering the 15
    nonmandatory sentencing jurisdictions in the aggregate, said nothing specific
    about California. In order to reliably determine whether the discretion afforded by
    section 190.5(b) has resulted only rarely in juvenile life without parole sentences,
    one would need to know not only the number of such sentences meted out in
    California but also the number of cases in which life without parole was
    considered and, in the exercise of the court’s discretion, rejected.
    To the extent they prove anything, the statistics from Miller support
    defendants’ point that a statutory presumption in favor of life without parole
    significantly increases the likelihood that such a sentence will be imposed. It is
    true that the 15 states with nonmandatory sentencing laws, including California,
    34
    accounted for 15% or a total of 376 of the 2,589 juveniles in the United States
    serving life without parole sentences in 2009. 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __,
    fn. 10 [132 S.Ct. at p. 2472, fn. 10], citing Human Rights Watch JLWOP Rep.)
    But California — apparently the only jurisdiction whose discretionary sentencing
    law incorporates a presumption in favor of life without parole — accounted for
    over 70% or a total of 265 of the 376 life without parole sentences in those 15
    states (see Human Rights Watch JLWOP Rep.), even though California accounted
    for only 43% of the combined juvenile population of those 15 states in 2009 (see
    U.S. Dept. of Justice, Off. of Juvenile Justice and Delinquency Prevention, Easy
    Access to Juvenile Populations: 1990–2012  [as of May 5, 2014] (OJJDP Juvenile Populations)). Thus, the vast
    majority of discretionary life without parole sentences imposed on juveniles are
    imposed in California, even though the juvenile population in the 14 other
    discretionary sentencing states taken together is much larger than the juvenile
    population in California. These data suggest that a statutory presumption in favor
    of life without parole makes a significant practical difference.
    The Attorney General finds it significant that “California (with close to
    fifteen percent of the nation’s population) plus fourteen other states produced just
    fifteen percent of all juveniles sentenced to LWOP terms.” But in 2009,
    California’s 265 juvenile offenders serving life without parole accounted for
    10.4% of all such juvenile offenders in the 44 states that authorize the sentence
    (see Human Rights Watch JLWOP Report), which is roughly comparable to
    California’s 13.3% share of the total juvenile population in those 44 states in 2009
    (see OJJDP Juvenile Populations). By contrast, the 14 other discretionary
    sentencing states taken together had 17.8% of the total juvenile population in those
    44 states (see ibid.) and a mere 4.4% of all juvenile offenders serving life without
    parole (see Human Rights Watch JLWOP Rep.). In sum, the Attorney General’s
    35
    reliance on the data cited in Miller does not enable us to confidently conclude that
    the discretion afforded by section 190.5(b), when constrained by a presumption in
    favor of life without parole, has resulted in imposition of life without parole only
    on “ ‘the rare juvenile offender whose crime reflects irreparable corruption.’ ”
    
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2469].)
    Finally, the Attorney General argues that the recent enactment of Penal
    Code, section 1170, subdivision (d)(2) (hereafter section 1170(d)(2)) eliminates
    any constitutional problems arising from the Guinn presumption. This statute
    provides: “When a defendant who was under 18 years of age at the time of the
    commission of the offense for which the defendant was sentenced to imprisonment
    for life without the possibility of parole has served at least 15 years of that
    sentence, the defendant may submit to the sentencing court a petition for recall and
    resentencing.” (§ 1170, subd. (d)(2)(A)(i).) The petition must include, among
    other things, a “statement describing his or her remorse and work towards
    rehabilitation.” (§ 1170, subd. (d)(2)(B).) “If the court finds by a preponderance
    of the evidence that the statements in the petition are true, the court shall hold a
    hearing to consider whether to recall the sentence and commitment previously
    ordered and to resentence the defendant in the same manner as if the defendant
    had not previously been sentenced, provided that the new sentence, if any, is not
    greater than the initial sentence.” (§ 1170, subd. (d)(2)(E).)
    “The factors that the court may consider when determining whether to
    recall and resentence include, but are not limited to, the following: [¶] (i) The
    defendant was convicted pursuant to felony murder or aiding and abetting murder
    provisions of law. [¶] (ii) The defendant does not have juvenile felony
    adjudications for assault or other felony crimes with a significant potential for
    personal harm to victims prior to the offense for which the sentence is being
    considered for recall. [¶] (iii) The defendant committed the offense with at least
    36
    one adult codefendant. [¶] (iv) Prior to the offense for which the sentence is
    being considered for recall, the defendant had insufficient adult support or
    supervision and had suffered from psychological or physical trauma, or significant
    stress. [¶] (v) The defendant suffers from cognitive limitations due to mental
    illness, developmental disabilities, or other factors that did not constitute a
    defense, but influenced the defendant’s involvement in the offense. [¶] (vi) The
    defendant has performed acts that tend to indicate rehabilitation or the potential for
    rehabilitation, including, but not limited to, availing himself or herself of
    rehabilitative, educational, or vocational programs, if those programs have been
    available at his or her classification level and facility, using self-study for self-
    improvement, or showing evidence of remorse. [¶] (vii) The defendant has
    maintained family ties or connections with others through letter writing, calls, or
    visits, or has eliminated contact with individuals outside of prison who are
    currently involved with crime. [¶] (viii) The defendant has had no disciplinary
    actions for violent activities in the last five years in which the defendant was
    determined to be the aggressor.” (§ 1170, subd. (d)(2)(F).)
    If the court declines to recall the defendant’s sentence, the defendant may
    try again after having served 20 years. (§ 1170, subd. (d)(2)(H).) If again
    unsuccessful, the defendant may file a third and final petition after having served
    24 years. (Ibid.)
    As an initial matter, section 1170(d)(2) has no bearing on Moffett’s case.
    Because the victim of Moffett’s homicide offense was “a public safety official,”
    Moffett is ineligible for resentencing under section 1170(d)(2). (§ 1170,
    subd. (d)(2)(A)(ii).) But even for juvenile offenders such as Gutierrez, the
    potential for relief under section 1170(d)(2) does not eliminate the serious
    constitutional doubts arising from a presumption in favor of life without parole
    under section 190.5(b) because the same questionable presumption would apply at
    37
    resentencing. The statute makes clear that if the sentencing court grants an
    inmate’s petition for a resentencing hearing, the hearing must be conducted “in the
    same manner as if the defendant had not previously been sentenced.” (§ 1170,
    subd. (d)(2)(G).) Thus, if section 190.5(b) establishes a presumption in favor of
    life without parole, a court acting pursuant to section 1170, subdivision (d)(2)(G)
    would be required to apply the same presumption in evaluating the circumstances
    at resentencing (only this time, unlike at the initial sentencing, the defendant
    would have no guarantee of counsel).
    Nor does the fact that section 1170(d)(2) provides a potential mechanism
    for resentencing after 15 to 24 years mean that the initial sentence “is thus no
    longer effectively a sentence of life without the possibility of parole,” as the
    Attorney General’s briefing contends. A sentence of life without parole under
    section 190.5(b) remains fully effective after the enactment of section 1170(d)(2).
    That is why section 1170(d)(2) sets forth a scheme for recalling the sentence and
    resentencing the defendant. As the Attorney General notes, section 1170(d)(2)
    provides juvenile offenders convicted of special circumstance murder with “three
    opportunities to have their sentences of life without the possibility of parole
    changed to a sentence of 25 years to life.” (Italics added.)
    The Attorney General contends that section 1170(d)(2) removes life
    without parole sentences for juvenile offenders from the ambit of Miller’s
    concerns because the statute provides a meaningful opportunity for such offenders
    to obtain release. In support of this contention, the Attorney General relies on a
    “cf.” citation in Miller to language in Graham. (See 
    Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at
    p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2469] [“Cf. Graham, 560 U.S., at __, 130 S.Ct., at 2030 (‘A
    State is not required to guarantee eventual freedom,’ but must provide ‘some
    meaningful opportunity to obtain release based on demonstrated maturity and
    rehabilitation’).”]; see also 
    Graham, supra
    , 560 U.S. at p. 75 [“It is for the State,
    38
    in the first instance, to explore the means and mechanisms for compliance.”].)
    However, Graham spoke of providing juvenile offenders with a “meaningful
    opportunity to obtain release” as a constitutionally required alternative to — not as
    an after-the-fact corrective for — “making the judgment at the outset that those
    offenders never will be fit to reenter society.” (Graham, at p. 75, italics added.)
    Likewise, Miller’s “cf.” citation to the “meaningful opportunity” language in
    Graham occurred in the context of prohibiting “imposition of that harshest prison
    sentence” on juveniles under a mandatory scheme. (Miller, at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at
    p. 2469].) Neither Miller nor Graham indicated that an opportunity to recall a
    sentence of life without parole 15 to 24 years into the future would somehow make
    more reliable or justifiable the imposition of that sentence and its underlying
    judgment of the offender’s incorrigibility “at the outset.” (Graham, at p. 75.)
    Indeed, the high court in Graham explained that a juvenile offender’s
    subsequent failure to rehabilitate while serving a sentence of life without parole
    cannot retroactively justify imposition of the sentence in the first instance: “Even
    if the State’s judgment that Graham was incorrigible were later corroborated by
    prison misbehavior or failure to mature, the sentence was still disproportionate
    because that judgment was made at the outset.” (
    Graham, supra
    , 560 U.S. at
    p. 73, italics added.) By the same logic, it is doubtful that the potential to recall a
    life without parole sentence based on a future demonstration of rehabilitation can
    make such a sentence any more valid when it was imposed. If anything, a
    decision to recall the sentence pursuant to section 1170(d)(2) is a recognition that
    the initial judgment of incorrigibility underlying the imposition of life without
    parole turned out to be erroneous. Consistent with Graham, Miller repeatedly
    made clear that the sentencing authority must address this risk of error by
    considering how children are different and how those differences counsel against a
    sentence of life without parole “before imposing a particular penalty.” 
    (Miller, 39 supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2471], italics added; see 
    id. at pp.
    __, __
    [132 S.Ct. at pp. 2469, 2475].)
    In sum, construing section 190.5(b) to establish a presumption in favor of
    life without parole raises serious constitutional concerns under the reasoning of
    Miller and the body of precedent on which Miller relied. The recent enactment of
    section 1170(d)(2) does not eliminate those concerns. Because section 190.5(b) is
    reasonably susceptible to two interpretations, we will adopt the construction that
    renders it “free from doubt as to its constitutionality.” (Conservatorship of
    
    Wendland, supra
    , 26 Cal.4th at p. 548.) We hold that section 190.5(b) confers
    discretion on the sentencing court to impose either life without parole or a term of
    25 years to life on a 16- or 17-year-old juvenile convicted of special circumstance
    murder, with no presumption in favor of life without parole. In light of this
    holding, we disapprove People v. 
    Guinn, supra
    , 
    28 Cal. App. 4th 1130
    , and its
    progeny.
    C.
    Defendants contend that even when section 190.5(b) is not construed to
    establish a presumption in favor of life without parole, the imposition of life
    without parole is unconstitutional because the statute does not allow the
    sentencing court to consider the distinctive attributes of youth discussed by the
    high court in Miller. We disagree. Section 190.5(b) authorizes and indeed
    requires consideration of the Miller factors.
    Under section 190.5(b), a sentencing court must consider the aggravating
    and mitigating factors enumerated in Penal Code section 190.3 and the California
    Rules of Court. (See 
    Ybarra, supra
    , 166 Cal.App.4th at pp. 1089–1093.) Section
    190.5(b) does not expressly direct the sentencing court to consider those factors,
    but “since all discretionary authority is contextual, those factors that direct similar
    sentencing decisions are relevant, including ‘the nature and circumstances of the
    40
    offense, the defendant’s appreciation of and attitude toward the offense, or his
    traits of character as evidenced by his behavior and demeanor at the trial.’ ”
    (People v. Superior Court (Alvarez) (1997) 
    14 Cal. 4th 968
    , 978.)
    The factors that a sentencing court must consider under section 190.3
    include “[t]he age of the defendant at the time of the crime.” (Pen. Code, § 190.3,
    factor (i).) We have said that this factor permits the court to consider not simply a
    defendant’s age but also “any age-related matter suggested by the evidence or by
    common experience or morality that might reasonably inform the choice of
    penalty.” (People v. Lucky (1988) 
    45 Cal. 3d 259
    , 302 (Lucky).) Lucky did not
    involve a juvenile offender, but as relevant here, Lucky confirms that section
    190.3, subdivision (i) provides a basis for the court to consider that “ ‘youth is
    more than a chronological fact’ ” and to take into account any mitigating relevance
    of “age and the wealth of characteristics and circumstances attendant to it,” as
    Miller requires. 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2467].)
    Miller discussed a range of factors relevant to a sentencer’s determination
    of whether a particular defendant is a “ ‘rare juvenile offender whose crime
    reflects irreparable corruption.’ ” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at
    p. 2469].) As noted at oral argument by counsel for amicus curiae Juvenile Law
    Center, the high court in Miller provided a “recap” of those factors, grouping them
    into five categories. (Id. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2468]; see ante, at p. 26.) We
    understand Miller to require a sentencing court to admit and consider relevant
    evidence of the following:
    First, a court must consider a juvenile offender’s “chronological age and its
    hallmark features—among them, immaturity, impetuosity, and failure to
    appreciate risks and consequences.” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at
    p. 2468]; see, e.g., 
    ibid. [“To be sure,
    Jackson learned on the way to the video
    store that his friend Shields was carrying a gun, but his age could well have
    41
    affected his calculation of the risk that posed, as well as his willingness to walk
    away at that point.”].) Miller observed that “ ‘developments in psychology and
    brain science continue to show fundamental differences between juvenile and
    adult minds,’ ” and that “those findings—of transient rashness, proclivity for
    risk, and inability to assess consequences—both lessened a child’s ‘moral
    culpability’ and enhanced the prospect that, as the years go by and neurological
    development occurs, his ‘ “deficiencies will be reformed.” ’ ” (Id. at pp. __–__
    [132 S.Ct. at pp. 2464–2465]; see 
    Roper, supra
    , 543 U.S. at p. 573 [“It is
    difficult even for expert psychologists to differentiate between the juvenile
    offender whose crime reflects unfortunate yet transient immaturity, and the rare
    juvenile offender whose crime reflects irreparable corruption.”].) Miller further
    noted that “the science and social science supporting [these] conclusions have
    become even stronger” in recent years. (Miller, at p. __, fn. 5 [132 S.Ct. at
    p. 2464, fn. 5].)
    Second, a sentencing court must consider any evidence or other information
    in the record regarding “the family and home environment that surrounds [the
    juvenile]—and from which he cannot usually extricate himself—no matter how
    brutal or dysfunctional.” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2468].)
    Relevant “environmental vulnerabilities” include evidence of childhood abuse or
    neglect, familial drug or alcohol abuse, lack of adequate parenting or education,
    prior exposure to violence, and susceptibility to psychological damage or
    emotional disturbance. (Id. at pp. __, __, __–__ [132 S.Ct. at pp. 2465, 2467,
    2468–2469].)
    Third, a court must consider any evidence or other information in the
    record regarding “the circumstances of the homicide offense, including the extent
    of [the juvenile defendant’s] participation in the conduct and the way familial and
    peer pressures may have affected him.” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132
    42
    S.Ct. at p. 2468]; see 
    ibid. [“ ‘a juvenile
    offender who did not kill or intend to kill
    has a twice diminished moral culpability’ ”].) Also relevant is whether substance
    abuse played a role in the juvenile offender’s commission of the crime. (Id. at
    p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2469].)
    Fourth, a court must consider any evidence or other information in the
    record as to whether the offender “might have been charged and convicted of a
    lesser offense if not for incompetencies associated with youth—for example, his
    inability to deal with police officers or prosecutors (including on a plea agreement)
    or his incapacity to assist his own attorneys. See, e.g., Graham, 560 U.S. at 
    —, 130 S. Ct., at 2032
    (‘[T]he features that distinguish juveniles from adults also put
    them at a significant disadvantage in criminal proceedings’); J.D.B. v. North
    Carolina, 564 U.S. —, —, 
    131 S. Ct. 2394
    , 2400–2401 (2011) (discussing
    children’s responses to interrogation). ” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132
    S.Ct. at p. 2468].)
    Finally, a sentencing court must consider any evidence or other information
    in the record bearing on “the possibility of rehabilitation.” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567
    U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2468]; see 
    id. at p.
    __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2464] [“[A]
    child’s character is not as ‘well formed’ as an adult’s; his traits are ‘less fixed’ and
    his actions less likely to be ‘evidence of irretrievabl[e] deprav[ity].’ ”].) The
    extent or absence of “past criminal history” is relevant here. (Id. at p. __ [132
    S.Ct. at p. 2469].)
    Although courts elsewhere have enumerated or categorized these factors in
    different ways, we note that the emerging body of post-Miller case law has
    uniformly held that a sentencing court must consider the factors discussed above
    before imposing life without parole on a juvenile homicide offender. (See State v.
    Henderson (Ala. 2013) __ So.3d __, __ [
    2013 WL 4873077
    , at p. *21]; State v.
    Null (Iowa 2013) 
    836 N.W.2d 41
    , 74; Parker v. State (Miss. 2013) 
    119 So. 3d 987
    ,
    43
    995–996, 998 & fn. 18; State v. Hart (Mo. 2013) 
    404 S.W.3d 232
    , 241;
    Commonwealth v. Batts (Pa. 2013) 
    66 A.3d 286
    , 297; Bear Cloud v. State (Wyo.
    2013) 
    294 P.3d 36
    , 47; People v. Carp (Mich.Ct.App. 2012) 
    828 N.W.2d 685
    ,
    720; Daugherty v. State (Fla.Dist.Ct.App. 2012) 
    96 So. 3d 1076
    , 1079; State v.
    Fletcher (La.Ct.App. 2013) 
    112 So. 3d 1031
    , 1036–1037; see also Williams v.
    Virgin Islands (V.I. 2013) __ V.I. __, __ [
    2013 WL 5913305
    at p. *8]; cf. Conley
    v. State (Ind. 2012) 
    972 N.E.2d 864
    , 875 [upholding a discretionary life without
    parole sentence with detailed findings].) This approach complements our recent
    holding in Caballero that a trial court must consider many of the same factors
    when imposing a sentence on a juvenile nonhomicide offender. (See 
    Caballero, supra
    , 55 Cal.4th at pp. 268–269.)
    In sum, we hold that the trial court must consider all relevant evidence
    bearing on the “distinctive attributes of youth” discussed in Miller and how those
    attributes “diminish the penological justifications for imposing the harshest
    sentences on juvenile offenders.” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at
    p. 2465].) To be sure, not every factor will necessarily be relevant in every case.
    For example, if there is no indication in the presentence report, in the parties’
    submissions, or in other court filings that a juvenile offender has had a troubled
    childhood, then that factor cannot have mitigating relevance. But Miller
    “require[s] [the sentencer] to take into account how children are different, and
    how those differences counsel against irrevocably sentencing them to a lifetime
    in prison.” (Id. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2469].)
    44
    III.
    We now determine the proper disposition of these cases in light of the
    principles above. In each case, the record indicates that the trial court understood
    it had a degree of discretion in sentencing the defendant. However, both courts
    imposed life without parole at a time when Guinn was the prevailing authority.
    In Moffett’s case, the trial court expressly acknowledged Guinn’s holding when it
    framed the pertinent question as whether it should “deviate from the statutory
    requirement of life without the possibility of parole and sentence Mr. Moffett to
    a determinate term of 25 years to life.” In Gutierrez’s case, the trial court did
    not explicitly refer to a presumption in favor of life without parole. But, as
    the Attorney General notes in her briefing, the “presumption . . . had previously
    been undisturbed for over 20 years.” Absent evidence to the contrary, we
    presume that the trial court knew and applied the governing law. (See People v.
    Thomas (2011) 
    52 Cal. 4th 336
    , 361.) To be clear, we do not fault the trial
    courts in these cases; they dutifully applied the law as it stood at the time.
    But we conclude that neither court made its sentencing decision with awareness
    of the full scope of discretion conferred by section 190.5(b) or with the guidance
    set forth in Miller and this opinion for the proper exercise of its discretion.
    “Defendants are entitled to sentencing decisions made in the exercise of the
    ‘informed discretion’ of the sentencing court. (See United States v. Tucker (1972)
    
    404 U.S. 443
    , 447 [
    30 L. Ed. 2d 592
    , 596, 92S.Ct. 589]; Townsend v. Burke (1948)
    
    334 U.S. 736
    , 741 [
    92 L. Ed. 1690
    , 1693, 
    68 S. Ct. 1252
    ].) A court which is
    unaware of the scope of its discretionary powers can no more exercise that
    ‘informed discretion’ than one whose sentence is or may have been based on
    misinformation regarding a material aspect of a defendant’s record.” (People v.
    Belmontes (1983) 
    34 Cal. 3d 335
    , 348, fn. 8.) In such circumstances, we have held
    that the appropriate remedy is to remand for resentencing unless the record
    45
    “clearly indicate[s]” that the trial court would have reached the same conclusion
    “even if it had been aware that it had such discretion.” (Ibid.; see People v.
    Rodriguez (1998) 
    17 Cal. 4th 253
    , 257; 
    Romero, supra
    , 13 Cal.4th at p. 530,
    fn. 13.) Although the trial courts in these cases understood that they had some
    discretion in sentencing, the records do not clearly indicate that they would have
    imposed the same sentence had they been aware of the full scope of their
    discretion. Because the trial courts operated under a governing presumption in
    favor of life without parole, we cannot say with confidence what sentence they
    would have imposed absent the presumption. Accordingly, we remand both cases
    for resentencing.
    CONCLUSION
    Juveniles who commit crimes that reflect impetuosity, irresponsibility,
    inability to assess risks and consequences, vulnerability to peer pressure, substance
    abuse, or pathologies traceable to an unstable childhood cannot and should not
    escape punishment. And when the crime is “a vicious murder,” it is “beyond
    question” that a juvenile offender “deserve[s] severe punishment.” 
    (Miller, supra
    ,
    567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2469].) Because Moffett and Gutierrez have
    been convicted of special circumstance murder, each will receive a life sentence.
    (§ 190.5(b).) The question is whether each can be deemed, at the time of
    sentencing, to be irreparably corrupt, beyond redemption, and thus unfit ever to
    reenter society, notwithstanding the “diminished culpability and greater prospects
    for reform” that ordinarily distinguish juveniles from adults. (Miller, at p. __ [132
    S.Ct. at p. 2464].) Because the trial courts here decided that question without
    proper guidance on the sentencing discretion conferred by section 190.5(b) and the
    46
    considerations that must inform the exercise of that discretion, we remand both
    cases for proceedings not inconsistent with this opinion.
    LIU, J.
    WE CONCUR: CANTIL-SAKAUYE, C. J.
    WERDEGAR, J.
    CHIN, J.
    KENNARD, J.*
    *      Retired Associate Justice of the Supreme Court, assigned by the Chief
    Justice pursuant to article VI, section 6 of the California Constitution.
    47
    CONCURRING OPINION BY CORRIGAN, J.
    I agree with the majority’s conclusion that Penal Code section 190.5,
    subdivision (b) (section 190.5(b)) imposes no presumption in favor of life without
    parole. So construed, the statute fully satisfies current federal constitutional
    concerns. I write separately to stress that California’s individualized, discretionary
    sentencing scheme is very different from the mandatory life without parole
    sentence the United States Supreme Court addressed in Miller v. Alabama (2012)
    567 U.S. __ [
    132 S. Ct. 2455
    ] (Miller).
    Discretionary decisions occur at multiple steps in our state’s process. First,
    the prosecutor exercises discretion in charging a minor as an adult. Next, unless
    the crime is one for which trial in criminal court is prescribed (see Welf. & Inst.
    Code, § 602, subd. (b)),1 the court determines whether the minor is unfit to be
    tried in juvenile court. Finally, if a minor is tried and convicted as an adult, the
    court makes an individualized determination about the appropriate sentence in
    light of all the evidence presented.
    In Miller, the Supreme Court commented that judicial discretion regarding
    a minor’s transfer to adult court is of “limited utility” if the court receives only
    1      Trial as an adult is automatic for special circumstance murder only if the
    prosecutor alleges the minor personally killed the victim. (Welf. & Inst. Code,
    § 602, subd. (b)(1).)
    1
    partial information about the minor and circumstances of the offense. 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2474].) California’s transfer process
    entails a substantial inquiry, however. When a motion for transfer is made, the
    court is required to order an investigation and written report on the minor’s
    behavioral patterns and social history. (Welf. & Inst. Code, § 707, subd. (c).) The
    court must also consider “any other relevant evidence” the minor wishes to
    submit. (Ibid.) Although there is a presumption of unfitness for extremely violent
    felonies such as murder, it is overcome if the court finds the minor amenable to
    juvenile court treatment based on an evaluation of (1) the degree of criminal
    sophistication the minor exhibits, (2) the possibility of rehabilitation, (3) the
    minor’s history of delinquency, (4) the success of previous attempts at
    rehabilitation, and (5) the circumstances and gravity of the alleged offense. (Ibid.)
    Miller also criticized transfer-stage discretion as a poor substitute for
    discretion at posttrial sentencing. (See 
    Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct.
    at pp. 2474-2475].) But in California the discretion available to a juvenile court in
    the transfer process is not a substitute for, but a supplement to, the robust
    discretion exercised at sentencing. Miller was addressing states in which the only
    discretionary review of a minor’s background and offense occurs at a pretrial
    fitness hearing. In those states, once a decision has been made to try a minor as an
    adult, a life-without-parole sentence is mandatory if the minor is found guilty of
    the charged offense. (See Miller, at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2474].) Evidence
    presented at the transfer hearing cannot be offered in mitigation at sentencing.
    (Ibid.) The situation is quite different in California. Courts in our state must
    consider all relevant circumstances in determining the appropriate sentence for a
    minor. When a minor between the ages of 16 and 18 is convicted of special
    circumstance murder, the court has discretion to impose a sentence of 25 years to
    life imprisonment or life without possibility of parole. (§ 190.5(b).) The harsher
    sentence is not available for any defendant who was under age 16 when the crime
    was committed. (Ibid.) This reality again sets California quite apart from the
    2
    states mentioned in Miller that expose minors to life without parole at “any age—
    be it 17 or 14 or 10 or 6.” (Miller, at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2473 & fn. 14].) Even
    for older teenagers, no mandatory sentence is ever required in California.
    Accordingly, while I agree that the concerns expressed in Miller are
    important, careful attention should be given to how a defendant’s age and maturity
    actually factor into each case when the court exercises its discretion under
    section 190.5(b). The special attributes of youth mentioned in Miller may well be
    present in the case of some minors. There will be other minors, however, who
    have grown beyond them. It is because each case is different, and should be
    treated accordingly, that we repose confidence in the discretion of the court to
    impose a sentence that is appropriate in light of all relevant circumstances.
    Whether “appropriate occasions” for sentencing juveniles to life without parole
    will be uncommon is not a prognostication that should be made globally and in the
    abstract. (See maj. opn. ante, at pp. 27, 28, quoting 
    Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at
    p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2469].) The Miller majority made this comment in the
    context of two 14-year-olds, one of whom had a delinquency history comprised of
    no more than truancy and one instance of “ ‘second-degree criminal mischief.’ ”
    (Miller, at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2469].) As noted, the court was also addressing
    very different state statutes, which imposed mandatory lifetime sentences on much
    younger children whose individual circumstances were never considered except at
    a limited pretrial fitness hearing.
    The appropriate sentence for any particular minor remains a question for
    the sentencing court. As the Miller majority itself observed: “Our decision does
    not categorically bar a penalty for a class of offenders or type of crime . . . .
    Instead, it mandates only that a sentencer follow a certain process—considering an
    offender’s youth and attendant characteristics—before imposing a particular
    penalty.” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2471].) We make clear
    today that this process is fully embraced in California. The majority opinion here
    should not be read to suggest otherwise.
    3
    CORRIGAN, J.
    WE CONCUR:
    CANTIL-SAKAUYE, C. J.
    BAXTER, J.
    CHIN, J.
    4
    CONCURRING OPINION BY LIU, J.
    In light of Miller v. Alabama (2012) 567 U.S. __ [
    132 S. Ct. 2455
    ] (Miller),
    the court today holds that Penal Code “section 190.5(b) confers discretion on the
    sentencing court to impose either life without parole or a term of 25 years to life
    on a 16- or 17-year-old juvenile convicted of special circumstance murder, with no
    presumption in favor of life without parole.” (Maj. opn., ante, at p. 40.) We also
    hold that “[s]ection 190.5(b) authorizes and indeed requires consideration of the
    Miller factors.” (Ibid.) Justice Corrigan’s concurring opinion does not disagree
    with either proposition.
    Justice Corrigan observes that our trial courts have discretion to decide
    whether trial as an adult is appropriate in cases where a juvenile is charged with
    murder but not charged with personally killing the victim. (Conc. opn., ante, at
    pp. 1–2 & fn. 1.) I agree that our trial courts have such discretion, but I would
    note Miller’s admonition that “transfer-stage discretion . . . has limited utility”
    because “the judge often does not know then what she will learn, about the
    offender or the offense, over the course of the proceedings.” 
    (Miller, supra
    , 567
    U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2474].) Further, “and still more important,” Miller
    said, “the question at transfer hearings may differ dramatically from the issue at
    a post-trial sentencing. Because many juvenile systems require that the offender
    be released at a particular age or after a certain number of years, transfer
    1
    decisions often present a choice between extremes: light punishment as a child
    or standard sentencing as an adult (here, life without parole).” (Ibid.; see Welf. &
    Inst. Code, § 607 [minor must be discharged from juvenile court’s jurisdiction at
    age 21 in most cases and at age 25 in any case, unless civilly committed].)
    “Discretionary sentencing in adult court would provide different options: There, a
    judge or jury could choose, rather than a life-without-parole sentence, a lifetime
    prison term with the possibility of parole or a lengthy term of years. It is easy to
    imagine a judge deciding that a minor deserves a (much) harsher sentence than he
    would receive in juvenile court, while still not thinking life-without-parole
    appropriate.” (Miller, at pp. __–__ [132 S.Ct. at pp. 2474–2475].) This, too,
    informed Miller’s judgment that “transfer-stage discretion . . . has limited utility.”
    (Id. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2474].)
    Finally, although Justice Corrigan is correct that Miller involved two 14-
    year-olds (conc. opn., ante, at p. 3), lower courts should take note that Miller, in
    clear language, announced a principle that applies to all juveniles, not just 14-year-
    olds: “[G]iven all we have said in Roper, Graham, and this decision about
    children’s diminished culpability and heightened capacity for change, we think
    appropriate occasions for sentencing juveniles to this harshest possible penalty
    will be uncommon. That is especially so because of the great difficulty we noted
    in Roper and Graham of distinguishing at this early age between ‘the juvenile
    offender whose crime reflects unfortunate yet transient immaturity, and the rare
    juvenile offender whose crime reflects irreparable corruption.’ ” 
    (Miller, supra
    ,
    567 U.S. at p. __ [132 S.Ct. at p. 2469].)
    LIU, J.
    2
    See last page for addresses and telephone numbers for counsel who argued in Supreme Court.
    Name of Opinion People v. Gutierrez and People v. Moffett
    __________________________________________________________________________________
    Unpublished Opinion
    Original Appeal
    Original Proceeding
    Review Granted XXX 
    209 Cal. App. 4th 646
    and 
    209 Cal. App. 4th 1465
    Rehearing Granted
    __________________________________________________________________________________
    Opinion No. S206365 and S206771
    Date Filed: May 5, 2014
    __________________________________________________________________________________
    Court: Superior
    County: Ventura and Contra Costa
    Judge: Patricia M. Murphy and Laurel S. Brady
    __________________________________________________________________________________
    Counsel:
    Jean Matulis, under appointment by the Supreme Court, for Defendant and Appellant Luis Angel Gutierrez.
    Joseph Shipp, under appointment by the Supreme Court, for Defendant and Appellant Andrew Lawrence
    Moffett.
    L. Richard Braucher; and Susan L. Burrell for Pacific Juvenile Defender Center and Youth Law Center as
    Amici Curiae on behalf of Defendant and Appellant Luis Angel Gutierrez.
    Latham & Watkins, Aaron Murphy and Anthony J. Bruno for United Mexican States as Amicus Curiae on
    behalf of Defendant and Appellant Luis Angel Gutierrez.
    Elizabeth M. Calvin; DLA Piper and Steven S. Kimball for Human Rights Watch as Amicus Curiae on
    behalf of Defendant and Appellant Luis Angel Gutierrez.
    International Human Rights Clinic, Elizabeth A. Henneke; Frank C. Newman International Human Rights
    Law Clinic, Constance de la Vega and Lani Virostko for Amnesty International, Disability Rights Legal
    Center, Human Rights Advocates, Loyola Law School Center for Juvenile Law and Policy and University
    of San Francisco Center for Law and Global Justice as Amici Curiae on behalf of Defendants and
    Appellants.
    Jessica R. Feierman and Marsha L. Levick for Juvenile Law Center as Amicus Curiae on behalf of
    Defendants and Appellants.
    Kamala D. Harris, Attorney General, Dane R. Gillette, Chief Assistant Attorney General, Lance E. Winters,
    Assistant Attorney General, Lawrence M. Daniels, Steven D. Matthews and David F. Glassman, Deputy
    Attorneys General, for Plaintiff and Respondent in S206365.
    1
    Page 2 – S206365 and S206771 – counsel continued
    Counsel:
    Edmund G. Brown, Jr., and Kamala D. Harris, Attorneys General, Dane R. Gillette, Chief Assistant
    Attorney General, Gerald A. Engler, Assistant Attorney General, Lawrence M. Daniels, René A. Chacón
    and David M. Baskind, Deputy Attorneys General, for Plaintiff and Respondent in S206771.
    Criminal Justice Legal Foundation and Kent S. Scheidegger for Jo Ann Lasater, Phyllis Loya and James
    Lasater as Amici Curiae on behalf of Plaintiff and Respondent.
    2
    Counsel who argued in Supreme Court (not intended for publication with opinion):
    Jean Matulis
    Post Office Box 1237
    Cambria, CA 93428
    (805) 927-1990
    Joseph Shipp
    Post Office Box 20347
    Oakland, CA 94620
    (510) 530-9043
    Marsha L. Levick
    Juvenile Law Center
    1315 Walnut Street, 4th Floor
    Philadelphia, PA 19107
    (215) 625-0551
    David F. Glassman
    Deputy Attorney General
    300 South Spring Street, Suite 1702
    Los Angeles, CA 90013
    (213) 897-2355
    David M. Baskind
    Deputy Attorney General
    455 Golden Gate Avenue, Suite 11000
    San Francisco, CA 94102-7004
    (415) 703-1308
    3
    

Document Info

Docket Number: S206365; S206771

Citation Numbers: 58 Cal. 4th 1354

Judges: Corrigan, Liu

Filed Date: 5/5/2014

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 8/31/2023

Authorities (17)

People v. Carmony , 14 Cal. Rptr. 3d 880 ( 2004 )

People v. Rodriguez , 17 Cal. 4th 253 ( 1998 )

People v. Thomas , 52 Cal. 4th 336 ( 2011 )

People v. Lucky , 45 Cal. 3d 259 ( 1988 )

People v. Belmontes , 34 Cal. 3d 335 ( 1983 )

Whitman v. Superior Court , 54 Cal. 3d 1063 ( 1991 )

Mays v. City of Los Angeles , 74 Cal. Rptr. 3d 891 ( 2008 )

Townsend v. Burke , 68 S. Ct. 1252 ( 1948 )

Woodson v. North Carolina , 96 S. Ct. 2978 ( 1976 )

Edward J. DeBartolo Corp. v. Florida Gulf Coast Building & ... , 108 S. Ct. 1392 ( 1988 )

Rust v. Sullivan , 111 S. Ct. 1759 ( 1991 )

Jones v. United States , 119 S. Ct. 1215 ( 1999 )

Atkins v. Virginia , 122 S. Ct. 2242 ( 2002 )

Roper v. Simmons , 125 S. Ct. 1183 ( 2005 )

Kennedy v. Louisiana , 128 S. Ct. 2641 ( 2008 )

J. D. B. v. North Carolina , 131 S. Ct. 2394 ( 2011 )

Miller v. Alabama , 132 S. Ct. 2455 ( 2012 )

View All Authorities »