Brown v. USA Taekwondo ( 2021 )


Menu:
  •          IN THE SUPREME COURT OF
    CALIFORNIA
    YAZMIN BROWN et al.,
    Plaintiffs and Appellants,
    v.
    USA TAEKWONDO et al.,
    Defendants and Respondents.
    S259216
    Second Appellate District, Division Seven
    B280550
    Los Angeles County Superior Court
    BC599321
    April 1, 2021
    Justice Kruger authored the opinion of the Court, in which
    Chief Justice Cantil-Sakauye and Justices Corrigan, Liu,
    Cuéllar, Groban, and Jenkins concurred.
    Justice Cuéllar filed a concurring opinion.
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    S259216
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    To state a cause of action for negligence, a plaintiff must
    establish the defendant owed a legal duty of care. Generally
    speaking, all persons have a duty to take reasonable care in
    their activities to avoid causing injury, though particular policy
    considerations may weigh in favor of limiting that duty in
    certain circumstances. (Civ. Code, § 1714; Rowland v. Christian
    (1968) 
    69 Cal.2d 108
     (Rowland).) The issue before us concerns
    how courts should decide whether a defendant has a legal duty
    to take action to protect the plaintiff from injuries caused by a
    third party. Despite a substantial body of case law addressing
    the issue, the Courts of Appeal have remained uncertain about
    the proper legal framework to apply. Distilling the principles
    articulated in prior cases, we now clarify that whether to
    recognize a duty to protect is governed by a two-step inquiry.
    First, the court must determine whether there exists a special
    relationship between the parties or some other set of
    circumstances giving rise to an affirmative duty to protect.
    Second, if so, the court must consult the factors described in
    Rowland to determine whether relevant policy considerations
    counsel limiting that duty. Because the Court of Appeal in this
    case employed the correct framework for decision, we affirm its
    judgment and remand for further proceedings.
    1
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    I.
    This case comes to us at the demurrer stage, so for present
    purposes we assume the truth of the allegations in the
    complaint. (Southern California Gas Leak Cases (2019) 
    7 Cal.5th 391
    , 395 (Gas Leak Cases).) As teenagers, plaintiffs
    Yazmin Brown, Kendra Gatt, and Brianna Bordon trained in
    the Olympic sport of taekwondo. They traveled to compete at
    various events in California and throughout the country with
    their coach, Marc Gitelman. Gitelman took advantage of these
    opportunities to sexually abuse the young athletes. This went
    on for years until the sponsor of these competitions, USA
    Taekwondo (USAT), banned Gitelman from coaching. Gitelman
    was ultimately convicted of multiple felonies for the sexual
    abuse of the minor athletes he trained.
    Plaintiffs (to whom we will generally refer as Brown) filed
    this civil suit against Gitelman and several others, including
    respondents USAT and the United States Olympic Committee
    (USOC).1 USOC is a federally chartered nonprofit corporation
    whose central function is to coordinate amateur sports
    throughout the country for athletes hoping to one day compete
    in the Olympics. (See 
    36 U.S.C. § 220505
    (c)(1).) In this role,
    USOC certifies and oversees each sport’s national governing
    body, the entity responsible for conducting and administering
    the sport in the United States. USAT is the national governing
    body for the sport of taekwondo. If an athlete wishes to compete
    in taekwondo at the Olympics or in any other USAT-sponsored
    competition (as Brown and the other plaintiffs did), the athlete
    1
    In June 2019, USOC’s name was changed to the United
    States Olympic and Paralympic Committee.
    2
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    must become a member of USAT and train under a USAT-
    registered coach (as Gitelman was before USAT banned him).
    As relevant here, Brown alleged that USOC and USAT
    were negligent in failing to protect her from Gitelman’s abuse. 2
    Brown emphasized that the sexual abuse of young athletes was
    a known problem; Gitelman’s abuse came on the heels of a series
    of similar instances of abuse of minors by their coaches dating
    back to the 1980’s. In the wake of these incidents, USOC
    mandated that national governing bodies adopt a Safe Sport
    Program to protect athletes from such abuse. Brown alleged
    that USAT failed to implement the program in a timely fashion
    — a fact known to USOC, which placed USAT on probation as a
    result. Brown further alleged that USAT took insufficient steps
    to protect Gitelman’s victims once it was made aware of her
    allegations:    USAT temporarily suspended Gitelman, but
    nevertheless permitted him to continue coaching at USAT
    competitions for several months before ultimately placing him
    on its list of banned coaches.
    USOC and USAT both demurred to the complaint. As
    relevant here, they argued Brown had not adequately alleged
    they had an affirmative duty to take action to protect her and
    the other plaintiffs from Gitelman’s abuse. The trial court
    sustained both demurrers without leave to amend and entered
    judgments of dismissal.
    2
    Brown also raised various other claims against USOC and
    USAT, including claims that USOC and USAT were vicariously
    liable for Gitelman’s conduct and claims for negligent hiring and
    intentional infliction of emotional distress. Those claims are not
    before us here.
    3
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    Brown appealed. The Court of Appeal reversed the
    judgment dismissing USAT but affirmed as to USOC. (Brown
    v. USA Taekwondo (2019) 
    40 Cal.App.5th 1077
    , 1083 (Brown).)
    In determining whether Brown had adequately alleged each
    defendant had a legal duty to protect plaintiffs from Gitelman’s
    abuse, the court employed a two-part framework. As a general
    rule, the court explained, “ ‘ “one owes no duty to control the
    conduct of another, nor to warn those endangered by such
    conduct.” ’ ” (Id. at p. 1091, quoting Regents of University of
    California v. Superior Court (2018) 
    4 Cal.5th 607
    , 619
    (Regents).) An exception to this no-duty-to-protect rule exists for
    cases in which the defendant has a special relationship with
    either the dangerous third party or with the victim. (Brown, at
    p. 1091.) But even when the so-called special relationship
    exception applies, the policy considerations described in
    Rowland, supra, 
    69 Cal.2d 108
    , may weigh against imposing a
    duty to protect in a given case.3 (Brown, at p. 1092.) The court
    thus asked, first, whether Brown had adequately alleged a
    special relationship between the parties that gave rise to a legal
    duty to protect, and second, whether the Rowland factors
    weighed in favor of limiting or eliminating this duty.
    3
    These considerations include “the foreseeability of harm to
    the plaintiff, the degree of certainty that the plaintiff suffered
    injury, the closeness of the connection between the defendant’s
    conduct and the injury suffered, the moral blame attached to the
    defendant’s conduct, the policy of preventing future harm, the
    extent of the burden to the defendant and consequences to the
    community of imposing a duty to exercise care with resulting
    liability for breach, and the availability, cost, and prevalence of
    insurance for the risk involved.” (Rowland, supra, 69 Cal.2d at
    p. 113.)
    4
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    Applying this framework, the Court of Appeal concluded
    that Brown had adequately alleged that USAT owed a duty to
    protect her from Gitelman. The court first concluded Brown had
    sufficiently alleged a special relationship between USAT and
    Gitelman that enabled USAT to control Gitelman’s actions, as
    demonstrated by the fact that USAT had registered him as a
    coach, took disciplinary action against him, and ultimately
    barred him from coaching. (Brown, supra, 40 Cal.App.5th at
    pp. 1094–1095.) The court then went on to consider whether the
    Rowland factors counseled against imposing a duty on USAT,
    and determined they did not. (Id. at pp. 1095–1101.)
    By contrast, the Court of Appeal concluded that USOC,
    unlike USAT, had no special relationship with either the
    plaintiffs or Gitelman, and thus no legal duty to protect the
    plaintiffs from Gitelman’s abuse. The court explained that
    Brown’s case for imposing an affirmative duty on USOC rested
    largely on allegations that USOC had the ability to regulate
    USAT’s conduct. The court considered this insufficient to
    establish a special relationship that would enable USOC to
    control Gitelman’s conduct, or that would give plaintiffs reason
    to look to the USOC for protection. (Brown, supra, 40
    Cal.App.5th at pp. 1101–1103.) Having concluded that Brown’s
    allegations faltered at the first step of the analysis, the court
    declined to consider how the Rowland factors might apply to
    USOC. (Id. at p. 1103.)
    The Court of Appeal’s decision added to a considerable
    body of law addressing the connection between the special
    relationship doctrine and the Rowland factors in cases alleging
    a duty to protect the plaintiff from harms caused by third
    parties. The appellate courts that have addressed the issue
    have adopted various approaches. Several other Courts of
    5
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    Appeal have employed the same two-part framework as the
    court in this case, holding that a plaintiff must satisfy both the
    special relationship test and the Rowland factors before a duty
    to protect the plaintiff from third party harm can be imposed on
    the defendant. (See, e.g., Barenborg v. Sigma Alpha Epsilon
    Fraternity (2019) 
    33 Cal.App.5th 70
    , 77 [“Thus, plaintiffs
    alleging a defendant had a duty to protect them must establish:
    (1) that an exception to the general no-duty-to-protect rule
    applies and (2) that the Rowland factors support imposition of
    the duty.”]; Doe v. United States Youth Soccer Assn., Inc. (2017)
    
    8 Cal.App.5th 1118
    , 1128 [noting that if courts find a special
    relationship, they go on to “balance[] the policy factors set forth
    in Rowland [citation] to assist in their determination of the
    existence and scope of a defendant’s duty in a particular case”].)
    Other Courts of Appeal, however, have held that a
    plaintiff can establish a duty to protect by satisfying either the
    special relationship doctrine or the Rowland factors. Under this
    approach, Rowland serves as an independent source of duty.
    (Juarez v. Boy Scouts of America, Inc. (2000) 
    81 Cal.App.4th 377
    ,
    401–402, 410–411 [finding duty under Rowland, but concluding
    in the alternative that the plaintiff satisfied the special
    relationship test]; see Adams v. City of Fremont (1998) 
    68 Cal.App.4th 243
    , 267–276, 282–288 (Adams) [noting that
    Rowland factors and the special relationship test are sometimes
    in conflict and finding no duty to protect under either test, while
    concluding that this court has generally favored applying
    Rowland’s multifactor test over the special relationship test]; cf.
    University of Southern California v. Superior Court (2018) 
    30 Cal.App.5th 429
    , 451 [finding no duty under either the special
    relationship test or Rowland, though recognizing that applying
    Rowland “may be unnecessary”].)
    6
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    Still other courts have taken the view that the special
    relationship test incorporates the Rowland factors — that is,
    that “[r]esolution of the issue whether a special relationship
    exists giving rise to a duty to protect (or warn) comprehends
    consideration of the same factors underlying any duty of care
    analysis” under Rowland. (Hansra v. Superior Court (1992) 
    7 Cal.App.4th 630
    , 646 (Hansra); accord, Titus v. Canyon Lake
    Property Owners Assn. (2004) 
    118 Cal.App.4th 906
    , 911–912
    (Titus).) Whereas the Court of Appeal in this case employed a
    two-part framework to evaluate defendants’ legal duty to
    protect, these courts have reduced the inquiry to a single step,
    applying the Rowland factors to determine whether a special
    relationship exists.
    In view of the different approaches taken by the Courts of
    Appeal, we granted review to clarify the applicable framework
    for determining whether a defendant has a duty to protect a
    plaintiff from harm caused by a third party. We conclude the
    two-part framework the Court of Appeal applied in this case
    accurately reflects the law as stated in this court’s precedents,
    and we accordingly affirm the court’s judgment.4
    II.
    A.
    To establish a cause of action for negligence, the plaintiff
    must show that the “defendant had a duty to use due care, that
    he breached that duty, and that the breach was the proximate
    4
    We express no view on the merits of the Court of Appeal’s
    application of the special relationship test to either USAT or
    USOC. These fact-dependent issues fall outside the scope of the
    only question presented for our review.
    7
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    or legal cause of the resulting injury.” (Nally v. Grace
    Community Church (1988) 
    47 Cal.3d 278
    , 292.) Recovery for
    negligence depends as a threshold matter on the existence of a
    legal duty of care. (Gas Leak Cases, supra, 7 Cal.5th at p. 397.)
    Duty is not universal; not every defendant owes every
    plaintiff a duty of care. A duty exists only if “ ‘the plaintiff’s
    interests are entitled to legal protection against the defendant’s
    conduct.’ ” (Dillon v. Legg (1968) 
    68 Cal.2d 728
    , 734, quoting
    Prosser, Torts (3d ed. 1964) § 53, p. 332.) Whether a duty exists
    is a question of law to be resolved by the court. (Bily v. Arthur
    Young & Co. (1992) 
    3 Cal.4th 370
    , 397.)
    The “general rule” governing duty is set forth in Civil Code
    section 1714 (section 1714). (Cabral v. Ralphs Grocery Co.
    (2011) 
    51 Cal.4th 764
    , 771 (Cabral).) First enacted in 1872,
    section 1714 provides: “Everyone is responsible . . . for an injury
    occasioned to another by his or her want of ordinary care or skill
    in the management of his or her property or person . . . .” (Id.,
    subd. (a).) This statute establishes the default rule that each
    person has a duty “to exercise, in his or her activities, reasonable
    care for the safety of others.” (Cabral, at p. 768.)
    Section 1714 states a broad rule, but it has limits. We
    have explained that the law imposes a general duty of care on a
    defendant only when it is the defendant who has “ ‘created a
    risk’ ” of harm to the plaintiff, including when “ ‘the defendant
    is responsible for making the plaintiff’s position worse.’ ” (Lugtu
    v. California Highway Patrol (2001) 
    26 Cal.4th 703
    , 716, quoting
    Weirum v. RKO General, Inc. (1975) 
    15 Cal.3d 40
    , 49; see Lugtu,
    at p. 716 [“Under general negligence principles, . . . a person
    ordinarily is obligated to exercise due care in his or her own
    actions so as not to create an unreasonable risk of injury to
    8
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    others . . . .” (Citing § 1714.)].) The law does not impose the
    same duty on a defendant who did not contribute to the risk that
    the plaintiff would suffer the harm alleged. Generally, the
    “person who has not created a peril is not liable in tort merely
    for failure to take affirmative action to assist or protect another”
    from that peril. (Williams v. State of California (1983) 
    34 Cal.3d 18
    , 23 (Williams); accord, Weirum, at p. 49; see Rest.3d Torts,
    Liability for Physical and Emotional Harm (2012) § 37
    [Generally, “[a]n actor whose conduct has not created a risk of
    physical or emotional harm to another has no duty of care to the
    other.”].) For example, a person who stumbles upon someone
    drowning generally has no legal duty to help the victim. The
    same rule applies to a person who stumbles upon a mugging, for
    “as a general matter, there is no duty to act to protect others
    from the conduct of third parties.” (Delgado v. Trax Bar & Grill
    (2005) 
    36 Cal.4th 224
    , 235 (Delgado); see also Regents, supra, 4
    Cal.5th at p. 619 [Generally, “ ‘one owes no duty to control the
    conduct of another, nor to warn those endangered by such
    conduct.’ ”].)5
    This general rule, we have explained, “derives from the
    common law’s distinction between misfeasance and
    nonfeasance, and its reluctance to impose liability for the
    latter.” (Tarasoff v. Regents of University of California (1976)
    5
    While these examples involve bystanders in the usual
    sense of the term, it bears emphasis that the relevant legal
    question is whether the defendant has engaged in activities that
    created or increased the plaintiff’s risk of harm. A defendant
    may have greater involvement in the plaintiff’s activities than a
    chance spectator yet play no meaningful part in exposing the
    plaintiff to harm. (Cf. conc. opn., post, at p. 7 [rejecting the idea
    that USOC was a bystander in this case].)
    9
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    
    17 Cal.3d 425
    , 435, fn. 5.) That distinction has deep roots in the
    law. (See, e.g., Bohlen, The Moral Duty to Aid Others as a Basis
    of Tort Liability (1908) 56 U.Pa. L.Rev. 217, 219 [“There is no
    distinction more deeply rooted in the common law and more
    fundamental than that between misfeasance and non-feasance,
    between active misconduct working positive injury to others and
    passive in action, a failure to take positive steps to benefit
    others, or to protect them from harm not created by any
    wrongful act of the defendant.”].)6 And although it may
    sometimes produce outcomes that appear “[m]orally
    questionable” (Tarasoff, at p. 435, fn. 5), there are several
    reasons the no-duty-to-protect rule has endured. The most
    commonly cited reason for the rule is rooted in “the liberal
    tradition of individual freedom and autonomy” — the idea that
    a person should be able to freely choose whether to come to the
    aid of a stranger, without fear of incurring legal liability for the
    choice. (Rest.3d Torts, supra, § 37, com. e, p. 5.) But our cases
    have recognized other reasons as well, including “ ‘the
    difficulties of setting any standards of unselfish service to fellow
    men,’ ” and the challenge of “ ‘making any workable rule to cover
    possible situations where fifty people might fail to rescue.’ ”
    (Tarasoff, at p. 435, fn. 5, quoting Prosser, Torts (4th ed. 1971)
    § 56, p. 341.)
    6
    Although our precedents have sometimes referred to the
    distinction between “misfeasance” and “nonfeasance,” we now
    understand this terminology to be imprecise and prone to
    misinterpretation. “The proper question is not whether an
    actor’s failure to exercise reasonable care entails the commission
    or omission of a specific act.” (Rest.3d Torts, supra, § 37, com. c,
    p. 3.) Rather, it is “whether the actor’s entire conduct created a
    risk of harm.” (Ibid.)
    10
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    The no-duty-to-protect rule is not absolute, however; this
    court has recognized a number of exceptions. (Delgado, 
    supra,
    36 Cal.4th at p. 235.) Under some circumstances, a defendant
    may have an affirmative duty to protect the plaintiff from harm
    at the hands of a third party, even though the risk of harm is
    not of the defendant’s own making. (Ibid.; see also Rest.3d
    Torts, supra, § 37.) For example, if a person does choose to
    “undertake[] to come to the aid of another,” she may then have
    an affirmative duty to exercise reasonable care in that
    undertaking. (Williams, supra, 34 Cal.3d at p. 23 [describing
    the negligent undertaking doctrine]; see, e.g., Paz v. State of
    California (2000) 
    22 Cal.4th 550
    , 559; Rest.3d Torts, supra,
    § 42.) We here focus, along with the parties, on another basis
    for finding an affirmative duty: In a case involving harm caused
    by a third party, a person may have an affirmative duty to
    protect the victim of another’s harm if that person is in what the
    law calls a “special relationship” with either the victim or the
    person who created the harm. (See, e.g., Regents, supra, 4
    Cal.5th at pp. 619–620; Delgado, at p. 235; Williams, at p. 23;
    see generally Rest.3d Torts, supra, §§ 40, 41.)7
    7
    This is not an exhaustive list. An affirmative duty to
    protect may also arise if, for example, the Legislature imposes
    one by statute. (See Hoff v. Vacaville Unified School Dist. (1998)
    
    19 Cal.4th 925
    , 938; Rest.3d Torts, supra, § 38.) Regardless of
    whether there is a basis for recognizing an affirmative duty, the
    no-duty-to-protect rule will not relieve the defendant of an
    otherwise applicable duty to exercise reasonable care when, by
    its own conduct, the defendant has increased the risk of harm to
    the plaintiff. (See, e.g., Kesner v. Superior Court (2016) 
    1 Cal.5th 1132
    , 1163 [“Although we have held that the existence
    of a relationship between the plaintiff and the defendant is one
    11
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    A special relationship between the defendant and the
    victim is one that “gives the victim a right to expect” protection
    from the defendant, while a special relationship between the
    defendant and the dangerous third party is one that “entails an
    ability to control [the third party’s] conduct.” (Regents, supra, 4
    Cal.5th at p. 619.) Relationships between parents and children,
    colleges and students, employers and employees, common
    carriers and passengers, and innkeepers and guests, are all
    examples of special relationships that give rise to an affirmative
    duty to protect. (Id. at pp. 619–620; see Rest.3d Torts, supra,
    §§ 40–41.) The existence of such a special relationship puts the
    defendant in a unique position to protect the plaintiff from
    injury. The law requires the defendant to use this position
    accordingly. (See, e.g., Rest.3d Torts, supra, § 40, com. h,
    pp. 42–43.)
    Where the defendant has neither performed an act that
    increases the risk of injury to the plaintiff nor sits in a relation
    to the parties that creates an affirmative duty to protect the
    plaintiff from harm, however, our cases have uniformly held the
    defendant owes no legal duty to the plaintiff. Our decision in
    Williams, supra, 
    34 Cal.3d 18
    , is illustrative. The question there
    was whether highway patrol officers who had aided an injured
    motorist after an accident had a duty to investigate, secure
    information, or preserve evidence for the motorist to use in later
    civil litigation against the driver who caused her injury. (Id. at
    p. 21.) We began our analysis by reciting the general rule that
    basis for finding liability premised on the conduct of a third
    party [citations], we have never held that such a relationship is
    a prerequisite to finding that a defendant had a duty to prevent
    injuries due to its own conduct or possessory control.”].)
    12
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    one has no duty to come to the aid of another. (Id. at pp. 23–24.)
    We then went on to consider whether the special relationship or
    negligent undertaking exceptions to the rule applied.
    Answering that question in the negative, we concluded the
    officers owed no duty to assist the motorist in preserving
    evidence. (Id. at pp. 27–28.) Other cases are to similar effect.
    (See, e.g., Davidson v. City of Westminster (1982) 
    32 Cal.3d 197
    ,
    203–209 [officers had no duty to protect victim of assault
    because they had not increased the risk of harm to the victim,
    they had no special relationship with the assailant or the victim,
    and they had not invited the plaintiff to depend on their
    protection]; Zelig v. County of Los Angeles (2002) 
    27 Cal.4th 1112
    , 1130 [officers had no duty to protect courthouse visitors
    from a third party assailant where officers had not increased the
    risk of harm to the victim, had no special relationship with
    either party, and had not given the victim a false sense of
    security by inviting her to depend on special protection].)
    B.
    Brown argues for a different approach to the duty to
    protect. She argues that even if the defendant lacks any special
    relationship with the parties and there are no other
    circumstances that would give rise to an affirmative duty to
    protect, such a duty may nonetheless arise after considering the
    policy factors set out in the landmark decision in Rowland,
    supra, 
    69 Cal.2d 108
    . We reject the argument.
    The multifactor test set forth in Rowland was not designed
    as a freestanding means of establishing duty, but instead as a
    means for deciding whether to limit a duty derived from other
    sources. The specific question in Rowland concerned the
    relationship between the common law duties of landowners and
    13
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    the general duty of care codified in section 1714. At common
    law, a landowner’s duty of care to his or her visitors varied based
    on the type of visitor. While landowners owed invitees an
    ordinary duty of care to maintain the premises in a safe
    condition, they generally owed trespassers and licensees only a
    duty to refrain from willful injury. (Rowland, supra, 69 Cal.2d
    at p. 114.) We held, however, that these “rigid common law
    classifications” were incompatible with California law. (Id. at
    p. 118.) We explained that “the basic policy of this state set forth
    by the Legislature in section 1714 . . . is that everyone is
    responsible for an injury caused to another by his want of
    ordinary care or skill in the management of his property.”
    (Rowland, at pp. 118–119.) And while there are exceptions to
    section 1714’s general rule, “in the absence of [a] statutory
    provision declaring an exception . . . , no such exception should
    be made unless clearly supported by public policy.” (Rowland,
    at p. 112.)
    In the passage of Rowland that has now become a
    touchstone of our negligence jurisprudence, we summarized the
    policy considerations that guide the inquiry. To depart from the
    general principle that all persons owe a duty of care to avoid
    injuring others, we explained, “involves the balancing of a
    number of considerations”: “the foreseeability of harm to the
    plaintiff, the degree of certainty that the plaintiff suffered
    injury, the closeness of the connection between the defendant’s
    conduct and the injury suffered, the moral blame attached to the
    defendant’s conduct, the policy of preventing future harm, the
    extent of the burden to the defendant and consequences to the
    community of imposing a duty to exercise care with resulting
    liability for breach, and the availability, cost, and prevalence of
    insurance for the risk involved.” (Rowland, supra, 69 Cal.2d at
    14
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    pp. 112–113.)    We reasoned that while the common law
    categories of landowner duties might align with some of these
    considerations in some cases, they did not align in every case. It
    followed that a victim’s status as a trespasser, licensee, or
    invitee cannot be determinative of a landowner’s duties. The
    inquiry whether a landowner owes a duty to her invitees instead
    begins with the “basic policy” that “everyone is responsible for
    an injury caused to another by his want of ordinary care or skill
    in the management of his property,” and then considers whether
    more particular considerations of policy call for departure from
    the basic rule. (Id. at pp. 118–119.)
    Rowland itself referred to this multifactor test as a guide
    for determining whether to recognize an “exception” to the
    general duty of care under section 1714. (Rowland, supra, 69
    Cal.2d at p. 113.) And in numerous cases since Rowland, we
    have repeated that the Rowland factors serve to determine
    whether an exception to section 1714’s general duty of
    reasonable care is warranted, not to determine whether a “ ‘new
    duty’ ” should be created. (Kesner v. Superior Court, supra, 1
    Cal.5th at p. 1143 [“Because Civil Code section 1714 establishes
    a general duty to exercise ordinary care in one’s activities, . . .
    we rely on these factors not to determine ‘whether a new duty
    should be created, but whether an exception to Civil Code section
    1714 . . . should be created,’ ” quoting Cabral, 
    supra,
     51 Cal.4th
    at p. 783]; accord, e.g., Gas Leak Cases, supra, 7 Cal.5th at
    p. 398 [“[Under section 1714], we presume the defendant owed
    the plaintiff a duty of care and then ask whether the
    circumstances ‘justify a departure’ from that usual
    presumption.”]; Ballard v. Uribe (1986) 
    41 Cal.3d 564
    , 572, fn. 6
    [similar].)
    15
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    Although Rowland itself concerned the general duty of
    care in section 1714, we have also routinely applied Rowland to
    consider whether to recognize exceptions to affirmative duties to
    protect or warn. For example, in our recent decision in Regents,
    supra, 4 Cal.5th at page 627, we held that the special
    relationship between a university and its students creates a
    “duty to use reasonable care to protect their students from
    foreseeable acts of violence in the classroom or during curricular
    activities.” We then turned to Rowland to decide whether policy
    considerations “justif[ied] excusing or limiting” that duty to
    protect, and concluded the answer was no. (Regents, at p. 628;
    see id. at pp. 628–634.) This is but one example of many; a long
    line of cases before Regents had taken the same approach. (C.A.
    v. William S. Hart Union High School Dist. (2012) 
    53 Cal.4th 861
    , 877 (William S. Hart) [finding special relationship between
    school employees and students and then analyzing Rowland
    factors to determine “[a]dditional limits” on the “scope of the
    duty implicated in this and similar cases”]; 
    id.
     at pp. 869–871,
    877–879; Castaneda v. Olsher (2007) 
    41 Cal.4th 1205
    , 1213
    [finding affirmative duty based on special relationship between
    landlord and tenants and then analyzing Rowland factors to
    determine “duty’s existence and scope”]; Delgado, 
    supra,
     36
    Cal.4th at p. 244 [finding special relationship between business
    proprietor and its tenants, patrons, and invitees imposed
    general duty on proprietor to take “ ‘reasonable steps to secure
    common areas against foreseeable criminal acts of third
    parties’ ” and then analyzing Rowland factors to determine
    scope of duty]; 
    id.
     at pp. 235–236, 244–247; Morris v. De La
    Torre (2005) 
    36 Cal.4th 260
    , 269, 271–272, 276–277 [same].)
    The cases recognize that even when two parties may be in a
    special relationship, the unforeseeability of the kind of harm
    16
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    suffered by the plaintiff or other policy factors may counsel
    against establishing an affirmative duty for one party to protect
    the other.
    Notwithstanding this considerable body of case law,
    Brown points to our decision in Nally v. Grace Community
    Church, supra, 
    47 Cal.3d 278
     as evidence that we have
    sometimes treated Rowland as an independent source of duty,
    and not merely as a guide to whether to create an exception to a
    duty otherwise established. In that case, parents of a suicide
    victim sued the victim’s nontherapist church counselors for
    failure to protect the victim from suicide. (Nally, at p. 292.) We
    held the nontherapist counselors had no duty to protect,
    consistent with the traditional rule that “one is ordinarily not
    liable for the actions of another and is under no duty to protect
    another from harm, in the absence of a special relationship of
    custody or control.” (Id. at p. 293.) We next held there was no
    such special relationship involved in the case. (Id. at p. 296.)
    But we then considered the Rowland factors, in belt-and-
    suspenders fashion, to “explain further why we should not
    impose a duty to prevent suicide on defendants and other
    nontherapist counselors.” (Ibid.)
    As Brown notes, some Courts of Appeal have understood
    Nally to mean that the Rowland factors and the special
    relationship test are both sources of duty. (See, e.g., Adams,
    supra, 68 Cal.App.4th at p. 267.) This understanding is
    mistaken. Nally never squarely addressed the proper role of
    Rowland in its analysis, nor did it purport to qualify or limit the
    considerable body of case law explaining that Rowland is a guide
    to determining when to create exceptions from duties otherwise
    established. And as Brown acknowledged at oral argument,
    neither Nally nor any other decision of this court has done what
    17
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    Brown now asks us to do: rely solely on the Rowland factors to
    create a duty to take action to protect the plaintiff from third
    party harm.8
    8
    Although Brown has not raised the point in her briefing,
    we acknowledge that certain language in other cases could be
    read as suggesting such an approach. For example, in Palma v.
    U.S. Industrial Fasteners, Inc. (1984) 
    36 Cal.3d 171
    , we said of
    a suit seeking to impose liability for leaving a commercial truck
    unsecured in a high-crime area, where it was stolen and later
    used to cause injury: “[O]rdinarily in the absence of a special
    relationship there is no duty to control the conduct of a third
    person so as to prevent him from harming another, but where
    special circumstances exist in which there is ‘a greater
    potentiality of foreseeable risk or more serious injury, or [which]
    require a lesser burden of preventative action,’ the risk is
    deemed unreasonable and imposes a duty to third persons.” (Id.
    at pp. 184–185, quoting Hergenrether v. East (1964) 
    61 Cal.2d 440
    , 444.) But as the broader context of Palma and other related
    cases makes clear, the focus of the duty inquiry in these cases is
    not on the defendant’s duty to protect the victim from the
    conduct of a third party, but instead on the defendant’s general
    duty under section 1714 to exercise due care in his or her own
    conduct. While a car owner ordinarily cannot be held liable
    simply for allowing her car to be stolen and used for harm
    (Cabral, supra, 51 Cal.4th at p. 779), in some cases, like Palma,
    the defendant’s decision to leave a vehicle unguarded does
    increase the risks the vehicle will be harmfully misused. (See
    Rest.3d Torts, supra, § 19, reporters’ note, com. c, p. 222 [citing
    vehicle-theft cases to illustrate the proposition that “[i]f the
    third party’s misconduct is among the risks making the
    defendant’s conduct negligent, then ordinarily plaintiff’s harm
    will be within the defendant’s scope of liability” (id., com. c,
    p. 216)].) Such cases “can be contrasted to cases in which the
    defendant merely takes no action to protect the plaintiff against
    the possibility of third-party misconduct” — which is Brown’s
    theory of liability in asserting the existence of a special
    relationship. (Rest.3d Torts, supra, § 19, com. e, p. 218; see also
    18
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    Precedent aside, Brown argues we should now take that
    step in order to establish what she terms a “more flexible and
    holistic approach to duty,” particularly in cases involving minor
    victims of sexual abuse. This approach would allow courts to
    make a case-by-case policy judgment under Rowland as to
    whether a defendant may be held liable for failing to protect the
    victim of harm caused by another, even if the defendant were in
    no special position to control the wrongdoer or to offer protection
    to the victim, and there were no other circumstances giving rise
    to an affirmative duty to take action.
    Without denying the gravity of the injuries these plaintiffs
    suffered, nor the broader problem of sexual abuse of minors in
    organized youth sports and other activities, we decline Brown’s
    invitation to take that step. The requirement of an affirmative
    duty to protect itself embodies a policy judgment of considerable
    standing: A defendant cannot be held liable in negligence for
    harms it did not cause unless there are special circumstances —
    such as a special relationship to the parties — that give the
    defendant a special obligation to offer protection or assistance.
    This rule reflects a long-standing balance between several
    competing interests. It avoids difficult questions about how to
    measure the legal liability of the stranger who fails to take
    affirmative steps to prevent foreseeable harm, instead leaving
    the stranger to make his or her own choices about what
    assistance to offer. (See pp. 9–10, ante.) At the same time, it
    extends a right of recovery to individuals in relationships
    involving dependence or control, and who by virtue of those
    relationships have reason to expect the defendant’s protection.
    id., illus. 1–3, pp. 218–219 [discussing circumstances where
    foreseeable risk makes a defendant’s conduct negligent].)
    19
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    (See Regents, supra, 4 Cal.5th at p. 621 [“ ‘[A] typical setting for
    the recognition of a special relationship is where “the plaintiff is
    particularly vulnerable and dependent upon the defendant who,
    correspondingly, has some control over the plaintiff’s
    welfare.” ’ ”].)
    Where such a special relationship exists between the
    defendant and a minor, the obligation to provide such protection
    and assistance may include a duty to protect the minor from
    third party abuse. (See, e.g., William S. Hart, 
    supra,
     53 Cal.4th
    at pp. 869–872, 879 [imposing such a duty]; Pamela L. v. Farmer
    (1980) 
    112 Cal.App.3d 206
    , 211 [same].) And there may be other
    circumstances that give rise to a comparable affirmative duty to
    protect. (Kesner v. Superior Court, supra, 1 Cal.5th at p. 1163.)
    But where no such circumstances exist, the Rowland factors do
    not serve as an alternative basis for imposing duties to protect.
    The purpose of the Rowland factors is to determine whether the
    relevant circumstances warrant limiting a duty already
    established, not to recognize legal duties in new contexts. (See
    Rowland, supra, 69 Cal.2d at p. 113; see also, e.g., Regents,
    supra, 4 Cal.5th at p. 628; cf. Rest.3d Torts, supra, § 40, com. b,
    p. 40 [“Even though an affirmative duty might exist pursuant to
    this Section, a court may decide, based on special problems of
    principle or policy, that no duty or a duty other than reasonable
    care exists.”].)
    The question remains whether Rowland has any role to
    play at all in cases concerning affirmative duties to protect. As
    noted, some courts have suggested the answer is no; that the
    special relationship test essentially encompasses the policy
    considerations set out in Rowland and renders it unnecessary to
    give separate consideration to the Rowland factors in
    determining whether to recognize a legal duty to protect.
    20
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    (Compare Hansra, supra, 7 Cal.App.4th at p. 646 [considering
    both tests together as one] and Titus, supra, 118 Cal.App.4th at
    pp. 911–912 [same] with Adams, supra, 68 Cal.App.4th at
    pp. 267–276, 282–288 [recognizing differences between them].)
    The suggestion is incorrect. While the Rowland factors do
    overlap to some degree with the considerations that determine
    the existence of a special relationship, application of one test
    does not obviate the need for the other. This is because the two
    tests operate differently. A court considers whether the parties
    have a special relationship by considering the particular facts
    and circumstances of their association with one another. The
    Rowland factors, by contrast, consider, “at a relatively broad
    level of factual generality,” whether policy considerations justify
    limiting any resulting duty of protection. (Cabral, supra, 51
    Cal.4th at p. 772; see Regents, supra, 4 Cal.5th at p. 629 [“In
    considering [the Rowland factors], we determine ‘not whether
    they support an exception to the general duty of reasonable care
    on the facts of the particular case before us, but whether carving
    out an entire category of cases from that general duty rule is
    justified by clear considerations of policy.’ ”].)
    Our opinion in Castaneda v. Olsher, 
    supra,
     
    41 Cal.4th 1205
     is illustrative of the difference between the two inquiries.
    In that case, the plaintiff was injured as a bystander to a gang-
    related shooting at the mobilehome park where he lived. He
    sued his landlord for negligence. (Id. at pp. 1211–1212.)
    Although the parties were in a special relationship, we
    concluded that the landlord did not have a duty to “withhold
    rental units from those they believe to be gang members” in
    order to protect his other tenants. (Id. at p. 1216.) We reasoned
    that requiring as much would, as a general proposition, result
    in “arbitrary discrimination on the basis of race, ethnicity,
    21
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    family composition, dress and appearance, or reputation” — all
    in service of a tenant screening process that was unlikely to
    effectively prevent injuries like those the plaintiff had suffered.
    (Ibid.) Thus, despite the existence of a special relationship,
    imposing such a duty on landlords would not be “fair or
    workable,” nor would it be “consistent with our state’s public
    policy as a whole.” (Ibid.)
    In other cases, a court might conclude that duty should not
    be imposed because, for example, the type of harm the plaintiff
    suffered was unforeseeable, or because there was no moral
    blameworthiness associated with the defendant’s conduct,
    notwithstanding the defendant’s special relationship to the
    plaintiff. Put differently, even when a special relationship gives
    rise to an affirmative duty to protect, a court must still consider
    whether the policy considerations set out in Rowland warrant a
    departure from that duty in the relevant category of cases.
    III.
    Brown alleged that USAT and USOC acted negligently by
    failing to take steps to protect her from her coach’s abuse. To
    evaluate her claim, the Court of Appeal first asked whether a
    duty existed based on a special relationship. Concluding that
    USOC had no such relationship with Brown, the court ended its
    analysis with respect to that defendant. This approach was
    sound. And after concluding that USAT did have a special
    relationship with plaintiffs, the court went on to apply Rowland
    to determine whether to limit that potential duty — deciding the
    22
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Opinion of the Court by Kruger, J.
    answer to that question was no.         This, too, was the correct
    approach.9
    The Court of Appeal’s judgment does not mark the end of
    the case. It affirms the trial court’s decision to dismiss one of
    several named defendants, USOC, for failure to adequately
    allege a special relationship giving rise to an affirmative duty to
    protect. Having concluded the Court of Appeal did not err by
    declining to apply the Rowland factors as an alternative source
    of duty, we now affirm the court’s judgment. On remand, Brown
    may continue to pursue her suit against USAT and the other
    remaining defendants.
    KRUGER, J.
    We Concur:
    CANTIL-SAKAUYE, C. J.
    CORRIGAN, J.
    LIU, J.
    CUÉLLAR, J.
    GROBAN, J.
    JENKINS, J.
    9
    We disapprove the following decisions to the extent they
    applied the Rowland factors as an alternative source of duty
    where defendant did not create the risk that resulted in
    plaintiff’s injuries:  University of Southern California v.
    Superior Court, supra, 
    30 Cal.App.5th 429
    ; Juarez v. Boy Scouts
    of America, Inc., supra, 
    81 Cal.App.4th 377
    ; Adams v. City of
    Fremont, supra, 
    68 Cal.App.4th 243
    ; Titus v. Canyon Lake
    Property Owners Assn., supra, 
    118 Cal.App.4th 906
    ; Doe 1 v.
    City of Murrieta (2002) 
    102 Cal.App.4th 899
    .
    23
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    S259216
    Concurring Opinion by Justice Cuéllar
    The young women who are plaintiffs in this case achieved,
    in taekwondo, uncommon excellence. What these young women
    nonetheless experienced in the process is all too common:
    someone they knew, trusted and relied on — their credentialed
    taekwondo coach — betrayed their trust and sexually assaulted
    them. The majority opinion specifies how a court must consider
    certain presumptions and exceptions when resolving whether
    such plaintiffs have any right to recover from entities at whose
    events and facilities the wrongs occurred — in this case, the
    United States Olympic Committee (USOC). I write separately
    to explain how those presumptions and exceptions realize a
    fundamental substantive principle: In California, “[t]ort law” —
    the law of when and how individuals who have suffered harm
    may seek compensation for their injuries through private
    actions — “serves society’s interest in allocating risks and costs
    to those who can better prevent them, and it provides aggrieved
    parties with just compensation.” (Southern California Gas Leak
    Cases (2019) 
    7 Cal.5th 391
    , 394 (SoCal Gas).)
    The majority specifically holds that when a plaintiff
    argues defendant owes a duty based on a “special relationship,”
    the policy analysis we first discussed in Rowland v. Christian is
    only relevant to decide whether to limit that duty. (See maj.
    opn., ante, at pp. 15–19; Rowland v. Christian (1968) 
    69 Cal.2d 108
    , 112–113, 119 (Rowland).) As the majority opinion explains,
    that procedure — first decide whether policy considerations
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    support a duty based on a “special relationship” and then
    consider whether public policy “clearly require[s] an exception”
    (Regents of University of California v. Superior Court (2018) 
    4 Cal.5th 607
    , 628 (Regents)) — reflects our precedents and
    provides a consistent way for courts to answer the threshold
    duty question.
    I write separately to clarify how that procedure fits with
    and furthers our principles and priorities in tort law. First, we
    generally start by presuming everyone has a duty of reasonable
    care “ ‘in the management of his or her property or person’ ”; we
    limit it based on policy considerations like those in Rowland
    only in “a particular category of cases” and only if “ ‘ “clearly
    supported by public policy.” ’ ” (Kesner v. Superior Court (2016)
    
    1 Cal.5th 1132
    , 1143, italics added (Kesner).) Second, in some
    cases, a defendant may argue that he or she was nothing more
    than a disengaged bystander — someone society recognizes as
    categorically outside the scope of any responsibility, having no
    material role in creating the risk of plaintiff’s harm and so no
    duty of reasonable care. Such cases of a named defendant whom
    society considers a true bystander are presumably rare. But the
    distinction between the putative bystander and the risk creator
    can be as subtle in principle as it is challenging to apply in many
    cases. So, we have developed a doctrinal mechanism to sidestep
    the distinction and make arguable edge cases more tractable:
    we allow a plaintiff to establish defendant owed a duty of
    reasonable care in virtue of a “special relationship” regardless of
    whether defendant contributed to the risk of plaintiff’s harm. As
    a matter of tradition, “recognizing” or “identifying” a “special
    relationship” is the label for weighing up those policy
    considerations our legal system treats as most relevant in such
    arguably ambiguous contexts. As the majority explains, once a
    2
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    court recognizes a duty based on a “special relationship,” it
    should also confirm that public policy doesn’t clearly support
    limiting the duty in a clearly defined category of cases. Third,
    ensuring that the duty inquiry remains focused at a relatively
    high level of generality on public policy preserves the proper
    balance between the court and the jury. And so, fourth, the
    procedure we reaffirm today — presuming a general duty of
    reasonable care or “recognizing” a “special relationship” before
    deciding whether public policy clearly supports limiting that
    duty in a category of cases — flexibly serves society’s interest in
    providing just compensation to aggrieved parties and allocating
    risks and costs to those who can better prevent them.
    I.
    A.
    At the core of California tort law is a rule born of common
    law judgments and reaffirmed in statute:             “Everyone is
    responsible, not only for the result of his or her willful acts, but
    also for an injury occasioned to another by his or her want of
    ordinary care or skill in the management of his or her property
    or person . . . .” (Civ. Code, § 1714, subd. (a).)1 This is the
    Legislature’s “conclusory expression[]” that, as “legal duties are
    not discoverable facts of nature,” generally speaking, “liability
    should be imposed for damage done.” (Tarasoff v. Regents of
    University of California (1976) 
    17 Cal.3d 425
    , 434 (Tarasoff).)
    For “injur[ies] occasioned” to others, this principle cuts — other
    things being equal — in favor of widespread liability. (§ 1714,
    subd. (a).)
    1
    All further statutory references are to the Civil Code.
    3
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    Of course, other things aren’t always equal. In Rowland,
    we recognized that the simple statutory presumption of a duty
    of reasonable care, rather than rigid common law categories,
    should generally guide our analysis of whether a defendant
    could be responsible at all. (See Rowland, supra, 
    69 Cal.2d 108
    ,
    118 [common law rules for landowner liability “obscure rather
    than illuminate the proper considerations which should govern
    determination of the question of duty”].) So, Rowland rejected
    a common law system that placed great weight on subtle,
    perhaps vanishing doctrinal distinctions without obvious
    practical or moral significance. (See id. at p. 119 [“we are
    satisfied that continued adherence to the common law
    distinctions can only lead to injustice or, if we are to avoid
    injustice, further fictions with resulting complexity and
    confusion”].) It replaced that system with a focus on the
    relevant consequences. (See id. at pp. 112–113, 117–119.) As
    we’d conveyed earlier that year, duty is just “ ‘an expression of
    the sum total of those considerations of policy which lead the
    law to say that the particular plaintiff is entitled to protection.’ ”
    (Dillon v. Legg (1968) 
    68 Cal.2d 728
    , 734.) That focus is how
    courts should determine when other things aren’t equal:
    presume a general duty of reasonable care, as described in
    section 1714, and create an exception only if “clearly supported
    by public policy.”2 (Rowland, at p. 112.)
    2
    Rowland identified a list of such considerations that would
    often be relevant. (Rowland, supra, 69 Cal.2d at pp. 112–113.)
    We have recognized, though, that the “inquiry hinges not on
    mere rote application of the[] separate so-called Rowland
    factors, but instead on a comprehensive look at the ‘ “sum total” ’
    of the policy considerations at play in the context before us.”
    (SoCal Gas, supra, 
    7 Cal.5th 391
    , 399.)
    4
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    When we decide on such exceptions, we endeavor to take
    account of reasonable inferences about social burdens and
    benefits — or “policy considerations.” We do so in relatively
    general terms to ensure that public policy as it applies to a
    certain broad class of situations with sufficiently common
    features, rather than the bespoke details of any particular
    case, supports a clearly defined departure from the general
    principle that “a person is liable for injuries caused by his failure
    to exercise reasonable care in the circumstances.” (Rowland,
    supra, 69 Cal.2d at p. 112; see also T.H. v. Novartis
    Pharmaceuticals Corp. (2017) 
    4 Cal.5th 145
    , 165 (Novartis);
    Kesner, supra, 
    1 Cal.5th 1132
    , 1143–1144; Cabral v. Ralphs
    Grocery Co. (2011) 
    51 Cal.4th 764
    , 772 (Cabral); Rest.3d Torts,
    Liability for Physical and Emotional Harm (2012) § 7, com. a
    (Rest.3d) [“when liability depends on factors applicable to
    categories of actors or patterns of conduct, the appropriate rubric
    is duty” (italics added)].)
    Against this backdrop, a court-imposed limitation on a
    duty of care is appropriate “only when a court can promulgate
    relatively clear, categorical, bright-line rules of law applicable
    to a general class of cases.” (Rest.3d, supra, § 7, com. a; see also
    Kesner, supra, 
    1 Cal.5th 1132
    , 1143 [“The conclusion that a
    defendant did not have a duty constitutes a determination by
    the court that public policy concerns outweigh, for a particular
    category of cases, the broad principle enacted by the Legislature
    . . . ” (italics added)].) And likewise under Rowland and our
    subsequent decisions, the relevant policy considerations
    primarily relate to the social cost (or benefit) of recognizing a
    duty in a category of cases, whether society would be worse off
    for having a particular class of defendants potentially liable.
    (See Novartis, supra, 4 Cal.5th at p. 168 [we limit duty “ ‘where
    5
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    the social utility of the activity concerned is so great, and
    avoidance of the injuries so burdensome to society, as to
    outweigh the compensatory and cost-internalization values of
    negligence liability’ ” (italics added)]; see also, e.g., Vasilenko v.
    Grace Family Church (2017) 
    3 Cal.5th 1077
    , 1092, 1096;
    Castaneda v. Olsher (2007) 
    41 Cal.4th 1205
    , 1216–1218
    (Castaneda).)
    In deciding whether to limit the general duty, our cases,
    starting with Rowland, have repeatedly emphasized
    defendants’ reasonable ability to anticipate a particular kind of
    harm. A court might limit the duty of some category of
    defendants who have no way to anticipate or avoid a category of
    harm, ensuring responsibility falls on those who can. (See, e.g.,
    Novartis, supra, 
    4 Cal.5th 145
    , 166–167; see also Tarasoff,
    supra, 17 Cal.3d at pp. 434–435.) As a matter of public policy,
    we seek to shift losses to those most able to spread the loss or
    prevent the kind of harm in question — doing so reduces the
    number of injuries and the costs of reducing the number of
    injuries. (See, e.g., Kesner, supra, 1 Cal.5th at p. 1153.) And of
    course, such considerations may cut in the other direction and
    simply support the usual duty of reasonable care in a certain
    category of cases.      (See, e.g., Peterson v. San Francisco
    Community College Dist. (1984) 
    36 Cal.3d 799
    , 807–809
    (Peterson); Palma v. U.S. Industrial Fasteners, Inc. (1984) 
    36 Cal.3d 171
    , 184–185 (Palma).)
    B.
    Sometimes defendants may assert that they were mere
    bystanders to the risk of plaintiff’s harm — that the risk had
    nothing to do with defendants’ “activities” and so defendants
    had no duty to exercise “reasonable care for the safety of others.”
    6
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    (Cabral, 
    supra,
     51 Cal.4th at p. 768.) Arguments that sound in
    this key are particularly relevant in this case.
    In some cases, defendant may, of course, just be wrong.
    Whether someone is a “bystander” to a particular risk is
    shorthand for whether we as a society are willing to say, based
    on reasonable inferences about the benefits and burdens of
    potential liability, that a particular defendant should bear no
    responsibility for the risk. Though the question isn’t before us
    in this case, it bears emphasis, given the all-too-common fact
    pattern, that USOC is hardly a bystander to plaintiffs’ harm.
    USOC is the organizer of the activity where the harm occurred.
    Between the organizer of an activity where someone is wronged
    and a mere bystander there is generally a world of difference:
    one at least sets the stage for what ends up becoming a tragedy;
    the other at most stumbles into the theater in the last act, when
    the story has unfolded and its casualties are known. The person
    who sets the stage owes the players a general duty to exercise
    reasonable care. (See Lugtu v. Cal. Highway Patrol (2001) 
    26 Cal.4th 703
    , 716 [“one’s general duty to exercise due care
    includes the duty not to place another person in a situation in
    which the other person is exposed to an unreasonable risk of
    harm through the reasonably foreseeable conduct (including the
    reasonably foreseeable negligent conduct) of a third person”].)
    The organizer, by bringing people together, may “creat[e] the
    risk” even if less directly than a criminal or intentional
    tortfeasor. (Rest.3d, supra, § 40, com. c.; cf. Williams v. State of
    California (1983) 
    34 Cal.3d 18
    , 23.) Considering the benefits
    and burdens of imposing some responsibility on that person, a
    court may decide that an organizer — even one lacking either
    awareness of a material risk or full control of every
    administrative nuance — is no bystander at all.
    7
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    But in difficult cases, plaintiffs may argue that defendants
    owed them a duty of care in virtue of a “special relationship.”
    (See maj. opn., ante, at pp. 11–12.) In deciding whether
    defendant made plaintiff worse off, courts need not envision a
    world where defendant never existed. Instead they can conclude
    that: “[r]egardless of whether the actor played any role in the
    creation of the risk, a special relationship with others imposes a
    duty of reasonable care.” 3 (Rest.3d, supra, § 40, com. c, italics
    added; see also Regents, supra, 4 Cal.5th at pp. 619–620;
    Tarasoff, supra, 17 Cal.3d at p. 435.)
    “Special relationship” is merely a label for those policy
    considerations that our shared experience has taught us to treat
    as especially relevant in such contexts. As the Restatement
    explains, “The term ‘special relationship’ has no independent
    significance. . . . Whether a relationship is deemed special is a
    conclusion based on reasons of principle or policy.” (Rest.3d,
    supra, § 40, com. h.) Among reasons of principle or policy, our
    precedents place special emphasis on two reasons in particular:
    defendant’s ability to control the environment, to predict and
    prevent the risk, and plaintiff’s reasonable dependency. A
    college or university may be well suited to foresee and control
    risks to students in the campus environment, and students
    3
    Courts may have sometimes suggested that a “special
    relationship” is relevant when defendant is engaged in
    “nonfeasance.” (See maj. opn., ante, at pp. 9–10 & fn. 6.) But
    our reference today to the confused and confusing
    “misfeasance”/“nonfeasance”      distinction   is   just    an
    acknowledgement of a now outmoded oddity. (See, e.g., Kesner,
    supra, 1 Cal.5th at p. 1163; see also Sommer v. Federal Signal
    Corp. (1992) 
    583 N.Y.S.2d 957
    , 961–962; Rest.3d, supra, § 37,
    com. c.; Abraham & Kendrick, There’s No Such Thing as
    Affirmative Duty (2019) 104 Iowa L.Rev. 1649, 1682–1685.)
    8
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    reasonably expect such protection and are especially vulnerable
    without it. (See, e.g., Regents, supra, 4 Cal.5th at p. 625; see
    also Peterson, supra, 
    36 Cal.3d 799
    , 807–809, 813–814.) Or a
    proprietor should be aware of a danger of assault; customers are
    at the mercy of the proprietor; and so the proprietor has a duty
    of reasonable care to reduce such risks. (See, e.g., Morris v. De
    La Torre (2005) 
    36 Cal.4th 260
    , 270; Delgado v. Trax Bar & Grill
    (2005) 
    36 Cal.4th 224
    , 241–242.) In some cases, we have also
    emphasized the burden on defendant of avoiding certain risks.
    (See Castaneda, 
    supra,
     41 Cal.4th at p. 1213.) This focus on
    foreseeability and defendant’s burden tracks defendant’s
    particular ability to reduce risk; the focus on reasonable
    dependence tracks the value society places on reducing that
    risk.
    As the majority explains, there is a second step when
    considering a duty based on a “special relationship” — whether
    public policy supports limiting the duty. (Maj. opn., ante, at pp.
    20, 22.) As when we consider the general duty of reasonable
    care, the analysis of public policy rationales occurs at a
    relatively high level of generality. (See id. at p. 21.) But
    identifying a “special relationship” already means that certain
    policy reasons — especially defendant’s ability to reduce the risk
    in question and blameworthiness for failing to do so — favor
    requiring reasonable care. Those reasons are not likely to justify
    excusing from liability a category of defendants that includes
    the particular defendant. The “special relationship” analysis
    determines that any such category, whatever its precise
    parameters, would exclude at least the particular defendant.
    Instead, primarily the undesirable consequences, the social cost,
    of holding a category of defendants liable for a category of risk
    would support limiting defendant’s duty if anything would.
    9
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    (See, e.g., Castaneda, 
    supra,
     41 Cal.4th at p. 1216 [no duty
    because requiring landlords to screen tenants for gang
    affiliations would lead to discrimination].)
    C.
    While many of our previous decisions focus on duty, they
    readily convey that analyzing duty is just one part of the
    negligence inquiry.    A duty’s existence does not determine
    whether defendant is liable and to what extent. (See Regents,
    supra, 4 Cal.5th at p. 634.) Most liability questions are case-
    specific and so not amenable to analysis in terms of duty — they
    do not allow a categorical determination whether defendant had
    to exercise reasonable care at all. (See Cabral, 
    supra,
     51 Cal.4th
    at pp. 772–774.)
    Unlike duty, the remaining liability questions — breach
    as well as factual and legal causation — are usually questions
    for the jury. What counts as reasonable care in a specific case,
    for instance, is characteristically a question of breach. (See
    Cabral, 
    supra,
     51 Cal.4th at p. 773.) As a policy matter, we tend
    to leave questions of breach to the jury as the institutional actor
    best situated to express, in a particular case, society’s judgment
    of whether the particular cost of avoiding a particular injury
    outweighs the particular cost of the injury. (See, e.g., Dobbs et
    al., The Law of Torts (2d ed. 2020) §§ 21, 161; cf. Calabresi,
    Concerning Cause and the Law of Torts: An Essay for Harry
    Kalven Jr. (1975) 43 U. Chi. L.Rev. 69, 75–76.) As we and other
    courts have long recognized, that judgment is the heart of what
    courts ask in assessing negligence. (See, e.g., United States v.
    Carroll Towing Co. (2d Cir. 1947) 
    159 F.2d 169
    , 173; Crane v.
    Smith (1944) 
    23 Cal.2d 288
    , 298 [“ ‘Where an act is one which a
    reasonable man would recognize as involving a risk of harm to
    10
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    another, the risk is unreasonable and the act is negligent if the
    risk is of such magnitude as to outweigh what the law regards
    as the utility of the act or of the particular manner in which it
    is done’ ”].)
    II.
    A.
    We granted review for one purpose: to clarify what steps
    a court should take when deciding whether a duty based on a
    “special relationship” exists. To provide that clarification, the
    majority restates the two-step process we endorsed in Rowland
    and have regularly followed since — start from a general duty
    of reasonable care based on section 1714 or a “special
    relationship” and then decide whether public policy requires
    limiting it in a clearly defined category of cases. (See maj. opn.,
    ante, at pp. 13–17; see also, e.g., Kesner, supra, 1 Cal.5th at pp.
    1143–1144.)       Through that process, California tort law
    structures a court’s threshold decision about how potential
    liability affects society’s interests even as it also embodies and
    preserves a degree of flexibility. Maintaining the balance
    between structure and flexibility, guided by important,
    longstanding values — allocating risks and costs to those who
    can avoid them, and ensuring just compensation — is critical to
    making tort law both relevant and useful.
    The following scenario shows how. A plaintiff alleges that
    a youth organization did not exercise reasonable care leading to
    a program leader molesting him. (See Juarez v. Boy Scouts of
    America, Inc. (2000) 
    81 Cal.App.4th 377
    , 385–386 (Juarez).)
    The defendant organization makes six arguments that it should
    not have a duty of reasonable care. First, it argues that it was
    merely a bystander. Second, it argues that organizations like it
    11
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    are not generally well-situated to predict and prevent
    molestation. (See 
    id.
     at pp. 408–409.) Third, it is specifically
    not well-situated to predict and prevent molestation. (See ibid.)
    Fourth, requiring organizations like it to prevent molestation
    would divert funds from youth programs and charitable
    enterprises thus harming society. (See id. at p. 409.) Fifth, it
    had procedures in place to prevent molestation. (See id. at pp.
    405–406.) And sixth, the likelihood of abuse was low, so
    plaintiff’s molestation was not foreseeable. (See id. at pp. 403–
    404.)
    Of course, the court may reject defendant’s “bystander”
    argument out of hand. If it does, the court should start with
    defendant’s general duty of reasonable care. And then the court
    considers whether large organizations’ purported inability to
    prevent molestation and the risk of charities diverting funds
    “ ‘clearly support[]’ ” limiting or eliminating the duty in an
    “entire category of cases.” (Cabral, 
    supra,
     51 Cal.4th at pp. 771,
    772.) To assess those arguments, the court will need to
    determine whether “large organizations” or “charities” form a
    clearly defined category. But those arguments are the right
    kind of reason, at the right level of generality, to consider as a
    basis for limiting a duty. And so it is a question for the court
    whether, in light of any and all other policy considerations, those
    reasons are sufficiently substantial to support limiting a duty
    for charitable organizations, if that category can be clearly
    defined.
    On the other hand, the court could worry that defendant
    may be no more than a bystander. Perhaps the organization has
    an educational mission but primarily licenses its name to local
    chapters. Nonetheless, the court may decide defendant is in fact
    well-situated to prevent molestation, notwithstanding
    12
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    defendant’s argument to the contrary. For example, the court
    might reason that children in the local chapters are especially
    vulnerable because they are children, and the organization can
    control local chapters’ activities through the licensing process.
    So, defendant should exercise reasonable care to limit the risk
    of molestation regardless of whether it “created that risk.” In
    drawing that inference, the court “recognizes” defendant has a
    “special relationship” with plaintiff. The court then proceeds to
    a second step: deciding whether public policy “clearly supports”
    limiting the duty of reasonable care in a category of cases. At
    this step in the analysis, large organizations’ purported inability
    to avoid molestation can have little relevance — whatever may
    be true of other large organizations, the court has already
    rejected the argument as to this organization. But it remains
    for the court, in light of all other relevant public policy
    considerations, to decide whether concerns about charitable
    organizations diverting funds “clearly require an exception.”
    (Regents, supra, 4 Cal.5th at p. 628.)
    In both these versions of the scenario, the court trains
    attention on reasons of public policy when deciding whether to
    limit a duty. It does so by considering possible consequences at
    a high level of generality and with an eye to the loss to society
    from imposing liability. A court can more effectively focus at the
    appropriate level of generality if it considers policy reasons to
    limit a duty after presuming a duty or recognizing the duty of a
    specific defendant based on a “special relationship.” (See maj.
    opn., ante, at pp. 21–22.) And the requirement that such reasons
    clearly support limiting a duty of reasonable care ensures that
    courts act for good reason and not based on idle speculation.
    By contrast, defendant’s other arguments — about specific
    measures it has already taken or its ability to predict that a
    13
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    specific harm would arise — bear simply on the details of the
    present case, and not on duty. (See Cabral, 
    supra,
     51 Cal.4th at
    p. 773.) The argument about having done enough concerns
    whether defendant in fact took reasonable care, a question of
    breach usually for the jury. (Id. at p. 772.) And the argument
    about specific foreseeability would be relevant to whether
    plaintiff had established proximate cause, also usually a
    question for the jury. (Id. at pp. 772–773.)
    Here too, the two-step process we endorse today serves an
    important function:          it helps courts guard against
    inappropriately taking questions from the jury. At the stage of
    deciding whether to limit a duty, courts should not look to
    features of the specific case but to considerations of public policy,
    clearly defined. By first presuming a duty or recognizing a duty
    based on a “special relationship” and then deciding whether
    public policy clearly requires limiting that duty, courts focus at
    the right level of generality at the right time. And that focus
    serves as a check on courts wading into fact-specific questions of
    breach or causation. (Cabral, supra, 51 Cal.4th at pp. 772–773.)
    In addition to these clarifying functions, the procedure we
    approve today remains flexible. We don’t disapprove our prior
    precedents that quickly or silently presume or recognize a duty
    before focusing primarily or entirely on whether policy
    considerations support it. (See maj. opn., ante, at pp. 18–19, fn.
    8 [discussing Palma, supra, 36 Cal.3d at pp. 184–185].) And
    while we disapprove several Court of Appeal cases, we don’t
    disapprove them to the extent they presume a general duty of
    reasonable care and find the policy considerations in Rowland
    support holding defendants to that duty. (See, e.g., Juarez,
    supra, 
    81 Cal.App.4th 377
    , 401–410.)
    14
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    This flexibility is rooted in tort law’s decidedly limber
    structure: a duty of reasonable care based on a “special
    relationship” may be functionally indistinguishable from the
    general duty of reasonable care.          As the Restatement
    acknowledges, some special-relationship-type duties “overlap
    with the general duty of reasonable care”; they are “a specialized
    application” of that general duty. (Rest.3d, supra, § 40, com. h.)
    In cases where “the actor’s conduct might have played a role in
    creating the risk to the injured party” there is a general “duty of
    reasonable care” even without any sort of “special relationship.”
    (Id., § 40, com. c, italics added.) What we must discern is if
    society has defensible reasons to restrict liability in certain
    situations; otherwise, a person’s duty is to exercise reasonable
    care. Whether there’s a “special relationship” is a question that
    structures, without ever supplanting, the ultimate inquiry —
    guiding deliberation just enough to avoid turning every duty
    question into a fact-specific monologue about the defendant’s
    role in creating the risk. (See, e.g., Tarasoff, supra, 17 Cal.3d at
    pp. 434–435; Rest.3d, supra, § 40, com. h.)
    B.
    Properly understood, the special relationship question
    plays a limited but important role under our law. If plaintiffs
    don’t want to wade into whether defendants “created the risk”
    of the harm plaintiffs experienced, they can argue that
    defendant owed a duty of reasonable care, based on a “special
    relationship.” To do so, plaintiffs have to show why specific
    policy factors under the “special relationship” rubric supported
    such a duty. We don’t address whether plaintiffs in this case did
    in fact make such a showing. And we don’t address the
    possibility, because it was not presented to us, that USOC had
    a general duty to exercise reasonable care in the management
    15
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    of its property or person.        (See § 1714, subd. (a).)     It
    presumptively would if it were not a “bystander,” and we
    certainly don’t decide public policy clearly supports exempting a
    category of organizations including USOC from that general
    duty. (See generally House Energy & Commerce Committee,
    Nassar and Beyond: A Review of the Olympic Community’s
    Efforts to Protect Athletes from Sexual Abuse (Dec. 20, 2018).)
    While we don’t address those claims today, we reaffirm
    that courts should assess such claims with the ultimate aim of
    deciding whether requiring reasonable care serves the goals tort
    law embodies: to achieve appropriate deterrence and
    compensate victims. (See SoCal Gas, supra, 
    7 Cal.5th 391
    , 394;
    see also Rest.3d, supra, § 40, com. h.)
    III.
    Tort law relies heavily on the concept of duty to render
    tractable a reality where lives are at risk in the very world that
    sustains them, and people are bound by intricate and far-
    reaching ties of responsibility and norms of reciprocity. But
    “ ‘ “duty” is not sacrosanct in itself’ ”; it is a means to an end,
    “ ‘only an expression of the sum total of those considerations of
    policy which lead the law to say that the particular plaintiff is
    entitled to protection.’ ” (Dillon v. Legg, supra, 68 Cal.2d at p.
    734.)    The majority opinion today sensibly clarifies the
    procedure for recognizing a duty where plaintiff attempts, by
    arguing for a “special relationship,” to cut through the knot of
    whether defendant did or didn’t create a risk. Specifically, it
    holds that the Rowland factors as such just feature in deciding
    whether to limit a duty. In so doing, it reaffirms that under
    California law everyone presumptively owes a duty of
    reasonable care in the management of his or her property or
    16
    BROWN v. USA TAEKWONDO
    Cuéllar, J., concurring
    person to avoid injuring others. And it doesn’t suggest that a
    corporate person’s duty of reasonable care in the management
    of its person or property extends any less than to the limits of
    foreseeable harm without substantial, concrete policy reasons to
    the contrary.
    The two-step procedure we endorse is grounded in long-
    established principles, emphasizing not only the importance of
    offering civil recourse and compensation to those harmed but
    also the value of allocating responsibility for losses to minimize
    future harm. We start from the premise that a duty of
    reasonable care ordinarily exists, whether arising generally or
    based on a “special relationship.” We then consider whether
    public policy requires limiting that duty in a clearly defined
    category of cases, assessed at the right level of
    generality. Implicit in this arrangement is the latitude for
    courts to minimize harms through the proper allocation of
    losses, and to compensate victims for their uncommon injuries
    — including in cases where the facts are not only tragic, but
    tragically all-too-common. Which is why I concur.
    CUÉLLAR, J.
    17
    See next page for addresses and telephone numbers for counsel who argued in Supreme Court.
    Name of Opinion Brown v. USA Taekwondo
    __________________________________________________________________________________
    Unpublished Opinion
    Original Appeal
    Original Proceeding
    Review Granted XX 
    40 Cal.App.5th 1077
    Rehearing Granted
    __________________________________________________________________________________
    Opinion No. S259216
    Date Filed: April 1, 2021
    __________________________________________________________________________________
    Court: Superior
    County: Los Angeles
    Judge: Michael P. Vicencia
    __________________________________________________________________________________
    Counsel:
    Estey & Bomberger, Stephen J. Estey; Corsiglia McMahon & Allard, B. Robert Allard; Turek Law,
    Kenneth C. Turek; Williams Iagmin and Jon R. Williams for Plaintiffs and Appellants.
    Arbogast Law, David M. Arbogast; Siminou Appeals, Benjamin I. Siminou; Herzog, Yuhas, Ehrlich &
    Ardell, Ian I. Herzog; The Bronson Firm and Steven M. Bronson for Consumer Attorneys of California as
    Amicus Curiae on behalf of Plaintiffs and Appellants.
    Esner, Chang & Boyer, Holly N. Boyer and Shea S. Murphy for National Crime Victim Bar Association
    and Manly, Stewart & Finaldi as Amici Curiae on behalf of Plaintiffs and Appellants.
    Kjar, McKenna, Stockalper, Patrick E. Stockalper, Matthew A. Schiller and Mina M. Morkos; Horvitz &
    Levy, Mitchell C. Tilner, Steven S. Fleischman and Yen-Shyang Tseng for Defendant and Respondent
    USA Taekwondo.
    Clyde & Co. US, Douglas J. Collodel, Margaret M. Holm, M. Christopher Hall; Covington & Burling, Beth
    Brinkmann, Mitch A. Kamin and Carolyn J. Kubota for Defendant and Respondent United States Olympic
    Committee.
    Munger, Tolles & Olson, Donald B. Verrilli, Jr., Hailyn J. Chen and John B. Major for National Collegiate
    Athletic Association as Amicus Curiae on behalf of Defendant and Respondent United States Olympic
    Committee.
    Counsel who argued in Supreme Court (not intended for publication with opinion):
    Jon R. Williams
    Williams Iagmin LLP
    666 State Street
    San Diego, CA 92101
    (619) 238-0370
    Yen-Shyang Tseng
    Horvitz & Levy LLP
    3601 W. Olive Ave., 8th Floor
    Burbank, CA 91505-4681
    (818) 995-0800
    Beth S. Brinkmann
    Covington & Burling LLP
    1 CityCenter, 850 10th St. NW
    Washington, DC 20001
    (202) 662-5312