State v. Peeler ( 2016 )


Menu:
  • ******************************************************
    The ‘‘officially released’’ date that appears near the
    beginning of each opinion is the date the opinion will
    be published in the Connecticut Law Journal or the
    date it was released as a slip opinion. The operative
    date for the beginning of all time periods for filing
    postopinion motions and petitions for certification is
    the ‘‘officially released’’ date appearing in the opinion.
    In no event will any such motions be accepted before
    the ‘‘officially released’’ date.
    All opinions are subject to modification and technical
    correction prior to official publication in the Connecti-
    cut Reports and Connecticut Appellate Reports. In the
    event of discrepancies between the electronic version
    of an opinion and the print version appearing in the
    Connecticut Law Journal and subsequently in the Con-
    necticut Reports or Connecticut Appellate Reports, the
    latest print version is to be considered authoritative.
    The syllabus and procedural history accompanying
    the opinion as it appears on the Commission on Official
    Legal Publications Electronic Bulletin Board Service
    and in the Connecticut Law Journal and bound volumes
    of official reports are copyrighted by the Secretary of
    the State, State of Connecticut, and may not be repro-
    duced and distributed without the express written per-
    mission of the Commission on Official Legal
    Publications, Judicial Branch, State of Connecticut.
    ******************************************************
    STATE v. PEELER—SECOND CONCURRENCE
    PALMER, J., with whom EVELEIGH and McDON-
    ALD, Js., join, concurring. In State v. Santiago, 
    318 Conn. 1
    , 
    122 A.3d 1
    (2015), a majority of this court
    concluded that, following the legislature’s April, 2012
    decision to abolish the death penalty for all future
    offenses; see Public Acts 2012, No. 12-5 (P.A. 12-5);
    capital punishment no longer comports with the state
    constitutional prohibition against cruel and unusual
    punishment. See State v. 
    Santiago, supra
    , 10, 86, 118–19,
    140; see also Conn. Const., art. I, §§ 8 and 9. Specifically,
    we determined that to execute individuals convicted of
    committing capital felonies prior to April, 2012, now
    that the legislature has determined that the death pen-
    alty is neither necessary nor appropriate for any crimes
    committed after that date, no matter how atrocious
    or depraved, would be out of step with contemporary
    standards of decency and devoid of any legitimate peno-
    logical justification. See State v. 
    Santiago, supra
    , 9,
    14–15. Accordingly, we vacated the death sentence of
    the defendant in that case, Eduardo Santiago, and we
    ordered that he be resentenced to life in prison without
    the possibility of release. 
    Id., 140. The
    present appeal is brought by another defendant,
    Russell Peeler, who, like Santiago, committed a capital
    felony and was sentenced to death prior to the enact-
    ment of P.A. 12-5. Ordinarily, our determination in San-
    tiago that the death penalty is no longer constitutional
    would control the outcome of the present case as well,
    and the defendant and others similarly situated would
    be entitled to resentencing consistent with our decision
    in Santiago. The state, however, has argued that Santi-
    ago was decided without the benefit of adequate brief-
    ing by the parties and that, as a result, the majority in
    Santiago made a series of legal and historical errors
    that led to an incorrect decision. Indeed, the state goes
    so far as to contend that our decision in Santiago was
    so unjust, and so completely devoid of legitimacy, that
    it should be afforded no precedential value and now
    may be overturned, only nine months later, merely
    because the composition of this court has changed.
    I agree with and join the per curiam opinion in this
    case, in which the majority concludes that Santiago
    remains binding and valid authority, and that other con-
    victed capital felons who have been sentenced to death
    are, therefore, entitled to be resentenced forthwith con-
    sistent with that decision. I write separately because I
    categorically reject any suggestion that the parties did
    not have the opportunity to brief these issues in Santi-
    ago, or that the court in that case overlooked key
    authorities, arguments, or historical developments that,
    if properly considered, would have resulted in a differ-
    ent outcome. We already have explained at some length
    why the parties, and particularly the state, had a full
    and fair opportunity to address the issues on which our
    decision in Santiago was based. See 
    id., 120–26; see
    also State v. Santiago, 
    319 Conn. 935
    , 936–40, 
    125 A.3d 520
    (2015) (denying state’s motion for stay of execution
    of judgment in Santiago pending resolution of appeal
    in present case). In this concurring opinion, I briefly
    address the state’s principal historical and legal argu-
    ments and explain why they are unpersuasive.
    I
    HISTORICAL ANALYSIS
    The state first argues that, in Santiago, we ‘‘relied
    on flawed historical analysis to justify [our] departure
    from well established principles of law . . . .’’ Specifi-
    cally, the state contends that we incorrectly concluded
    that, prior to the adoption of the 1818 constitution,
    Connecticut courts were authorized to review the con-
    stitutionality of allegedly cruel and unusual punish-
    ments. In reality, the state contends, the authority to
    review and determine the propriety of a punishment
    always has rested solely with the legislature. In so
    arguing, the state fundamentally misunderstands the
    relevant Connecticut history, this court’s precedents,
    and the basis of our decision in Santiago. Although a
    full review of the relevant history and the scope of the
    state’s confusion in this regard lies beyond the ambit
    of this opinion, I briefly address three of the most signifi-
    cant flaws in the state’s analysis.
    First, the state misperceives the purpose of the dis-
    cussion in part I of our decision in State v. 
    Santiago, supra
    , 
    318 Conn. 1
    5–46, and the role that that discussion
    played in the outcome of the case. Our goal in part I
    of Santiago was not to establish that this court has
    the constitutional authority to strike down legislatively
    enacted punishments as impermissibly cruel and
    unusual. There was no need to establish that principle
    because, as the defendant explains, and as the state
    ultimately concedes, the state lost that argument
    decades—if not centuries—ago. Just four years after
    the adoption of the 1818 constitution, Chief Justice Ste-
    phen Titus Hosmer, writing for the Connecticut
    Supreme Court of Errors, rejected the asserted ‘‘omnip-
    otence of the legislature’’ with respect to punitive sanc-
    tions such as imprisonment and clarified that the review
    of such laws was properly within the purview of the
    judiciary. Goshen v. Stonington, 
    4 Conn. 209
    , 225 (1822);
    see also C. Collier, ‘‘The Connecticut Declaration of
    Rights Before the Constitution of 1818: A Victim of
    Revolutionary Redefinition,’’ 
    15 Conn. L
    . Rev. 87, 97
    (1982) (‘‘the delegates to the Connecticut [c]onstitu-
    tional [c]onvention of 1818 overrode the protestations
    of the Federalist old republicans who still clung to a
    faith in legislative supremacy and the common law to
    uphold all of the natural rights of individuals’’). More
    recently, in State v. Lamme, 
    216 Conn. 172
    , 179–80, 
    579 A.2d 484
    (1990), and again in State v. Ross, 
    230 Conn. 183
    , 249, 
    646 A.2d 1318
    (1994), cert. denied, 
    513 U.S. 1165
    , 
    115 S. Ct. 1133
    , 
    130 L. Ed. 2d 1095
    (1995), we
    rejected the state’s argument that our state constitution
    confers the authority to determine what constitutes
    cruel and unusual punishment solely on the legislature.1
    Our purpose in part I of Santiago, then, was merely to
    trace in greater detail than we previously had the origins
    and contours of our state constitutional freedoms from
    cruel and unusual punishment. In other words, the ques-
    tion we considered in Santiago was the scope of the
    rights at issue, and not which branch of government is
    charged with securing their enforcement.2
    The second fundamental flaw in the state’s historical
    analysis is its suggestion that, prior to 1818, Connecticut
    courts played no role in securing our common-law and
    statutory freedoms from cruel and unusual punishment.
    In Santiago, we reviewed numerous instances and con-
    texts in which each of the three branches of government
    at times sought to temper what were perceived as cruel
    or unusual punishments. With respect to the judiciary,
    for example, we noted agreement among scholars of
    early Connecticut history that (1) magistrates enforced
    the criminal law during the colonial period so as to
    avoid needless cruelty, especially with regard to capital
    crimes; State v. 
    Santiago, supra
    , 
    318 Conn. 29
    –31; (2)
    Connecticut courts began to nullify dubious capital sen-
    tences as early as the 1660s; 
    id., 31–32 n.27;
    and (3)
    in the years leading up to the adoption of the 1818
    constitution, ‘‘courts were adopting a milder practice
    in applying the capital law.’’ (Internal quotation marks
    omitted.) 
    Id., 36. Indeed,
    the very source on which the
    state relies explains at the outset how this preconstitu-
    tional history sowed the seeds that ultimately blos-
    somed into this court’s judicial review authority: ‘‘When
    we speak of law in early Connecticut—legislation, adju-
    dication, and executive administration—we speak of
    the law of the magistrates.’’ E. Goodwin, The Magistracy
    Rediscovered: Connecticut, 1636–1818 (1981) p. 11.
    ‘‘The Puritan’s peculiar concept of the magistracy was
    . . . a unique contribution to the development of later
    concepts of independent judiciaries, distinct functions
    for courts of law, and even, perhaps, the distinctively
    American notion of judicial review.’’ 
    Id. In Lamme,
    hav-
    ing reviewed this history, we concluded that ‘‘the most
    significant aspect of the pre-1818 declaration of rights
    is that it had constitutional overtones even though it was
    statutory in form. The [d]eclaration and supplementary
    statutes relating to individual rights were grounded in
    the Connecticut common law and viewed as inviolate.
    Abridgements perpetrated by the government were con-
    sidered void on their face and courts were to refuse
    to enforce them.’’ (Emphasis added; internal quotation
    marks omitted.) State v. 
    Lamme, supra
    , 
    216 Conn. 179
    ,
    quoting C. 
    Collier, supra
    , 
    15 Conn. L
    . Rev. 94; see also
    Binette v. Sabo, 
    244 Conn. 23
    , 79, 
    710 A.2d 688
    (1998)
    (Katz, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
    Accordingly, although the state is certainly correct that
    the legislature played a central role in establishing and
    enforcing our traditional freedoms from cruel and
    unusual punishment during Connecticut’s preconstitu-
    tional era, the state has offered no reason to conclude,
    counter to well established authority, that the legisla-
    ture has been the exclusive guardian of those freedoms.3
    Of course, any discussion of the relationship between
    the judicial and legislative authorities during the pre-
    constitutional era, and especially prior to the creation
    of this court in 1784, must be qualified by the recognition
    that the General Court, which, at the end of the seven-
    teenth century, was renamed the General Assembly,
    blended and simultaneously exercised both judicial and
    lawmaking functions during that period. See, e.g., H.
    Cohn & W. Horton, Connecticut’s Four Constitutions
    (1988) p. 21; E. Goodwin, supra, pp. 33–35, 52–54. In
    some sense, then, any discussion of whether the legisla-
    ture or the judiciary was responsible for securing the
    people’s freedom from cruel and unusual punishment
    is academic. In any event, it is clear that the adoption
    of the state’s first formal constitution in 1818 was moti-
    vated in no small part by a desire to create an indepen-
    dent judiciary tasked with securing those basic con-
    stitutional liberties, and that these changes embodied
    a rejection of the belief ‘‘that republican government
    with legislative supremacy was the best safeguard of
    personal liberties.’’ (Internal quotation marks omitted.)
    State v. 
    Lamme, supra
    , 
    216 Conn. 180
    ; see also Starr
    v. Pease, 
    8 Conn. 541
    , 546–48 (1831) (declaration of
    rights contained in 1818 constitution imposed limita-
    tions on excessive powers previously wielded by legisla-
    ture); H. Cohn & W. Horton, supra, p. 23 (call for
    independent judiciary was primary reason for constitu-
    tional convention).
    The third fundamental flaw in the state’s historical
    analysis is the state’s failure to adequately and accu-
    rately document its theory that the freedoms from cruel
    and unusual punishment enshrined in the state constitu-
    tion arose from and were limited to legislative efforts
    to circumscribe the harsh and arbitrary punishments
    imposed by colonial magistrates. Although the state
    weaves a lengthy and intriguing narrative in support of
    this theory, the state’s account is sparse on citation,
    and, it must be said, one searches the cited authorities
    in vain for the propositions that the state attributes to
    them. Nowhere in the cited text, for example, does
    Professor Lawrence B. Goodheart state that the Ludlow
    Code of 1650—from which article first, § 9, of the state
    constitution derives its origins—was drafted to address
    public concerns that magistrates were wielding exces-
    sive power or imposing arbitrary penal sanctions. See
    L. Goodheart, The Solemn Sentence of Death: Capital
    Punishment in Connecticut (2011) pp. 11–12. Quite the
    contrary. In the section of his book on which the state
    relies, Goodheart explains that the colonists generally
    deferred to magistrates’ interpretation of Biblical
    authority; see 
    id., p. 9;
    and he discusses at some length
    the key role that the magistrates played in securing
    fundamental liberties and tempering the colonies’ dra-
    conian capital statutes: ‘‘The statutes are deceptive as
    to what occurred in practice. The laws represented a
    religious ideal, a public declaration, as the 1672 [colo-
    nial] code put it, of what was ‘suitable for the people
    of Israel.’ The judicial system was much more lenient.
    The courts aspired to be scrupulous and fair. There
    was concern to balance individual protection with the
    greater good. Drawing on centuries of English tradition,
    the Puritans upheld civil rights, including . . . no tor-
    ture [and] no cruel or barbarous punishments . . . .
    Attorneys did not usually function in either colony; the
    wise and impartial rule of the magistrates was deemed
    sufficient.’’ (Footnotes omitted.) 
    Id., p. 14.
       The state’s reliance on Everett Goodwin’s book, The
    Magistracy Rediscovered: Connecticut, 1636–1818, is
    similarly misplaced. The state cites page 103 of Good-
    win’s book for the proposition that, in the state’s words,
    ‘‘Connecticut’s history is unique in selecting the legisla-
    ture as the body ‘safeguarding’ citizens from abusive,
    unlegislated, court-imposed punishments, and not the
    other way around.’’ The cited passage, however, con-
    tains no mention whatsoever of abusive, court-imposed
    punishments. Rather, Goodwin merely discusses the
    fact that, as a general matter, Connecticut’s early legal
    system relied less on English common law than did the
    other American colonies. E. Goodwin, supra, p. 103. He
    also references the evolution in Chief Justice Zephaniah
    Swift’s thinking with respect to the separation of pow-
    ers; although Swift initially believed in the primacy of
    the legislature; see 
    id., pp. 99–100,
    103; he ultimately
    came to conclude that, because the legislature is vulner-
    able to ‘‘ ‘undue and improper influence’ ’’; 
    id., p. 114;
    the courts must play an important role with respect to
    the constitutional review of statutes. See 
    id., pp. 99,
    101, 103, 109–10, 114, 160 n.34. In other parts of his
    book, Goodwin explains that the colonists codified an
    extreme version of the criminal law but ‘‘[left] the miti-
    gation to the discretion of the [m]agistrate’’; (internal
    quotation marks omitted) 
    id., p. 27;
    and that the discre-
    tion invested in the magistrates reflected the Puritans’
    confidence in their wisdom and godliness. 
    Id., p. 30.
    Like Goodheart, then, Goodwin provides little support
    for the state’s account.
    The other sources on which the state relies likewise
    fail to support—and in some cases flatly belie—the
    state’s theory that Connecticut’s traditional freedoms
    from cruel and unusual punishment originated from
    and were limited to a commitment to statutory law as
    a bulwark against abusive judicial sentencing practices.
    William Holdsworth, for example, explains that magis-
    trates in both the Connecticut and New Haven colonies
    ‘‘repeatedly avoided imposing the full penalties pre-
    scribed by . . . [law]’’; W. Holdsworth, Law and Soci-
    ety in Colonial Connecticut, 1636–1672 (1974) p. 124
    (unpublished doctoral dissertation, Claremont Gradu-
    ate School); and that, although Connecticut’s first crimi-
    nal statutes were more severe than those of Massa-
    chusetts, Connecticut’s colonial code actually ‘‘placed
    fewer restrictions on the discretionary powers of the
    magistrates, and increased the penalties they could
    impose for certain crimes . . . .’’ 
    Id., p. 132.
    Holds-
    worth explains that ‘‘these differences reflect a greater
    consensus in Connecticut between rulers and ruled and
    a greater degree of trust of the one for the other, but
    they also reflect the growth in magisterial power
    . . . .’’ (Emphasis added.) Id.4 The state’s heavy reliance
    on the language of Ludlow’s Code also misses the point.
    Ludlow’s Code authorized not only those punishments
    established by express legislative enactment, but also,
    in the absence of a controlling statute, penal sanctions
    imposed on the basis of the magistrates’ own under-
    standing of ‘‘the word of God.’’ (Internal quotation
    marks omitted.) L. Goodheart, supra, p. 12.
    Even more troubling is the state’s representation that
    this court’s decision in Pratt v. Allen, 
    13 Conn. 119
    ,
    125 (1839), stands for the proposition that, ‘‘[w]ith the
    exception of moving the judiciary to an independent
    body, the 1818 constitution ‘left the legislative depart-
    ment as it found it.’ ’’ (Emphasis added.) The state
    uses the quoted passage from Pratt in an attempt to
    demonstrate that the judiciary, which, the state alleges,
    had no authority to review the appropriateness of legis-
    latively imposed punishments under the colonial com-
    mon law, obtained no greater authority in this respect
    under the 1818 constitution. The state, however,
    neglects to account for the sentence in Pratt immedi-
    ately preceding the one that it quotes. The full passage
    reads as follows: ‘‘The [constitution of Connecticut], so
    far as it respects the legislature, is conversant princi-
    pally with its organization, the authority of its separate
    branches, and the privileges of its members. But we
    look in vain for the character of its legislative acts any
    further than as they are, in some measure, restrained,
    by the bill of rights. In short, with few limitations, it
    left the legislative department as it found it.’’ (Emphasis
    added.) Pratt v. 
    Allen, supra
    , 125. The only fair reading
    of Pratt, then, is that the creation of an independent
    judiciary was not the only change effected by the state
    constitution, as the state suggests. Rather, the high-
    lighted portions of the foregoing passage, which the
    state omits, clearly indicate that the constitution, in
    tandem with the creation of an independent judiciary,
    constrained the authority of the legislature to enact
    laws that infringe our basic liberties.
    A thorough review of the cited historical sources and
    our related cases thus leaves one with the discomforting
    impression that the state, in its apparent zeal to retain
    the death penalty, has mischaracterized not only this
    court’s precedents but history itself. For all of these
    reasons, I reject the state’s contention that this court,
    in Santiago, relied on a flawed historical analysis or
    exercised its powers of judicial review in a manner
    precluded by either tradition or precedent.
    II
    DELAYS AND INFREQUENCY
    OF IMPLEMENTATION
    The state’s next argument is that, in Santiago, we
    improperly considered the infrequency with which the
    death penalty is imposed in Connecticut, as well as
    the lengthy delays in carrying out capital sentences, in
    determining that capital punishment no longer com-
    ports with contemporary standards of decency and no
    longer serves any legitimate penological purpose. Spe-
    cifically, the state contends that (1) this court rejected
    these arguments in State v. Rizzo, 
    303 Conn. 71
    , 191–94,
    
    31 A.3d 1094
    (2011), cert. denied,        U.S.     , 133 S.
    Ct. 133, 
    184 L. Ed. 2d 64
    (2012), (2) nothing has changed
    since our decision in Rizzo to justify a different out-
    come, and (3) in any event, our conclusion that delays
    in carrying out capital sentences render the punishment
    unconstitutional is precluded by this court’s decision
    in State v. Smith, 5 Day (Conn.) 175 (1811). I consider
    each argument in turn.
    Nothing in our decision in Rizzo precluded the result
    we reached in Santiago. In Rizzo, we looked at the
    growing infrequency of capital sentencing and execu-
    tions throughout the country. See State v. 
    Rizzo, supra
    ,
    
    303 Conn. 192
    –94 and nn. 89–94. At that time, we did
    not reject out of hand the argument of the defendant,
    Todd Rizzo, that the death penalty had come to be so
    rarely used in the United States as to constitute cruel
    and unusual punishment. Nor did we specifically con-
    sider recent developments in this state. Rather, we rec-
    ognized that both capital sentences and executions
    were declining in number nationwide, and we acknowl-
    edged that several of the likely causes of those declines
    suggested diminishing public support for capital punish-
    ment. See 
    id., 192–94. At
    the same time, however, we
    noted that the decline also might reflect other, short-
    term factors, such as the economic recession, supply
    shortages of one of the lethal injection drugs, and tem-
    porary uncertainty about the legal status of capital pun-
    ishment pending the United States Supreme Court’s
    decision in Baze v. Rees, 
    553 U.S. 35
    , 
    128 S. Ct. 1520
    ,
    
    170 L. Ed. 2d 420
    (2008). State v. 
    Rizzo, supra
    , 192–94.
    We also noted that the number of executions carried
    out nationally in 2007 and 2008, although a recent low,
    remained substantially higher than during the early
    1990s, just prior to our decision in State v. 
    Ross, supra
    ,
    
    230 Conn. 183
    . See State v. 
    Rizzo, supra
    , 192. Accord-
    ingly, and in light of the fact that capital punishment
    remained legal in most states; see 
    id., 190; we
    could
    not conclude at that time that infrequency of imposition
    alone was sufficient evidence that the death penalty
    had become impermissibly cruel and unusual. See 
    id., 194. Because
    capital punishment remained legal, and
    so presumably retained some deterrent value, we also
    did not have cause at that time to consider whether
    lengthy delays in carrying out capital sentences
    deprived capital punishment of its retributive value.
    Much has changed since Rizzo. Two additional
    states—Maryland and Nebraska—have abolished capi-
    tal punishment.5 The number of executions carried out
    nationally has continued to decline, falling by more than
    one third from 2011 to 2015, and is now lower than
    at any time since 1991.6 The number of new capital
    sentences imposed likewise continues to fall; the total
    fell by nearly 40 percent between 2011 and 2015, and
    is now by far the lowest of the post-Furman7 era.8 It
    has been more than one decade since the last execution
    was carried out in New England (Michael Ross, who
    essentially volunteered to die, in 2005), and more than
    five decades since the one before that (Joseph Taborsky
    in 1960). That this is all true even though many of the
    short-term factors we considered in Rizzo no longer
    apply strongly suggests that the persistent, long-term
    declines in capital punishment are just what they appear
    to be—evidence that contemporary standards of
    decency have evolved away from execution as a neces-
    sary and acceptable form of punishment. Significantly,
    the Death Penalty Information Center has published
    its 2015 year-end summary, and the statistics for 2015
    continue to reflect a substantial decline in the imposi-
    tion and implementation of the death penalty nation-
    wide.9 If anything, the pace of decline is accelerating.
    Since our decision in Rizzo, a number of respected
    jurists also have concluded that the infrequent imposi-
    tion and delayed execution of the death penalty call
    its constitutionality into question. See, e.g., Glossip v.
    Gross,      U.S.     , 
    135 S. Ct. 2726
    , 2764–76, 
    192 L. Ed. 2d
    761 (2015) (Breyer, J., with whom Ginsburg, J., joins,
    dissenting); Jones v. Chappell, 
    31 F. Supp. 3d 1050
    ,
    1065–67 (C.D. Cal. 2014) (Carney, J.), rev’d sub nom.
    Jones v. Davis, 
    806 F.3d 538
    (9th Cir. 2015). At the same
    time, new legal scholarship has emerged that power-
    fully debunks the state’s argument that the rarity with
    which the death penalty is imposed in Connecticut
    merely indicates that our capital felony statutes are
    working as intended, and that the ultimate punishment
    is being reserved for the very worst offenders.10
    Most significant, however, is the fact that, in 2012,
    the year after we decided Rizzo, the legislature enacted
    P.A. 12-5, which prospectively abolished the death pen-
    alty in Connecticut. Legislative abolition fundamentally
    altered the constitutional calculation we conducted in
    Rizzo. It cast in a new light all of the various factors
    pointing to reduced societal acceptance of capital pun-
    ishment. It swept away the most compelling arguments
    that capital punishment serves legitimate penological
    functions. And it reflected the awareness of the legisla-
    ture that the infrequency with which the death penalty
    is imposed and the slowness with which it is carried
    out dramatically undermine its ability to serve a valid
    retributive function and to secure justice and peace for
    the families of murder victims. See State v. 
    Santiago, supra
    , 
    318 Conn. 1
    03 and n.99. In light of these dramatic,
    recent changes in the constitutional landscape, it is
    difficult to comprehend how the state can argue with
    a straight face that ‘‘[t]here is nothing new under the
    sun . . . .’’ (Footnote omitted.)
    Lastly, I am not persuaded by the state’s assertion
    that State v. 
    Smith, supra
    , 5 Day (Conn.) 175, a case
    decided two decades before the invention of the type-
    writer, somehow precludes the result this court reached
    in Santiago. Smith was the first published case in which
    this court considered whether two sentences of impris-
    onment may be imposed to run consecutively without
    offending the state’s common-law prohibition against
    cruel and unusual punishment. See 
    id., 178. Because
    ‘‘such ha[d] been the usage of our courts, for many
    years past,’’ we concluded that postponing the com-
    mencement of the second term of imprisonment until
    the first had been completed was neither unprece-
    dented nor cruel. 
    Id., 179. Nowhere
    in the court’s brief
    discussion of that issue, however, did it consider or
    decide any of the novel questions raised in Santiago
    and in the present appeal: (1) whether a method of
    punishment that is only imposed a few times per decade
    and only carried out a few times per century may be
    deemed to violate contemporary standards of decency;
    (2) whether the retributive value of a punishment—both
    to the offender and to the victims—dissipates when
    decades pass before it is carried out; and (3) whether
    the various procedural safeguards established by the
    federal and state legislatures and courts, which permit
    individuals on death row to pursue nearly endless appel-
    late and postconviction remedies, reflect society’s
    reluctance to impose the ultimate punishment and
    unwillingness to see it imposed erroneously. For these
    reasons, there is no doubt that, in Santiago, we properly
    considered the actual practices of this state with respect
    to the imposition and carrying out of capital sentences
    in concluding that capital punishment constitutes what
    has come to be seen as cruel and unusual.
    III
    RACIAL DISPARITIES AND PROSECUTORIAL
    DISCRETION
    The state next contends that, in Santiago, when we
    observed that ‘‘the selection of which offenders live
    and which offenders die appears to be inescapably
    tainted by caprice and bias’’; State v. 
    Santiago, supra
    ,
    
    318 Conn. 1
    06–107; we improperly relied on statistical
    evidence suggesting that people of color who offend
    against white victims are more likely than other offend-
    ers to be capitally charged and sentenced to death. The
    state argues that (1) a court in a habeas case currently
    pending on appeal before this court rejected these sta-
    tistical claims; see In re Death Penalty Disparity
    Claims, Docket No. TSR-CV-05-4000632-S, 
    2013 WL 5879422
    (Conn. Super. October 11, 2013); (2) studies
    that have documented racial disparities in other juris-
    dictions are not relevant to this state because, in the
    1970s, Connecticut enacted the narrowest capital sen-
    tencing scheme in the country, and (3) in any event,
    such claims were not properly before us in Santiago.
    The short answer to the state’s arguments is simply
    to reiterate what we stated in Santiago: the question
    whether there are presently statistically significant
    racial disparities in the imposition of the death penalty
    in Connecticut was not before us in that case, as it is
    not before us in the present case, and we did not reach
    or rely on any such conclusion in holding the death
    penalty unconstitutional. See State v. 
    Santiago, supra
    ,
    
    318 Conn. 1
    09 n.104. What we did consider in Santi-
    ago—on the basis of an abundance of legal scholarship,
    persuasive federal and state authority, a thorough
    review of the relevant history, and our knowledge of
    human nature—was the proposition that any sentencing
    scheme that allows prosecutors not to seek and jurors
    not to impose the death penalty for any reason ‘‘neces-
    sarily opens the door’’ to caprice and bias of various
    sorts, racial or otherwise. (Emphasis added.) 
    Id., 108. In
    other words, we agreed, as a matter of law, with
    those judges and scholars who have concluded that
    such a system cannot, in principle, ensure that the ulti-
    mate punishment will be imposed fairly and objectively,
    as it must be. The factual question of the extent to
    which the undisputed facial disparities in Connecticut’s
    capital charging and sentencing system do in fact result
    from subconscious racial biases never entered into
    our analysis.11
    The state’s argument to the contrary—that Connecti-
    cut law does not afford jurors unlimited discretion to
    find mitigating factors—is unavailing. ‘‘It is well estab-
    lished that federal constitutional . . . law establishes
    a minimum national standard for the exercise of individ-
    ual rights . . . .’’ (Internal quotation marks omitted.)
    State v. Miller, 
    227 Conn. 363
    , 379, 
    630 A.2d 1315
    (1993);
    see also State v. 
    Santiago, supra
    , 
    318 Conn. 1
    8–19 (rule
    applies to eighth amendment protections). The United
    States Supreme Court repeatedly has instructed that
    juries must retain the discretion to consider any poten-
    tially mitigating factors when deciding whether to
    impose a capital sentence,12 and the supremacy clause
    of the federal constitution bars both our legislature and
    this court from abridging that discretion. It is true that
    the United States Supreme Court has explained, and
    we have recognized, that the states remain free to chan-
    nel the manner in which jurors exercise their broad
    discretion, such as by instructing that mitigating factors
    should be considered in light of ‘‘all the facts and cir-
    cumstances of the case.’’ (Internal quotation marks
    omitted.) State v. 
    Ross, supra
    , 
    230 Conn. 284
    ; see also
    
    id. (ultimately concluding
    that ‘‘[t]he instructions as
    given did not preclude the jury from giving mitigating
    force to any fact, taken alone or taken in conjunction
    with any other facts presented’’ [emphasis added]). Ulti-
    mately, however, there is nothing in the law of Connecti-
    cut or in this court’s precedents that prevents a capital
    jury from considering racial, ethnic, or other such fac-
    tors when deciding whether to impose the ultimate
    punishment. None of the cases cited by the state are
    to the contrary.
    Because we did not rely on any factual finding of
    recent racial disparities in Santiago, and we do not do
    so now, it is not necessary to address fully the state’s
    first and second arguments. I would, however, briefly
    note my disagreement with each.
    With respect to In re Death Penalty Disparity
    Claims, I do not understand the court in that case to
    have rejected the petitioners’ claim that there is statisti-
    cally significant evidence that people of color who kill
    white victims are capitally charged, and thus placed at
    risk of death, at a much higher rate than are other
    offenders, and that those disparities cannot reasonably
    be accounted for by innocuous, nonracial factors.
    Rather, I understand the court to have acknowledged
    that there are significant racial disparities in capital
    charging (but not sentencing) in Connecticut; see In
    re Death Penalty Disparity 
    Claims, supra
    , 
    2013 WL 5879422
    *19, *24–*25; but to have concluded that, as a
    matter of federal constitutional and discrimination law,
    such disparities do not impair the validity of capital
    sentences imposed in this state. See 
    id., *7, *10,
    *16–*18,
    *22–*25. The court further concluded, as a matter of
    law, that the constitution of Connecticut affords no
    greater protections than does federal law in this regard.
    
    Id., *3, *8.
    Whether the court in In re Death Penalty
    Disparity Claims was correct with respect to the latter
    conclusion is a question that this court has yet to
    answer.
    Turning to the state’s second argument, I am troubled
    by its repeated contention that the abundant evidence
    of racial disparities in other jurisdictions is irrelevant
    to the Connecticut experience because, ‘‘[i]n response
    to Furman [v. Georgia, 
    408 U.S. 238
    , 
    92 S. Ct. 2726
    , 33 L.
    Ed. 2d 346 (1972)], Connecticut enacted the narrowest
    capital sentencing scheme in the country.’’ The state
    relies on the following footnote in a 1980 law review
    article to support its proposition: ‘‘Connecticut’s capital
    punishment law is unique in one regard. It enumerates
    five mitigating circumstances. But it states that the sen-
    tence shall not be death, if any mitigating factor exists,
    whether statutorily defined or not. In other words,
    unlike the practice in every other state (except to some
    extent Colorado), a Connecticut jury, once it finds a
    mitigating fact, whether enumerated or not, does not
    have the power to balance or weigh the mitigating fact
    against any aggravating fact that may be present. The
    very existence of a mitigating fact precludes a death
    sentence.’’ S. Gillers, ‘‘Deciding Who Dies,’’ 129 U. Pa.
    L. Rev. 1, 104 n.10 (1980). Setting aside the question of
    whether the quoted passage even stands for the proposi-
    tion for which the state cites it, the state is well aware
    that Connecticut’s capital punishment law has not been
    as Gillers describes it for more than two decades. In
    1995, the legislature amended General Statutes (Rev.
    to 1995) § 53a-46a to eliminate the provision on which
    the state relies. See Public Acts 1995, No. 95-19, § 1.
    Since then, juries in capital cases in Connecticut have
    balanced aggravating and mitigating factors in deciding
    whether to impose the ultimate punishment, just as
    they do in our sister states. In addition, any past idiosyn-
    crasies in Connecticut’s capital sentencing scheme are
    simply irrelevant to the central question of whether
    minority defendants accused of offending against white
    victims are capitally charged at a disproportionately
    high rate.
    IV
    EXECUTION OF THE INNOCENT
    The state next contends that, in Santiago, we improp-
    erly considered the possibility that an innocent person
    may be erroneously executed as one reason why the
    death penalty fails to serve a legitimate retributive pur-
    pose. Although the state does not dispute the growing
    body of research that recently persuaded two justices
    of the United States Supreme Court that capital punish-
    ment is likely unconstitutional for this reason; see
    Glossip v. 
    Gross, supra
    , 
    135 S. Ct. 2756
    –59 (Breyer, J.,
    with whom Ginsburg, J., joins, dissenting); the state
    contends that the possibility of error is no longer a
    concern in this state because none of the eleven men
    currently subject to a sentence of death in Connecticut
    has professed his innocence.
    Even if this were true, and even if it were properly
    subject to judicial notice, the state simply ignores the
    fact that, under P.A. 12-5, new prosecutions can still be
    brought at any time for capital felonies committed prior
    to April, 2012. Of the thousands of murders committed
    in Connecticut over the past several decades, some of
    which would be death eligible, many remain unsolved.13
    Accordingly, it is not at all unlikely that, if the death
    penalty were to remain available, the state would con-
    tinue to seek it for some who have been accused of
    committing those crimes, with the possibility that an
    innocent person could wrongly be sentenced to die.
    Indeed, in the four years since the legislature prospec-
    tively abolished capital punishment, one additional
    offender has been sentenced to death,14 and at least
    one other likely would have been capitally charged if
    not for our decision in Santiago.15 The state is fully
    aware of this possibility, as both the majority and a
    dissenting justice discussed it in Santiago. See State
    v. 
    Santiago, supra
    , 
    318 Conn. 1
    06 and n.102; 
    id., 397 (Espinosa,
    J., dissenting). I am, therefore, perplexed
    as to why the state continues to press this argument.
    V
    STATUTORY INTERPRETATION
    The state next contends that, in Santiago, we improp-
    erly departed from our ordinary approach to questions
    of statutory interpretation. The basis of the state’s
    objection is not entirely clear. For example, the state
    contends that, in Santiago, we failed to make what it
    considers to be ‘‘the required predicate finding that the
    language of [P.A. 12-5] itself is ambiguous,’’ but, in the
    very next paragraph of its brief, the state quotes our
    conclusion in Santiago that ‘‘the policy judgments
    embodied in the relevant legislation are ambiguous.’’
    State v. 
    Santiago, supra
    , 
    318 Conn. 89
    ; see also 
    id., 89 n.
    91 (discussing textual ambiguity); 
    id., 59–73 (consid-
    ering competing interpretations of statutory text). More
    fundamentally, the state appears to assume that Santi-
    ago presented a conventional question of statutory
    interpretation, for which we are constrained to follow
    the dictates of General Statutes § 1-2z, which embodies
    the plain meaning rule. At the same time, the state also
    appears to recognize that claims that a penal sanction
    constitutes cruel and unusual punishment are reviewed
    according to a unique standard of review that requires
    us to assess ‘‘what a penal statute actually indicates
    about contemporary social mores.’’ (Emphasis in origi-
    nal.) 
    Id., 72 n.62.
       In any event, to the extent that it was not transparent
    from our decision in Santiago, I take this opportunity to
    clarify that a claim that a penal sanction impermissibly
    offends contemporary standards of decency is not a
    question of statutory interpretation subject to § 1-2z and
    the attendant rules of construction.16 When a reviewing
    court considers whether a challenged punishment is
    excessive and disproportionate according to current
    social standards, legislative enactments are just one—
    albeit the most important—factor to be considered.
    Moreover, our goal in evaluating those enactments is
    not merely to determine what the legislature intended
    to accomplish through the enabling legislation (the
    touchstone of statutory interpretation), but also to
    understand what the legislation says and signifies
    about our society’s evolving perspectives on crime and
    punishment. In that respect, we look not only to the
    words of the statute, but also to its legislative history,
    the aspirations and concerns that were before the legis-
    lature as it deliberated, and, to the extent we can per-
    ceive them, the political motivations and calculations
    that affected or effected the outcome of those delibera-
    tions. The latter, as much as anything else, offer a portal
    into what the final legislative product indicates about
    our contemporary standards of decency.
    VI
    RETRIBUTION AND VENGEANCE
    The state next argues that, in Santiago, we incor-
    rectly concluded that the death penalty now lacks any
    legitimate penological purpose because, among other
    things, the legislature’s decision to retain it on a retroac-
    tive only basis was intended primarily to satisfy a public
    thirst for vengeance toward two especially notorious
    inmates, rather than to accomplish permissible retribu-
    tive purposes. The state counters that (1) the legislature
    regularly and properly crafts penal statutes in response
    to public reactions to specific notorious and vicious
    crimes, and (2) P.A. 12-5 was crafted to make good on
    a promise to the families of murder victims that death
    would be repaid with death, and making good on such
    a promise is a legitimate manifestation of retributive
    justice.
    Although it is undoubtedly true that the legislature
    is naturally responsive to powerful public sentiments,
    in the arena of criminal law as in other areas, that alone
    does not insulate a penal statute from constitutional
    scrutiny. As we explained in Santiago, if the mere fact
    that a punishment arose out of the democratic process
    established that it served a legitimate penological pur-
    pose, then the eighth amendment and its state constitu-
    tional counterparts would be largely superfluous. See
    
    id., 134–35. Rather,
    as the United States Supreme Court
    explained in United States v. Brown, 
    381 U.S. 437
    , 
    85 S. Ct. 1707
    , 
    14 L. Ed. 2d 484
    (1965), ‘‘in a representative
    republic . . . [in which] the legislative power is exer-
    cised by an assembly . . . [that] is sufficiently numer-
    ous to feel all the passions [that] actuate a multitude
    . . . yet not so numerous as to be incapable of pursuing
    the objects of its passions . . . barriers [must] be
    erected to ensure that the legislature [does] not over-
    step the bounds of its authority . . . .’’ (Emphasis omit-
    ted; internal quotation marks omitted.) 
    Id., 443–44. ‘‘Nothing
    is more common than for a free people, in
    times of heat and violence, to gratify momentary pas-
    sions, by letting into the government principles and
    precedents [that afterward] prove fatal to themselves.’’
    (Internal quotation marks omitted.) 
    Id., 444. The
    court
    further emphasized that, in a government of divided
    powers in which each checks the others, the judiciary
    must play a central role in tempering the legislature’s
    ‘‘[peculiar] susceptib[ility] to popular clamor,’’ espe-
    cially with respect to the levying of punishments against
    particular infamous persons. (Internal quotation marks
    omitted.) 
    Id., 445. It
    is that task that we undertook
    in Santiago.
    With respect to promises made to families and friends
    of the victims, we all have deep compassion for those
    who have been made to suffer the curse of crime. See,
    e.g., Luurtsema v. Commissioner of Correction, 
    299 Conn. 740
    , 772, 
    12 A.3d 817
    (2011). As we explained in
    Santiago, however, whatever vows the state has made
    that it will seek and impose the ultimate penalty have
    proved to be unkeepable. Of the thousands of heinous
    murders that have been committed in Connecticut in
    the last six decades, only two have resulted in execu-
    tions, and those only after the offenders renounced
    their appellate and habeas remedies and, in essence,
    volunteered to die. For the countless other families
    and secondary victims, the promise that they will find
    ‘‘restoration and closure’’17 in the hangman’s noose, or
    an infusion of sodium thiopental, has proved to be a
    false hope. The vast majority of even the worst of the
    worst offenders are never sentenced to die, and, for
    the minuscule number who are, the delays are endless.
    Accordingly, although I am sensitive to the state’s plea,
    I remain convinced that the death penalty, as it has
    been implemented in Connecticut over the past one-
    half century, serves no useful retributive purpose.18
    VII
    CONSTITUTIONAL TEXT
    The state next argues that the death penalty can never
    be held unconstitutional because ‘‘it is expressly permit-
    ted by the Connecticut constitution.’’ The state further
    argues that our reliance in Santiago on People v. Ander-
    son, 
    6 Cal. 3d 628
    , 
    493 P.2d 880
    , 
    100 Cal. Rptr. 152
    , cert.
    denied, 
    406 U.S. 958
    , 
    92 S. Ct. 2060
    , 
    32 L. Ed. 2d 344
    (1972);19 see State v. 
    Santiago, supra
    , 
    318 Conn. 1
    31; was
    misplaced because that decision has been the subject of
    some judicial and scholarly criticism. Instead, the state
    recommends for our consideration a concurring opin-
    ion authored by Justice Antonin Scalia, who opines that
    ‘‘[i]t is impossible to hold unconstitutional that which
    the [c]onstitution explicitly contemplates.’’ (Emphasis
    omitted.) Glossip v. 
    Gross, supra
    , 
    135 S. Ct. 2747
    (Scalia,
    J., concurring).
    The dissenting justices in Santiago raised similar
    objections. See, e.g., State v. 
    Santiago, supra
    , 
    318 Conn. 246
    –47 (Rogers, C. J., dissenting); 
    id., 353–54 (Zarella,
    J., dissenting). The majority responded to them at some
    length in that decision; see 
    id., 129–32; and
    no useful
    purpose would be served by rehashing those arguments
    here. I would, however, make a few additional points.
    Regardless of whether one considers Anderson itself
    to be persuasive authority, recent scholarship both vin-
    dicates the reasoning of that case and sheds light on
    the defects in Justice Scalia’s position. As Professor
    Joseph Blocher explains, ‘‘some supporters of the death
    penalty continue to argue . . . that the death penalty
    must be constitutional because the [f]ifth [a]mendment
    explicitly contemplates it. The appeal of this argument
    is obvious, but its strength is largely superficial, and is
    also mostly irrelevant to the claims being made against
    the constitutionality of capital punishment. At most,
    the references to the death penalty in the [constitution]
    may reflect a founding era assumption that it was consti-
    tutionally permissible at that time. But they do not
    amount to a constitutional authorization; if capital pun-
    ishment violates another constitutional provision, it is
    unconstitutional.’’ J. Blocher, ‘‘The Death Penalty and
    the Fifth Amendment’’ (December 16, 2015) p. 1 (unpub-
    lished manuscript), available at http://scholarship.law.
    duke.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=6227&context=
    faculty_scholarship; see also B. Ledewitz, ‘‘Judicial
    Conscience and Natural Rights: A Reply to Professor
    Jaffa,’’ 10 U. Puget Sound L. Rev. 449, 459 (1987) (‘‘The
    fifth amendment represents a limitation on capital pun-
    ishment, that it was not to be carried out in the future
    as it had been in the past. One could hardly call the
    due process clause an endorsement of capital pun-
    ishment.’’).
    The state’s argument appears to be that, with respect
    to the Connecticut constitution in particular, the due
    process clause of article first, § 8, cannot form the basis
    for holding capital punishment unconstitutional when
    that same clause authorizes the state to impose the
    death penalty, as long as it affords adequate due process
    of law. As the aforementioned authorities explain, how-
    ever, this argument rests on two conceptual errors.
    First, a declaration of rights such as that contained in
    article first of the Connecticut constitution, or the fed-
    eral Bill of Rights, is not a grant of governmental author-
    ity; rather, it delineates the rights and freedoms of the
    people as against the government. See State v. Conlon,
    
    65 Conn. 478
    , 488–89, 
    33 A. 519
    (1895); see also J.
    Blocher, supra, pp. 3, 8–9. For the state to suggest that
    one right (to be free from cruel and unusual punish-
    ment) bars the exercise of another right (presumably,
    to execute capital felons) is to fundamentally misunder-
    stand the nature of the freedoms enshrined in article
    first. States have powers, and the people have rights
    vis-a`-vis the exercise of those powers; there is no gov-
    ernmental right to kill.
    A second, related conceptual error is the state’s
    apparent failure to distinguish necessary from sufficient
    conditions. See J. Blocher, supra, p. 9. Article first, § 8,
    of the Connecticut constitution, as amended by article
    seventeen and twenty-nine of the amendments, which
    provides in relevant part that ‘‘[n]o person shall be . . .
    deprived of life . . . without due process of law . . .
    [or] held to answer for any crime, punishable by death
    . . . unless upon probable cause,’’ indicates that, to the
    extent that the death penalty is otherwise permissible
    and authorized by law, it may be imposed only after
    the defendant is afforded adequate due process. In other
    words, due process is a necessary condition for the
    imposition of the death penalty, and article first, § 8,
    as amended, thereby restricts the circumstances under
    which that penalty may be imposed. There is no textual
    support, however, for the state’s apparent belief that
    article first, § 8, as amended, makes the provision of
    due process a sufficient condition for the imposition
    of capital punishment, so that the state is authorized
    to carry out executions as long as it has complied with
    the requirements of due process. Of course, as we
    explained in State v. 
    Ross, supra
    , 
    230 Conn. 249
    –50,
    the fact that the founders expressly referenced capital
    punishment in the state constitution, and the fact that
    such references were retained when article first, § 8,
    was amended at the most recent constitutional conven-
    tion in 1965, provides strong evidence that, at those
    times, capital punishment was seen to be a legal and
    permissible penalty that comported with standards of
    decency of the day. But that implies at most that the
    death penalty is not unconstitutional per se, at all times
    and under all circumstances. As Blocher explains, ‘‘one
    could grant Justice Scalia’s argument that the death
    penalty is not ‘categorically impermissible’ while main-
    taining that the conditions for its constitutional use are
    not currently satisfied and perhaps never will be.’’ J.
    Blocher, supra, p. 5.
    VIII
    STARE DECISIS
    Lastly, the state argues that, to the extent that Santi-
    ago was wrongly decided and resulted in an unjust
    outcome, the principle of stare decisis, that is, the duty
    of a court to adhere to established precedent, does
    not require that we uphold the conclusion that capital
    punishment offends the state constitution. The state
    itself concedes, however, that ‘‘a court should not over-
    rule its earlier decisions unless the most cogent reasons
    and inescapable logic require it . . . .’’ (Citation omit-
    ted; internal quotation marks omitted.) State v. Alvarez,
    
    257 Conn. 782
    , 793–94, 
    778 A.2d 938
    (2001). The state
    has provided neither reasons nor logic to justify overrul-
    ing our recent decision in Santiago.20
    First, having fully reviewed the state’s arguments and
    the authorities on which it relies, I find no reason to
    conclude that Santiago was wrongly decided, let alone
    unjust. The state has not pointed to any controlling
    cases that we overlooked, persuasive arguments that
    we failed to consider, or fatal defects in our reasoning.
    Most of the state’s arguments are ones that we expressly
    considered and rejected in Santiago, and the others
    fail to hold up under scrutiny or simply miss the point.
    In a disturbing number of instances, the authorities on
    which the state relies do not even support the proposi-
    tion for which the state cites them.
    Second, the state has failed to identify any case, and
    I am not aware of any, in which a court of last resort
    has reversed its own landmark constitutional ruling
    after a matter of just months. For this court to entomb
    the death penalty in Santiago, and then to exhume and
    revivify it nine months later, would be unprecedented
    and would make a mockery of the freedoms enshrined
    in article first of the state constitution. If the people
    of Connecticut believe that we have misperceived the
    scope of that constitution, it now falls on them to
    amend it.21
    Finally, I question whether a decision in this case to
    overrule Santiago, and to revive the death penalty for
    the defendant in the present case, could survive federal
    constitutional scrutiny. The defendant in Santiago has
    received the benefit of our decision therein, namely,
    that capital punishment is an excessive and dispropor-
    tionate punishment, and that he no longer may be exe-
    cuted. The state now proposes that we reauthorize the
    death penalty22 and proceed to execute the defendant,
    Peeler, solely on the basis of the fact that a different
    panel of this court, having considered essentially the
    same arguments only months later, might reach a differ-
    ent result. Nothing could be more arbitrary than to
    execute one convicted capital felon who committed his
    offense prior to the enactment of P.A. 12-5 but to spare
    another, solely on the basis of the timing of their
    appeals. For this reason as well, I reject the state’s
    request that we overrule Santiago and revive the death
    penalty in Connecticut.
    1
    The state, while ultimately acknowledging that the court in Ross
    ‘‘employed an independent analysis of the facial validity of a [capital] sen-
    tence,’’ suggests that we did so principally to review the procedural safe-
    guards that must be followed before the death penalty may be imposed,
    and not to review the constitutionality of the punishment itself. This argu-
    ment ignores the fact that, in both State v. 
    Ross, supra
    , 
    230 Conn. 245
    –52,
    and State v. Rizzo, 
    303 Conn. 71
    , 184–201, 
    31 A.3d 1094
    (2011), cert. denied,
    U.S.     , 
    133 S. Ct. 133
    , 
    184 L. Ed. 2d 64
    (2012), we purported to conduct
    a comprehensive analysis of precisely the question presented in Santiago
    and the present case, namely, whether, as a general matter, the death penalty
    had come to offend the state constitutional prohibition against cruel and
    unusual punishment, either because it fails to comport with contemporary
    standards of decency or because it no longer serves any legitimate penologi-
    cal purpose. The fact that capital punishment survived constitutional scru-
    tiny in Ross and Rizzo but failed to do so in Santiago does not indicate
    that we applied a less deferential standard of review in the latter case, as
    the state contends. Rather, it simply reflects the fact that the legislature’s
    prospective abolition of the death penalty in 2012 fundamentally reshaped
    the penological landscape and thus altered our constitutional calculation.
    2
    I further note that the state’s argument that our reliance on State v.
    Smith, 5 Day (Conn.) 175 (1811), was misplaced because that decision failed
    to address the constitutionality of the sentence at issue proves little and
    less. I will return to the holdings and implications of Smith. For now, suffice
    it to say that one should not expect that a case decided in 1811, seven years
    before the adoption of this state’s first formal constitution, would speak to
    the constitutionality of the sentence in question. Rather, to reiterate, in
    Santiago, we cited to pre-1818 authority such as Smith and Lung’s Case,
    
    1 Conn. 428
    (1815), merely as evidence of the well established common-
    law freedoms from cruel and unusual punishment that were incorporated
    into the due process provisions of the 1818 constitution. This court’s power
    of judicial review was never in question.
    3
    The other cases on which the state relies are readily distinguishable or
    otherwise fail to support the propositions for which the state cites them.
    See, e.g., State v. 
    Lamme, supra
    , 
    216 Conn. 183
    (indicating that cases on
    which state relies in construing article first, § 9, are not binding precedent);
    State v. Davis, 
    158 Conn. 341
    , 358–59, 
    260 A.2d 587
    (1969) (relying on fact
    that five successive legislatures had declined to abolish death penalty in
    holding that penalty complied with federal constitution), vacated in part,
    
    408 U.S. 935
    , 
    92 S. Ct. 2856
    , 
    33 L. Ed. 2d 750
    (1972); State v. Williams, 
    157 Conn. 114
    , 120–21, 
    249 A.2d 245
    (1968) (when sentence that ultimately was
    imposed was not illegal, failure of jail physician to provide certain medication
    prior to trial did not constitute cruel and unusual punishment), cert. denied,
    
    395 U.S. 927
    , 
    89 S. Ct. 1783
    , 
    23 L. Ed. 2d 244
    (1969); Simborski v. Wheeler,
    
    121 Conn. 195
    , 197–98, 201, 
    183 A. 688
    (1936) (challenge to form of execution
    was based on statutory rather than constitutional ground). Although the
    state suggests that the United States Supreme Court vacated Davis on other
    grounds, in truth, it was precisely this court’s determination that legislative
    authorization insulated the death penalty from constitutional review that
    the Supreme Court rejected, in light of its decision in Furman v. Georgia,
    
    408 U.S. 238
    , 239–40, 
    92 S. Ct. 2726
    , 
    33 L. Ed. 2d 346
    (1972).
    4
    The portions of Holdsworth’s dissertation suggesting that early criminal
    statutes were enacted in response to concerns over the abuse of magisterial
    discretion primarily refer to the prevalence of such concerns in Massachu-
    setts. See W. Holdsworth, supra, pp. 104, 109, 167–71. The state fails to
    acknowledge that Holdsworth repeatedly emphasizes that such concerns
    were less pronounced in the Connecticut and New Haven colonies and that,
    in fact, those colonies continued to increase the authority and discretion
    of the magistrates after the adoption of Ludlow’s Code. See 
    id., pp. 104,
    132, 137, 152–53, 171–72. As Holdsworth concludes, ‘‘[Ludlow] omitted most
    of the Bay Colony’s liberties and permitted the magistrates greater discretion
    in dealing with many crimes. At one time, Connecticut’s leaders were dis-
    trustful of magisterial discretion, but they became less anxious about it
    once they assumed the mantle of authority themselves, trusting themselves
    to deal sternly but justly with the multitude of problems that beset their
    commonwealth.’’ 
    Id., pp. 171–72;
    but see J. Trumbull, Historical Notes on
    the Constitutions of Connecticut, 1639–1818 (1901) pp. 9, 42 (noting that
    prominent founders of Connecticut, such as Thomas Hooker, founded colony
    to escape magisterial tyranny that they perceived in Massachusetts).
    5
    Death Penalty Information Center, ‘‘States With and Without the Death
    Penalty,’’ available at http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/states-and-without-
    death-penalty (last visited May 12, 2016) (Maryland abolished death penalty
    in 2013, and Nebraska abolished death penalty in 2015).
    6
    See Death Penalty Information Center, ‘‘Executions by Year,’’ available at
    http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/executions-year (last visited May 12, 2016)
    (detailing number of executions in United States since 1976).
    7
    Furman v. Georgia, 
    408 U.S. 238
    , 
    92 S. Ct. 2726
    , 
    33 L. Ed. 2d 346
    (1972).
    8
    See Death Penalty Information Center, ‘‘Death Sentences by Year: 1976–
    2014,’’ available at http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/death-sentences-year-
    1977-2009 (last visited May 12, 2016); Death Penalty Information Center,
    ‘‘2015 Sentencing,’’ available at http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/2015-
    sentencing (last visited May 12, 2016).
    9
    See generally Death Penalty Information Center, ‘‘The Death Penalty
    in 2015: Year End Report,’’ available at http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/
    documents/2015YrEnd.pdf (last visited May 12, 2016).
    10
    See J. Donohue, Capital Punishment in Connecticut, 1973–2007: A Com-
    prehensive Evaluation from 4686 Murders to One Execution (2011) pp.
    131–46,       available    at    http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/documents/
    DonohueCTStudy.pdf (last visited May 12, 2016) (finding little relationship
    between egregiousness and rate at which cases are charged as capital felon-
    ies, and noting that, of seventeen offenders potentially chargeable with
    capital felony murder for hire, only thirteen were charged capitally and only
    one—Santiago—was sentenced to death).
    11
    Nor did we conclude in Santiago that Connecticut’s prosecutors have
    exercised their discretion with anything less than complete professionalism.
    In Santiago, we opined only that, in light of the constraints imposed by
    federal law, it is virtually impossible to exercise such discretion so as to
    ensure that the imposition of the death penalty, writ large, will not be
    arbitrary and capricious.
    12
    See, e.g., Johnson v. Texas, 
    509 U.S. 350
    , 361, 
    113 S. Ct. 2658
    , 125 L.
    Ed. 2d 290 (1993); see also Walton v. Arizona, 
    497 U.S. 639
    , 663, 
    110 S. Ct. 3047
    , 
    111 L. Ed. 2d 511
    (1990) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and concurring
    in the judgment) (opining that state cannot preclude consideration of defen-
    dant’s racial beliefs as mitigating evidence), overruled in part on other
    grounds by Ring v. Arizona, 
    536 U.S. 584
    , 
    122 S. Ct. 2428
    , 
    153 L. Ed. 2d 556
    (2002).
    13
    See, e.g., Division of Criminal Justice, State of Connecticut, ‘‘Cold
    Cases—Open,’’ available at http://www.ct.gov/csao/cwp/view.asp?a=1798&
    q=291462 (last visited May 12, 2016).
    14
    See State v. Roszkowski, Superior Court, judicial district of Fairfield,
    Docket No. FBT-CR-06-0218479-T.
    15
    See State v. Howell, Superior Court, judicial district of New Britain,
    Docket No. HHB-CR-15-0279874-T.
    16
    For the same reasons, the state’s argument that our decision in Santiago
    was precluded by Connecticut’s savings statutes, General Statutes §§ 1-1 (t)
    and 54-194, also misses the mark.
    17
    The state notes in its brief that maintaining the death penalty could
    serve a retributive purpose by ‘‘providing a sense of restoration and closure
    to victims and their families . . . .’’
    18
    The state, which quotes from the Book of Ecclesiastes in its brief, would
    do well to consider the following passage therefrom: ‘‘Better not vow at all
    than vow and fail to pay.’’ Ecclesiastes 5:5, in The New English Bible: Old
    Testament (Oxford University Press & Cambridge University Press 1970)
    p. 931.
    19
    We relied on Anderson for the proposition that ‘‘incidental references
    to the death penalty in a state constitution merely acknowledge that the
    penalty was in use at the time of drafting; they do not forever enshrine the
    death penalty’s constitutional status as standards of decency continue to
    evolve . . . .’’ State v. 
    Santiago, supra
    , 
    318 Conn. 1
    31.
    20
    Justice Espinosa, in her dissenting opinion in the present case, repeat-
    edly suggests that Santiago is not binding precedent because it was decided
    on the basis of the subjective moral beliefs of the majority, contrary to
    precedent and in violation of our sworn duty to follow the law. We already
    have said everything that needs to be said with respect to these baseless
    assertions. See State v. 
    Santiago, supra
    , 
    318 Conn. 86
    n.89. With respect to
    the issue of stare decisis, we merely reiterate that our decision in Santiago
    did not overturn controlling precedent but, rather, applied the well estab-
    lished evolving standards of decency test in the context of a fundamentally
    new and different legal landscape, in which capital punishment has been
    legislatively abolished—an issue of first impression never before addressed
    by this or any other court prior to the adoption of P.A. 12-5. Justice Espinosa’s
    reliance on Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Pena, 
    515 U.S. 200
    , 234, 115 S.
    Ct. 2097, 
    132 L. Ed. 2d 158
    (1995), therefore, is misplaced.
    21
    Whether capital punishment might be reinstated in Connecticut by
    means other than a constitutional amendment is not before us in this case.
    See State v. 
    Santiago, supra
    , 
    318 Conn. 86
    n.88.
    22
    I take no position on the question of whether, following our decision
    in Santiago, this court has the power to reauthorize the death penalty
    without new enabling legislation. Compare Jawish v. Morlet, 
    86 A.2d 96
    , 97
    (D.C. 1952) (statute held to be unconstitutional is ‘‘not void in the sense
    that it is repealed or abolished’’ but remains dormant, and may be revived
    by subsequent judicial decision), with Dascola v. Ann Arbor, 
    22 F. Supp. 3d
    736, 744–46 (E.D. Mich. 2014) (decision holding statute unconstitutional
    essentially nullifies statute, and if court should later determine that it does
    in fact pass constitutional muster, legislature must reenact it).