Matal v. Tam , 137 S. Ct. 1744 ( 2017 )


Menu:
  • (Slip Opinion)              OCTOBER TERM, 2016                                       1
    Syllabus
    NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is
    being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued.
    The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been
    prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader.
    See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 
    200 U.S. 321
    , 337.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    Syllabus
    MATAL, INTERIM DIRECTOR, UNITED STATES
    PATENT AND TRADEMARK OFFICE v. TAM
    CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR
    THE FEDERAL CIRCUIT
    No. 15–1293. Argued January 18, 2017—Decided June 19, 2017
    Simon Tam, lead singer of the rock group “The Slants,” chose this mon-
    iker in order to “reclaim” the term and drain its denigrating force as
    a derogatory term for Asian persons. Tam sought federal registration
    of the mark “THE SLANTS.” The Patent and Trademark Office
    (PTO) denied the application under a Lanham Act provision prohibit-
    ing the registration of trademarks that may “disparage . . . or bring
    . . . into contemp[t] or disrepute” any “persons, living or dead.” 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1052(a). Tam contested the denial of registration through
    the administrative appeals process, to no avail. He then took the
    case to federal court, where the en banc Federal Circuit ultimately
    found the disparagement clause facially unconstitutional under the
    First Amendment’s Free Speech Clause.
    Held: The judgment is affirmed.
    
    808 F.3d 1321
    , affirmed.
    JUSTICE ALITO delivered the opinion of the Court with respect to
    Parts I, II, and III–A, concluding:
    1. The disparagement clause applies to marks that disparage the
    members of a racial or ethnic group. Tam’s view, that the clause ap-
    plies only to natural or juristic persons, is refuted by the plain terms
    of the clause, which uses the word “persons.” A mark that disparages
    a “substantial” percentage of the members of a racial or ethnic group
    necessarily disparages many “persons,” namely, members of that
    group. Tam’s narrow reading also clashes with the breadth of the
    disparagement clause, which by its terms applies not just to “per-
    sons,” but also to “institutions” and “beliefs.” §1052(a). Had Con-
    gress wanted to confine the reach of the clause, it could have used the
    2                            MATAL v. TAM
    Syllabus
    phrase “particular living individual,” which it used in neighboring
    §1052(c). Tam contends that his interpretation is supported by legis-
    lative history and by the PTO’s practice for many years of registering
    marks that plainly denigrated certain groups. But an inquiry into
    the meaning of the statute’s text ceases when, as here, “the statutory
    language is unambiguous and the statutory scheme is coherent and
    consistent.” Barnhart v. Sigmon Coal Co., 
    534 U.S. 438
    , 450 (inter-
    nal quotation marks omitted). Even if resort to legislative history
    and early enforcement practice were appropriate, Tam has presented
    nothing showing a congressional intent to adopt his interpretation,
    and the PTO’s practice in the years following the disparagement
    clause’s enactment is unenlightening. Pp. 8–12.
    2. The disparagement clause violates the First Amendment’s Free
    Speech Clause. Contrary to the Government’s contention, trade-
    marks are private, not government speech. Because the “Free Speech
    Clause . . . does not regulate government speech,” Pleasant Grove
    City v. Summum, 
    555 U.S. 460
    , 467, the government is not required
    to maintain viewpoint neutrality on its own speech. This Court exer-
    cises great caution in extending its government-speech precedents,
    for if private speech could be passed off as government speech by
    simply affixing a government seal of approval, government could si-
    lence or muffle the expression of disfavored viewpoints.
    The Federal Government does not dream up the trademarks regis-
    tered by the PTO. Except as required by §1052(a), an examiner may
    not reject a mark based on the viewpoint that it appears to express.
    If the mark meets the Lanham Act’s viewpoint-neutral requirements,
    registration is mandatory. And once a mark is registered, the PTO is
    not authorized to remove it from the register unless a party moves for
    cancellation, the registration expires, or the Federal Trade Commis-
    sion initiates proceedings based on certain grounds. It is thus far-
    fetched to suggest that the content of a registered mark is govern-
    ment speech, especially given the fact that if trademarks become gov-
    ernment speech when they are registered, the Federal Government is
    babbling prodigiously and incoherently. And none of this Court’s
    government-speech cases supports the idea that registered trade-
    marks are government speech. Johanns v. Livestock Marketing
    Assn., 
    544 U.S. 550
    ; Pleasant Grove City v. Summum, 
    555 U.S. 460
    ;
    and Walker v. Texas Div., Sons of Confederate Veterans, Inc., 576
    U. S. ___, distinguished. Holding that the registration of a trade-
    mark converts the mark into government speech would constitute a
    huge and dangerous extension of the government-speech doctrine, for
    other systems of government registration (such as copyright) could
    easily be characterized in the same way. Pp. 12–18.
    JUSTICE ALITO, joined by THE CHIEF JUSTICE, JUSTICE THOMAS, and
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)                     3
    Syllabus
    JUSTICE BREYER, concluded in Parts III–B, III–C, and IV:
    (a) The Government’s argument that this case is governed by the
    Court’s subsidized-speech cases is unpersuasive. Those cases all in-
    volved cash subsidies or their equivalent, e.g., funds to private par-
    ties for family planning services in Rust v. Sullivan, 
    500 U.S. 173
    ,
    and cash grants to artists in National Endowment for Arts v. Finley,
    
    524 U.S. 569
    . The federal registration of a trademark is nothing like
    these programs. The PTO does not pay money to parties seeking reg-
    istration of a mark; it requires the payment of fees to file an applica-
    tion and to maintain the registration once it is granted. The Gov-
    ernment responds that registration provides valuable non-monetary
    benefits traceable to the Government’s resources devoted to register-
    ing the marks, but nearly every government service requires the ex-
    penditure of government funds. This is true of services that benefit
    everyone, like police and fire protection, as well as services that are
    utilized by only some, e.g., the adjudication of private lawsuits and
    the use of public parks and highways. Pp. 18–20.
    (b) Also unpersuasive is the Government’s claim that the dispar-
    agement clause is constitutional under a “government-program” doc-
    trine, an argument which is based on a merger of this Court’s gov-
    ernment-speech cases and subsidy cases. It points to two cases
    involving a public employer’s collection of union dues from its em-
    ployees, Davenport v. Washington Ed. Assn., 
    551 U.S. 177
    , and Ys-
    ursa v. Pocatello Ed. Assn., 
    555 U.S. 353
    , but these cases occupy a
    special area of First Amendment case law that is far removed from
    the registration of trademarks. Cases in which government creates a
    limited public forum for private speech, thus allowing for some con-
    tent- and speaker-based restrictions, see, e.g., Good News Club v.
    Milford Central School, 
    533 U.S. 98
    , 106–107; Rosenberger v. Rector
    and Visitors of Univ. of Va., 
    515 U.S. 819
    , 831, are potentially more
    analogous. But even in those cases, viewpoint discrimination is for-
    bidden. The disparagement clause denies registration to any mark
    that is offensive to a substantial percentage of the members of any
    group. That is viewpoint discrimination in the sense relevant here:
    Giving offense is a viewpoint. The “public expression of ideas may
    not be prohibited merely because the ideas are themselves offensive
    to some of their hearers.” Street v. New York, 
    394 U.S. 576
    , 592.
    Pp. 20–23.
    (c) The dispute between the parties over whether trademarks are
    commercial speech subject to the relaxed scrutiny outlined in Central
    Hudson Gas & Elect. v. Public Serv. Comm’n of N. Y., 
    447 U.S. 557
    ,
    need not be resolved here because the disparagement clause cannot
    withstand even Central Hudson review. Under Central Hudson, a
    restriction of speech must serve “a substantial interest” and be “nar-
    4                             MATAL v. TAM
    Syllabus
    rowly drawn.” 
    Id., at 564–565
    (internal quotation marks omitted).
    One purported interest is in preventing speech expressing ideas that
    offend, but that idea strikes at the heart of the First Amendment.
    The second interest asserted is protecting the orderly flow of com-
    merce from disruption caused by trademarks that support invidious
    discrimination; but the clause, which reaches any trademark that
    disparages any person, group, or institution, is not narrowly drawn.
    Pp. 23–26.
    JUSTICE KENNEDY, joined by JUSTICE GINSBURG, JUSTICE SO-
    TOMAYOR, and JUSTICE KAGAN, agreed that 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1052(a) con-
    stitutes viewpoint discrimination, concluding:
    (a) With few narrow exceptions, a fundamental principle of the
    First Amendment is that the government may not punish or suppress
    speech based on disapproval of the ideas or perspectives the speech
    conveys. See Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va., 
    515 U.S. 819
    , 828–829. The test for viewpoint discrimination is wheth-
    er—within the relevant subject category—the government has sin-
    gled out a subset of messages for disfavor based on the views ex-
    pressed. Here, the disparagement clause identifies the relevant
    subject as “persons, living or dead, institutions, beliefs, or national
    symbols,” §1052(a); and within that category, an applicant may regis-
    ter a positive or benign mark but not a derogatory one. The law thus
    reflects the Government’s disapproval of a subset of messages it finds
    offensive, the essence of viewpoint discrimination. The Government’s
    arguments in defense of the statute are unpersuasive. Pp. 2–5.
    (b) Regardless of whether trademarks are commercial speech, the
    viewpoint based discrimination here necessarily invokes heightened
    scrutiny. See Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc., 
    564 U.S. 552
    , 566. To the
    extent trademarks qualify as commercial speech, they are an exam-
    ple of why that category does not serve as a blanket exemption from
    the First Amendment’s requirement of viewpoint neutrality. In the
    realm of trademarks, the metaphorical marketplace of ideas becomes
    a tangible, powerful reality. To permit viewpoint discrimination in
    this context is to permit Government censorship. Pp. 5–7.
    ALITO, J., announced the judgment of the Court and delivered the
    opinion of the Court with respect to Parts I, II, and III–A, in which
    ROBERTS, C. J., and KENNEDY, GINSBURG, BREYER, SOTOMAYOR, and
    KAGAN, JJ., joined, and in which THOMAS, J., joined except for Part II,
    and an opinion with respect to Parts III–B, III–C, and IV, in which
    ROBERTS, C. J., and THOMAS and BREYER, JJ., joined. KENNEDY, J., filed
    an opinion concurring in part and concurring in the judgment, in which
    GINSBURG, SOTOMAYOR, and KAGAN, JJ., joined. THOMAS, J., filed an
    opinion concurring in part and concurring in the judgment. GORSUCH,
    J., took no part in the consideration or decision of the case.
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)                              1
    Opinion of the Court
    NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal revision before publication in the
    preliminary print of the United States Reports. Readers are requested to
    notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Wash-
    ington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in order
    that corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to press.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 15–1293
    _________________
    JOSEPH MATAL, INTERIM DIRECTOR, UNITED
    STATES PATENT AND TRADEMARK OFFICE,
    PETITIONER v. SIMON SHIAO TAM
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE FEDERAL CIRCUIT
    [June 19, 2017]
    JUSTICE ALITO announced the judgment of the Court
    and delivered the opinion of the Court with respect to
    Parts I, II, and III–A, and an opinion with respect to Parts
    III–B, III–C, and IV, in which THE CHIEF JUSTICE,
    JUSTICE THOMAS, and JUSTICE BREYER join.
    This case concerns a dance-rock band’s application for
    federal trademark registration of the band’s name, “The
    Slants.” “Slants” is a derogatory term for persons of Asian
    descent, and members of the band are Asian-Americans.
    But the band members believe that by taking that slur as
    the name of their group, they will help to “reclaim” the
    term and drain its denigrating force.
    The Patent and Trademark Office (PTO) denied the
    application based on a provision of federal law prohibiting
    the registration of trademarks that may “disparage . . . or
    bring . . . into contemp[t] or disrepute” any “persons, living
    or dead.” 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1052(a). We now hold that this
    provision violates the Free Speech Clause of the First
    Amendment. It offends a bedrock First Amendment prin-
    ciple: Speech may not be banned on the ground that it
    2                        MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion of the Court
    expresses ideas that offend.
    I
    A
    “The principle underlying trademark protection is that
    distinctive marks—words, names, symbols, and the like—
    can help distinguish a particular artisan’s goods from
    those of others.” B&B Hardware, Inc. v. Hargis Indus-
    tries, Inc., 575 U. S. ___, ___ (2015) (slip op., at 3); see also
    Wal-Mart Stores, Inc. v. Samara Brothers, Inc., 
    529 U.S. 205
    , 212 (2000). A trademark “designate[s] the goods as
    the product of a particular trader” and “protect[s] his good
    will against the sale of another’s product as his.” United
    Drug Co. v. Theodore Rectanus Co., 
    248 U.S. 90
    , 97
    (1918); see also Hanover Star Milling Co. v. Metcalf, 
    240 U.S. 403
    , 412–413 (1916). It helps consumers identify
    goods and services that they wish to purchase, as well as
    those they want to avoid. See Wal-Mart 
    Stores, supra, at 212
    –213; Park ’N Fly, Inc. v. Dollar Park & Fly, Inc., 
    469 U.S. 189
    , 198 (1985).
    “[F]ederal law does not create trademarks.”              B&B
    
    Hardware, supra
    , at ___ (slip op., at 3). Trademarks and
    their precursors have ancient origins, and trademarks
    were protected at common law and in equity at the time of
    the founding of our country. 3 J. McCarthy, Trademarks
    and Unfair Competition §19:8 (4th ed. 2017) (hereinafter
    McCarthy); 1 
    id., §§5:1, 5:2,
    5:3; Pattishal, The Constitu-
    tional Foundations of American Trademark Law, 78
    Trademark Rep. 456, 457–458 (1988); Pattishall, Two
    Hundred Years of American Trademark Law, 68 Trade-
    mark Rep. 121, 121–123 (1978); see Trade-Mark Cases,
    
    100 U.S. 82
    , 92 (1879). For most of the 19th century,
    trademark protection was the province of the States. See
    Two Pesos, Inc. v. Taco Cabana, Inc., 
    505 U.S. 763
    , 780–
    782 (1992) (Stevens, J., concurring in judgment); 
    id., at 785
    (THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment). Eventually,
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)            3
    Opinion of the Court
    Congress stepped in to provide a degree of national uni-
    formity, passing the first federal legislation protecting
    trademarks in 1870. See Act of July 8, 1870, §§77–84, 16
    Stat. 210–212. The foundation of current federal trade-
    mark law is the Lanham Act, enacted in 1946. See Act of
    July 5, 1946, ch. 540, 60 Stat. 427. By that time, trade-
    mark had expanded far beyond phrases that do no more
    than identify a good or service. Then, as now, trademarks
    often consisted of catchy phrases that convey a message.
    Under the Lanham Act, trademarks that are “used in
    commerce” may be placed on the “principal register,” that
    is, they may be federally registered.            
    15 U.S. C
    .
    §1051(a)(1). And some marks “capable of distinguishing
    [an] applicant’s goods or services and not registrable on
    the principal register . . . which are in lawful use in com-
    merce by the owner thereof ” may instead be placed on a
    different federal register: the supplemental register.
    §1091(a). There are now more than two million marks
    that have active federal certificates of registration. PTO
    Performance and Accountability Report, Fiscal Year 2016,
    p. 192 (Table 15), https://www.uspto.gov/sites/default/files/
    documents/USPTOFY16PAR.pdf (all Internet materials as
    last visited June 16, 2017). This system of federal regis-
    tration helps to ensure that trademarks are fully protected
    and supports the free flow of commerce. “[N]ational pro-
    tection of trademarks is desirable,” we have explained,
    “because trademarks foster competition and the mainte-
    nance of quality by securing to the producer the benefits of
    good reputation.” San Francisco Arts & Athletics, Inc. v.
    United States Olympic Comm., 
    483 U.S. 522
    , 531 (1987)
    (internal quotation marks omitted); see also Park ’N Fly,
    
    Inc., supra, at 198
    (“The Lanham Act provides national
    protection of trademarks in order to secure to the owner of
    the mark the goodwill of his business and to protect the
    ability of consumers to distinguish among competing
    producers”).
    4                           MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion of the Court
    B
    Without federal registration, a valid trademark may
    still be used in commerce. See 3 McCarthy §19:8. And an
    unregistered trademark can be enforced against would-be
    infringers in several ways. Most important, even if a
    trademark is not federally registered, it may still be en-
    forceable under §43(a) of the Lanham Act, which creates a
    federal cause of action for trademark infringement. See
    Two 
    Pesos, supra, at 768
    (“Section 43(a) prohibits a broader
    range of practices than does §32, which applies to regis-
    tered marks, but it is common ground that §43(a) protects
    qualifying unregistered trademarks” (internal quotation
    marks and citation omitted)).1 Unregistered trademarks
    may also be entitled to protection under other federal
    statutes, such as the Anticybersquatting Consumer Pro-
    tection Act, 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1125(d).       See 5 McCarthy
    §25A:49, at 25A–198 (“[T]here is no requirement [in the
    Anticybersquatting Act] that the protected ‘mark’ be regis-
    tered: unregistered common law marks are protected by
    the Act”). And an unregistered trademark can be enforced
    under state common law, or if it has been registered in a
    State, under that State’s registration system. See 3 
    id., §19:3, at
    19–23 (explaining that “[t]he federal system of
    registration and protection does not preempt parallel state
    ——————
    1 In the opinion below, the Federal Circuit opined that although “Sec-
    tion 43(a) allows for a federal suit to protect an unregistered trade-
    mark,” “it is not at all clear” that respondent could bring suit under
    §43(a) because “there is no authority extending §43(a) to marks denied
    under §2(a)’s disparagement provision.” In re Tam, 
    808 F.3d 1321
    ,
    1344–1345, n.11 (en banc), as corrected (Feb. 11, 2016). When drawing
    this conclusion, the Federal Circuit relied in part on our statement in
    Two Pesos that “the general principles qualifying a mark for registra-
    tion under §2 of the Lanham Act are for the most part applicable in
    determining whether an unregistered mark is entitled to protection
    under 
    §43(a).” 505 U.S., at 768
    . We need not decide today whether
    respondent could bring suit under §43(a) if his application for federal
    registration had been lawfully denied under the disparagement clause.
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)              5
    Opinion of the Court
    law protection, either by state common law or state regis-
    tration” and “[i]n the vast majority of situations, federal
    and state trademark law peacefully coexist”); 
    id., §22:1 (discussing
    state trademark registration systems).
    Federal registration, however, “confers important legal
    rights and benefits on trademark owners who register
    their marks.” B&B Hardware, 575 U. S., at ___ (slip op.,
    at 3) (internal quotation marks omitted). Registration on
    the principal register (1) “serves as ‘constructive notice of
    the registrant’s claim of ownership’ of the mark,” ibid.
    (quoting 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1072); (2) “is ‘prima facie evidence of
    the validity of the registered mark and of the registration
    of the mark, of the owner’s ownership of the mark, and of
    the owner’s exclusive right to use the registered mark in
    commerce on or in connection with the goods or services
    specified in the certificate,’ ” B & B Hardware, 575 U. S.
    ___ (slip op., at 3) (quoting §1057(b)); and (3) can make a
    mark “ ‘incontestable’ ” once a mark has been registered for
    five years,” 
    ibid. (quoting §§1065, 1115(b));
    see Park ’N
    
    Fly, 469 U.S., at 193
    . Registration also enables the
    trademark holder “to stop the importation into the United
    States of articles bearing an infringing mark.” 3 Mc-
    Carthy §19:9, at 19–38; see 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1124.
    C
    The Lanham Act contains provisions that bar certain
    trademarks from the principal register. For example, a
    trademark cannot be registered if it is “merely descriptive or
    deceptively misdescriptive” of goods, §1052(e)(1), or if it is so
    similar to an already registered trademark or trade name
    that it is “likely . . . to cause confusion, or to cause mistake,
    or to deceive,” §1052(d).
    At issue in this case is one such provision, which we will
    call “the disparagement clause.” This provision prohibits the
    registration of a trademark “which may disparage . . . per-
    sons, living or dead, institutions, beliefs, or national symbols,
    6                        MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion of the Court
    or bring them into contempt, or disrepute.” §1052(a).2 This
    clause appeared in the original Lanham Act and has re-
    mained the same to this day. See §2(a), 60 Stat. 428.
    When deciding whether a trademark is disparaging, an
    examiner at the PTO generally applies a “two-part test.”
    The examiner first considers “the likely meaning of the
    matter in question, taking into account not only dictionary
    definitions, but also the relationship of the matter to the
    other elements in the mark, the nature of the goods or
    services, and the manner in which the mark is used in the
    marketplace in connection with the goods or services.”
    Trademark Manual of Examining Procedure §1203.03(b)(i)
    (Apr. 2017), p. 1200–150, http://tmep.uspto.gov. “If that
    meaning is found to refer to identifiable persons, institu-
    tions, beliefs or national symbols,” the examiner moves to
    the second step, asking “whether that meaning may be
    disparaging to a substantial composite3 of the referenced
    group.” 
    Ibid. If the examiner
    finds that a “substantial
    composite, although not necessarily a majority, of the
    referenced group would find the proposed mark . . . to be
    disparaging in the context of contemporary attitudes,” a
    prima facie case of disparagement is made out, and the
    burden shifts to the applicant to prove that the trademark
    is not disparaging. 
    Ibid. What is more,
    the PTO has
    specified that “[t]he fact that an applicant may be a mem-
    ber of that group or has good intentions underlying its use
    of a term does not obviate the fact that a substantial
    composite of the referenced group would find the term
    objectionable.” 
    Ibid. D Simon Tam
    is the lead singer of “The Slants.” In re
    Tam, 
    808 F.3d 1321
    , 1331 (CA Fed. 2015) (en banc), as
    ——————
    2 The disparagement clause also prevents a trademark from being
    registered on the supplemental register. §1091(a).
    3 By “composite,” we assume the PTO means component.
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)            7
    Opinion of the Court
    corrected (Feb. 11, 2016). He chose this moniker in order
    to “reclaim” and “take ownership” of stereotypes about
    people of Asian ethnicity. 
    Ibid. (internal quotation marks
    omitted). The group “draws inspiration for its lyrics from
    childhood slurs and mocking nursery rhymes” and has
    given its albums names such as “The Yellow Album” and
    “Slanted Eyes, Slanted Hearts.” 
    Ibid. Tam sought federal
    registration of “THE SLANTS,” on
    the principal register, App. 17, but an examining attorney
    at the PTO rejected the request, applying the PTO’s two-
    part framework and finding that “there is . . . a substan-
    tial composite of persons who find the term in the applied-
    for mark offensive.” 
    Id., at 30.
    The examining attorney
    relied in part on the fact that “numerous dictionaries
    define ‘slants’ or ‘slant-eyes’ as a derogatory or offensive
    term.” 
    Id., at 29.
    The examining attorney also relied on a
    finding that “the band’s name has been found offensive
    numerous times”—citing a performance that was canceled
    because of the band’s moniker and the fact that “several
    bloggers and commenters to articles on the band have
    indicated that they find the term and the applied-for mark
    offensive.” 
    Id., at 29–30.
       Tam contested the denial of registration before the
    examining attorney and before the PTO’s Trademark Trial
    and Appeal Board (TTAB) but to no avail. Eventually, he
    took the case to federal court, where the en banc Federal
    Circuit ultimately found the disparagement clause facially
    unconstitutional under the First Amendment’s Free
    Speech Clause. The majority found that the clause en-
    gages in viewpoint-based discrimination, that the clause
    regulates the expressive component of trademarks and
    consequently cannot be treated as commercial speech, and
    that the clause is subject to and cannot satisfy strict scru-
    tiny. 
    See 808 F.3d, at 1334
    –1339. The majority also
    rejected the Government’s argument that registered
    trademarks constitute government speech, as well as the
    8                      MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion of the Court
    Government’s contention that federal registration is a
    form of government subsidy. See 
    id., at 1339–1355.
    And
    the majority opined that even if the disparagement clause
    were analyzed under this Court’s commercial speech
    cases, the clause would fail the “intermediate scrutiny”
    that those cases prescribe. See 
    id., at 1355–1357.
       Several judges wrote separately, advancing an assort-
    ment of theories. Concurring, Judge O’Malley agreed with
    the majority’s reasoning but added that the disparage-
    ment clause is unconstitutionally vague. See 
    id., at 1358–
    1363. Judge Dyk concurred in part and dissented in part.
    He argued that trademark registration is a government
    subsidy and that the disparagement clause is facially
    constitutional, but he found the clause unconstitutional as
    applied to THE SLANTS because that mark constitutes
    “core expression” and was not adopted for the purpose of
    disparaging Asian-Americans. See 
    id., at 1363–1374.
    In
    dissent, Judge Lourie agreed with Judge Dyk that the
    clause is facially constitutional but concluded for a variety
    of reasons that it is also constitutional as applied in this
    case. See 
    id., at 1374–1376.
    Judge Reyna also dissented,
    maintaining that trademarks are commercial speech and
    that the disparagement clause survives intermediate
    scrutiny because it “directly advances the government’s
    substantial interest in the orderly flow of commerce.” See
    
    id., at 1376–1382.
       The Government filed a petition for certiorari, which we
    granted in order to decide whether the disparagement
    clause “is facially invalid under the Free Speech Clause of
    the First Amendment.” Pet. for Cert. i; see sub. nom. Lee
    v. Tam, 579 U. S. ___ (2016).
    II
    Before reaching the question whether the disparage-
    ment clause violates the First Amendment, we consider
    Tam’s argument that the clause does not reach marks that
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)            9
    Opinion of the Court
    disparage racial or ethnic groups. The clause prohibits the
    registration of marks that disparage “persons,” and Tam
    claims that the term “persons” “includes only natural and
    juristic persons,” not “non-juristic entities such as racial
    and ethnic groups.” Brief for Respondent 46.
    Tam never raised this argument before the PTO or the
    Federal Circuit, and we declined to grant certiorari on this
    question when Tam asked us to do so, see Brief Respond-
    ing to Petition for Certiorari, pp. i, 17–21. Normally, that
    would be the end of the matter in this Court. See, e.g., Yee
    v. Escondido, 
    503 U.S. 519
    , 534–538 (1992); Freytag v.
    Commissioner, 
    501 U.S. 868
    , 894–895 (1991) (Scalia, J.,
    concurring in part and concurring in judgment).
    But as the Government pointed out in connection with
    its petition for certiorari, accepting Tam’s statutory inter-
    pretation would resolve this case and leave the First
    Amendment question for another day. See Reply Brief 9.
    “[W]e have often stressed” that it is “importan[t] [to]
    avoid[d] the premature adjudication of constitutional
    questions,” Clinton v. Jones, 
    520 U.S. 681
    , 690 (1997), and
    that “we ought not to pass on questions of constitutionality
    . . . unless such adjudication is unavoidable,” Spector
    Motor Service, Inc. v. McLaughlin, 
    323 U.S. 101
    , 105
    (1944). See also Alabama State Federation of Labor v.
    McAdory, 
    325 U.S. 450
    , 461 (1945); Burton v. United
    States, 
    196 U.S. 283
    , 295 (1905). We thus begin by ex-
    plaining why Tam’s argument about the definition of
    “persons” in the Lanham Act is meritless.
    As noted, the disparagement clause prohibits the regis-
    tration of trademarks “which may disparage . . . persons,
    living or dead.” 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1052(a). Tam points to a
    definition of “person” in the Lanham Act, which provides
    that “[i]n the construction of this chapter, unless the
    contrary is plainly apparent from the context . . . [t]he
    term ‘person’ and any other word or term used to desig-
    nate the applicant or other entitled to a benefit or privi-
    10                          MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion of the Court
    lege or rendered liable under the provisions of this chapter
    includes a juristic person as well as a natural person.”
    §1127. Because racial and ethnic groups are neither
    natural nor “juristic” persons, Tam asserts, these groups
    fall outside this definition. Brief for Respondent 46–48.
    Tam’s argument is refuted by the plain terms of the
    disparagement clause. The clause applies to marks that
    disparage “persons.” A mark that disparages a “substan-
    tial” percentage of the members of a racial or ethnic group,
    Trademark Manual §1203.03(b)(i), at 1200–150, necessar-
    ily disparages many “persons,” namely, members of that
    group. Tam’s argument would fail even if the clause used
    the singular term “person,” but Congress’ use of the plural
    “persons” makes the point doubly clear.4
    Tam’s narrow reading of the term “persons” also clashes
    with the breadth of the disparagement clause. By its
    terms, the clause applies to marks that disparage, not just
    “persons,” but also “institutions” and “beliefs.” 
    15 U.S. C
    .
    §1052(a). It thus applies to the members of any group
    whose members share particular “beliefs,” such as politi-
    cal, ideological, and religious groups. It applies to marks
    that denigrate “institutions,” and on Tam’s reading, it also
    reaches “juristic” persons such as corporations, unions,
    and other unincorporated associations. See §1127. Thus,
    the clause is not limited to marks that disparage a partic-
    ular natural person. If Congress had wanted to confine
    ——————
    4 Tam  advances a convoluted textual argument that goes as follows.
    The definition of a “person” in 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1127 does not include a
    “non-juristic person,” i.e., a group that cannot sue or be sued in its own
    right. Brief for Respondent 46–47. Such groups consist of multiple
    natural persons. Therefore, the members of such groups are not
    “persons” under the disparagement clause. 
    Id., at 46–48.
       This argument leads to the absurd result that no person is a “person”
    within the meaning of the disparagement clause. This is so because
    every person is a member of a “non-juristic” group, e.g., right-handers,
    left-handers, women, men, people born on odd-numbered days, people
    born on even-numbered days.
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)                    11
    Opinion of the Court
    the reach of the disparagement clause in the way that
    Tam suggests, it would have been easy to do so. A neigh-
    boring provision of the Lanham Act denies registration to
    any trademark that “[c]onsists of or comprises a name,
    portrait, or signature identifying a particular living indi-
    vidual except by his written consent.” §1052(c) (emphasis
    added).
    Tam contends that his interpretation of the disparage-
    ment clause is supported by its legislative history and by
    the PTO’s willingness for many years to register marks
    that plainly denigrated African-Americans and Native
    Americans. These arguments are unpersuasive. As al-
    ways, our inquiry into the meaning of the statute’s text
    ceases when “the statutory language is unambiguous and
    the statutory scheme is coherent and consistent.” Barn-
    hart v. Sigmon Coal Co., 
    534 U.S. 438
    , 450 (2002) (inter-
    nal quotation marks omitted). Here, it is clear that the
    prohibition against registering trademarks “which may
    disparage . . . persons,” §1052(a), prohibits registration of
    terms that disparage persons who share a common race or
    ethnicity.
    Even if resort to legislative history and early enforce-
    ment practice were appropriate, we would find Tam’s
    arguments unconvincing. Tam has not brought to our
    attention any evidence in the legislative history showing
    that Congress meant to adopt his interpretation. And the
    practice of the PTO in the years following the enactment
    of the disparagement clause is unenlightening. The ad-
    mitted vagueness of the disparagement test5 and the huge
    ——————
    5 The PTO has acknowledged that the guidelines “for determining
    whether a mark is scandalous or disparaging are somewhat vague and
    the determination of whether a mark is scandalous or disparaging is
    necessarily a highly subjective one.” In re In Over Our Heads, Inc., 
    16 U.S.P.Q. 2d (BNA) 1653
    , 1654 (TTAB 1990) (brackets and internal quotation
    marks omitted). The PTO has similarly observed that whether a mark
    is disparaging “is highly subjective and, thus, general rules are difficult
    12                         MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion of the Court
    volume of applications have produced a haphazard record
    of enforcement. (Even today, the principal register is
    replete with marks that many would regard as disparag-
    ing to racial and ethnic groups.6) Registration of the
    offensive marks that Tam cites is likely attributable not to
    the acceptance of his interpretation of the clause but to
    other factors—most likely the regrettable attitudes and
    sensibilities of the time in question.
    III
    Because the disparagement clause applies to marks that
    disparage the members of a racial or ethnic group, we
    must decide whether the clause violates the Free Speech
    Clause of the First Amendment. And at the outset, we
    must consider three arguments that would either elimi-
    nate any First Amendment protection or result in highly
    permissive rational-basis review. Specifically, the Gov-
    ernment contends (1) that trademarks are government
    speech, not private speech, (2) that trademarks are a form
    of government subsidy, and (3) that the constitutionality
    of the disparagement clause should be tested under a new
    “government-program” doctrine. We address each of these
    arguments below.
    A
    The First Amendment prohibits Congress and other
    government entities and actors from “abridging the free-
    dom of speech”; the First Amendment does not say that
    Congress and other government entities must abridge
    their own ability to speak freely. And our cases recognize
    that “[t]he Free Speech Clause . . . does not regulate gov-
    ernment speech.” Pleasant Grove City v. Summum, 555
    ——————
    to postulate.” Harjo v. Pro-Football Inc., 
    50 U.S.P.Q. 2d (BNA) 1705
    , 1737 (TTAB
    1999), rev’d, 
    284 F. Supp. 2d 96
    (DC 2003), rev’d and remanded in part,
    
    415 F.3d 44
    (CADC 2005) (per curiam).
    6 See, e.g., App. to Brief for Pro-Football, Inc., as Amicus Curiae.
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)              13
    Opinion of the Court
    U. S. 460, 467 (2009); see Johanns v. Livestock Marketing
    Assn., 
    544 U.S. 550
    , 553 (2005) (“[T]he Government’s own
    speech . . . is exempt from First Amendment scrutiny”);
    Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth,
    
    529 U.S. 217
    , 235 (2000).
    As we have said, “it is not easy to imagine how govern-
    ment could function” if it were subject to the restrictions
    that the First Amendment imposes on private speech.
    
    Summum, supra, at 468
    ; see Walker v. Texas Div., Sons of
    Confederate Veterans, Inc., 576 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2015)
    (slip op., at 5–7). “ ‘[T]he First Amendment forbids the
    government to regulate speech in ways that favor some
    viewpoints or ideas at the expense of others,’ ” Lamb’s
    Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free School Dist., 
    508 U.S. 384
    , 394 (1993), but imposing a requirement of
    viewpoint-neutrality on government speech would be para-
    lyzing. When a government entity embarks on a course
    of action, it necessarily takes a particular viewpoint
    and rejects others. The Free Speech Clause does not re-
    quire government to maintain viewpoint neutrality when
    its officers and employees speak about that venture.
    Here is a simple example. During the Second World
    War, the Federal Government produced and distributed
    millions of posters to promote the war effort.7 There were
    posters urging enlistment, the purchase of war bonds, and
    the conservation of scarce resources.8 These posters ex-
    pressed a viewpoint, but the First Amendment did not
    demand that the Government balance the message of
    these posters by producing and distributing posters en-
    couraging Americans to refrain from engaging in these
    activities.
    But while the government-speech doctrine is im-
    portant—indeed, essential—it is a doctrine that is suscep-
    ——————
    7 See,    e.g., D. Nelson, The Posters That Won the War (1991).
    8 
    Ibid. 14 MATAL v.
    TAM
    Opinion of the Court
    tible to dangerous misuse. If private speech could be
    passed off as government speech by simply affixing a
    government seal of approval, government could silence or
    muffle the expression of disfavored viewpoints. For this
    reason, we must exercise great caution before extending
    our government-speech precedents.
    At issue here is the content of trademarks that are
    registered by the PTO, an arm of the Federal Government.
    The Federal Government does not dream up these marks,
    and it does not edit marks submitted for registration.
    Except as required by the statute involved here, 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1052(a), an examiner may not reject a mark
    based on the viewpoint that it appears to express. Thus,
    unless that section is thought to apply, an examiner does
    not inquire whether any viewpoint conveyed by a mark is
    consistent with Government policy or whether any such
    viewpoint is consistent with that expressed by other
    marks already on the principal register. Instead, if the
    mark meets the Lanham Act’s viewpoint-neutral require-
    ments, registration is mandatory. 
    Ibid. (requiring that “[n]o
    trademark . . . shall be refused registration on the
    principal register on account of its nature unless” it falls
    within an enumerated statutory exception). And if an
    examiner finds that a mark is eligible for placement on the
    principal register, that decision is not reviewed by any
    higher official unless the registration is challenged. See
    §§1062(a), 1071; 37 CFR §41.31(a) (2016). Moreover, once
    a mark is registered, the PTO is not authorized to remove
    it from the register unless a party moves for cancellation,
    the registration expires, or the Federal Trade Commission
    initiates proceedings based on certain grounds. See 
    15 U.S. C
    . §§1058(a), 1059, 1064; 37 CFR §§2.111(b), 2.160.
    In light of all this, it is far-fetched to suggest that the
    content of a registered mark is government speech. If the
    federal registration of a trademark makes the mark gov-
    ernment speech, the Federal Government is babbling
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)                  15
    Opinion of the Court
    prodigiously and incoherently. It is saying many unseemly
    things. See App. to Brief for Pro-Football, Inc., as Amicus
    Curiae. It is expressing contradictory views.9 It is una-
    shamedly endorsing a vast array of commercial products
    and services. And it is providing Delphic advice to the
    consuming public.
    For example, if trademarks represent government
    speech, what does the Government have in mind when it
    advises Americans to “make.believe” (Sony),10 “Think
    different” (Apple),11 “Just do it” (Nike),12 or “Have it your
    way” (Burger King)13? Was the Government warning
    about a coming disaster when it registered the mark
    “EndTime Ministries”14?
    The PTO has made it clear that registration does not
    constitute approval of a mark. See In re Old Glory Con-
    dom Corp., 
    26 U.S.P.Q. 2d (BNA) 1216
    , 1220, n. 3 (TTAB 1993)
    (“[I]ssuance of a trademark registration . . . is not a gov-
    ernment imprimatur”). And it is unlikely that more than
    a tiny fraction of the public has any idea what federal
    registration of a trademark means. See Application of
    National Distillers & Chemical Corp., 
    49 Cow. C
    . P. A. (Pat.)
    854, 863, 
    297 F.2d 941
    , 949 (1962) (Rich, J., concurring)
    (“The purchasing public knows no more about trademark
    registrations than a man walking down the street in a
    ——————
    9 Compare “Abolish Abortion,” Registration No. 4,935,774 (Apr. 12,
    2016), with “I Stand With Planned Parenthood,” Registration No.
    5,073,573 (Nov. 1, 2016); compare “Capitalism Is Not Moral, Not Fair,
    Not Freedom,” Registration No. 4,696,419 (Mar. 3, 2015), with “Capital-
    ism Ensuring Innovation,” Registration No. 3,966,092 (May 24, 2011);
    compare “Global Warming Is Good,” Registration No. 4,776,235 (July
    21, 2015), with “A Solution to Global Warming,” Registration No.
    3,875,271 (Nov. 10, 2010).
    10 “make.believe,” Registration No. 4,342,903 (May 28, 2013).
    11 “Think Different,” Registration No. 2,707,257 (Apr. 15, 2003).
    12 “Just Do It,” Registration No. 1,875,307 (Jan. 25, 1995).
    13 “Have It Your Way,” Registration No. 0,961,016. (June 12, 1973)
    14 “EndTime Ministries,” Registration No. 4,746,225 (June 2, 2015).
    16                      MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion of the Court
    strange city knows about legal title to the land and build-
    ings he passes” (emphasis deleted)).
    None of our government speech cases even remotely
    supports the idea that registered trademarks are govern-
    ment speech. In Johanns, we considered advertisements
    promoting the sale of beef products. A federal statute
    called for the creation of a program of paid advertising “ ‘to
    advance the image and desirability of beef and beef prod-
    ucts.’ 
    544 U.S., at 561
    (quoting 
    7 U.S. C
    . § 2902(13)).
    Congress and the Secretary of Agriculture provided guide-
    lines for the content of the ads, Department of Agriculture
    officials attended the meetings at which the content of
    specific ads was discussed, and the Secretary could edit or
    reject any proposed 
    ad. 544 U.S., at 561
    . Noting that
    “[t]he message set out in the beef promotions [was] from
    beginning to end the message established by the Federal
    Government,” we held that the ads were government
    speech. 
    Id., at 560.
    The Government’s involvement in the
    creation of these beef ads bears no resemblance to any-
    thing that occurs when a trademark is registered.
    Our decision in Summum is similarly far afield. A small
    city park contained 15 
    monuments. 555 U.S., at 464
    .
    Eleven had been donated by private groups, and one of
    these displayed the Ten Commandments. 
    Id., at 464–465.
    A religious group claimed that the city, by accepting do-
    nated monuments, had created a limited public forum for
    private speech and was therefore obligated to place in the
    park a monument expressing the group’s religious beliefs.
    Holding that the monuments in the park represented
    government speech, we cited many factors. Governments
    have used monuments to speak to the public since ancient
    times; parks have traditionally been selective in accepting
    and displaying donated monuments; parks would be over-
    run if they were obligated to accept all monuments offered
    by private groups; “[p]ublic parks are often closely identi-
    fied in the public mind with the government unit that
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)          17
    Opinion of the Court
    owns the land”; and “[t]he monuments that are accepted
    . . . are meant to convey and have the effect of conveying a
    government message.” 
    Id., at 472.
        Trademarks share none of these characteristics.
    Trademarks have not traditionally been used to convey a
    Government message. With the exception of the enforce-
    ment of 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1052(a), the viewpoint expressed by a
    mark has not played a role in the decision whether to
    place it on the principal register. And there is no evidence
    that the public associates the contents of trademarks with
    the Federal Government.
    This brings us to the case on which the Government
    relies most heavily, Walker, which likely marks the outer
    bounds of the government-speech doctrine. Holding that
    the messages on Texas specialty license plates are gov-
    ernment speech, the Walker Court cited three factors
    distilled from Summum. 576 U. S., at ___–___ (slip op., at
    7–8). First, license plates have long been used by the
    States to convey state messages. Id., at ___–___ (slip op.,
    at 9–10). Second, license plates “are often closely identi-
    fied in the public mind” with the State, since they are
    manufactured and owned by the State, generally designed
    by the State, and serve as a form of “government ID.” Id.,
    at ___ (slip op., at 10) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    Third, Texas “maintain[ed] direct control over the mes-
    sages conveyed on its specialty plates.” Id., at ___ (slip
    op., at 11). As explained above, none of these factors are
    present in this case.
    In sum, the federal registration of trademarks is vastly
    different from the beef ads in Johanns, the monuments in
    Summum, and even the specialty license plates in Walker.
    Holding that the registration of a trademark converts the
    mark into government speech would constitute a huge and
    dangerous extension of the government-speech doctrine.
    For if the registration of trademarks constituted govern-
    ment speech, other systems of government registration
    18                      MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion
    Opinion of
    of the Court
    ALITO, J.
    could easily be characterized in the same way.
    Perhaps the most worrisome implication of the Govern-
    ment’s argument concerns the system of copyright regis-
    tration. If federal registration makes a trademark gov-
    ernment speech and thus eliminates all First Amendment
    protection, would the registration of the copyright for a
    book produce a similar transformation? 
    See 808 F.3d, at 1346
    (explaining that if trademark registration amounts
    to government speech, “then copyright registration” which
    “has identical accoutrements” would “likewise amount to
    government speech”).
    The Government attempts to distinguish copyright on
    the ground that it is “ ‘the engine of free expression,’ ” Brief
    for Petitioner 47 (quoting Eldred v. Ashcroft, 
    537 U.S. 186
    , 219 (2003)), but as this case illustrates, trademarks
    often have an expressive content. Companies spend huge
    amounts to create and publicize trademarks that convey a
    message. It is true that the necessary brevity of trade-
    marks limits what they can say. But powerful messages
    can sometimes be conveyed in just a few words.
    Trademarks are private, not government, speech.
    B
    We next address the Government’s argument that this
    case is governed by cases in which this Court has upheld
    the constitutionality of government programs that subsi-
    dized speech expressing a particular viewpoint. These
    cases implicate a notoriously tricky question of constitu-
    tional law. “[W]e have held that the Government ‘may not
    deny a benefit to a person on a basis that infringes his
    constitutionally protected . . . freedom of speech even if he
    has no entitlement to that benefit.’ ” Agency for Int’l De-
    velopment v. Alliance for Open Society Int’l, Inc., 570 U. S.
    ___, ___ (2013) (slip op., at 8) (some internal quotation
    marks omitted). But at the same time, government is not
    required to subsidize activities that it does not wish to
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)           19
    Opinion
    Opinion of
    of the Court
    ALITO, J.
    promote. 
    Ibid. Determining which of
    these principles
    applies in a particular case “is not always self-evident,”
    id., at ___ (slip op., at 11), but no difficult question is
    presented here.
    Unlike the present case, the decisions on which the
    Government relies all involved cash subsidies or their
    equivalent. In Rust v. Sullivan, 
    500 U.S. 173
    (1991), a
    federal law provided funds to private parties for family
    planning services. In National Endowment for Arts v.
    Finley, 
    524 U.S. 569
    (1998), cash grants were awarded to
    artists. And federal funding for public libraries was at
    issue in United States v. American Library Assn., Inc., 
    539 U.S. 194
    (2003). In other cases, we have regarded tax
    benefits as comparable to cash subsidies. See Regan v.
    Taxation With Representation of Wash., 
    461 U.S. 540
    (1983); Cammarano v. United States, 358 U. S 498 (1959).
    The federal registration of a trademark is nothing like
    the programs at issue in these cases. The PTO does not
    pay money to parties seeking registration of a mark.
    Quite the contrary is true: An applicant for registration
    must pay the PTO a filing fee of $225–$600. 37 CFR
    §2.6(a)(1). (Tam submitted a fee of $275 as part of his
    application to register THE SLANTS. App. 18.) And to
    maintain federal registration, the holder of a mark must
    pay a fee of $300–$500 every 10 years. §2.6(a)(5); see also
    
    15 U.S. C
    . §1059(a). The Federal Circuit concluded that
    these fees have fully supported the registration system for
    the past 27 
    years. 808 F.3d, at 1353
    .
    The Government responds that registration provides
    valuable non-monetary benefits that “are directly trace-
    able to the resources devoted by the federal government to
    examining, publishing, and issuing certificates of registra-
    tion for those marks.” Brief for Petitioner 27. But just
    about every government service requires the expenditure
    of government funds. This is true of services that benefit
    everyone, like police and fire protection, as well as services
    20                     MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion
    Opinion of
    of the Court
    ALITO, J.
    that are utilized by only some, e.g., the adjudication of
    private lawsuits and the use of public parks and highways.
    Trademark registration is not the only government
    registration scheme. For example, the Federal Govern-
    ment registers copyrights and patents. State governments
    and their subdivisions register the title to real property
    and security interests; they issue driver’s licenses, motor
    vehicle registrations, and hunting, fishing, and boating
    licenses or permits.
    Cases like Rust and Finley are not instructive in analyz-
    ing the constitutionality of restrictions on speech imposed
    in connection with such services.
    C
    Finally, the Government urges us to sustain the dispar-
    agement clause under a new doctrine that would apply to
    “government-program” cases. For the most part, this
    argument simply merges our government-speech cases
    and the previously discussed subsidy cases in an attempt
    to construct a broader doctrine that can be applied to the
    registration of trademarks. The only new element in this
    construct consists of two cases involving a public employ-
    er’s collection of union dues from its employees. But
    those cases occupy a special area of First Amendment case
    law, and they are far removed from the registration of
    trademarks.
    In Davenport v. Washington Ed. Assn., 
    551 U.S. 177
    ,
    181–182 (2007), a Washington law permitted a public
    employer automatically to deduct from the wages of em-
    ployees who chose not to join the union the portion of
    union dues used for activities related to collective bargain-
    ing. But unless these employees affirmatively consented,
    the law did not allow the employer to collect the portion of
    union dues that would be used in election activities. 
    Id., at 180–182.
    A public employee union argued that this law
    unconstitutionally restricted its speech based on its con-
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)           21
    Opinion
    Opinion of
    of the Court
    ALITO, J.
    tent; that is, the law permitted the employer to assist
    union speech on matters relating to collective bargaining
    but made it harder for the union to collect money to sup-
    port its election activities. 
    Id., at 188.
    Upholding this law,
    we characterized it as imposing a “modest limitation” on
    an “extraordinary benefit,” namely, taking money from the
    wages of non-union members and turning it over to the
    union free of charge. 
    Id., at 184.
    Refusing to confer an
    even greater benefit, we held, did not upset the market-
    place of ideas and did not abridge the union’s free speech
    rights. 
    Id., at 189–190.
      Ysursa v. Pocatello Ed. Assn., 
    555 U.S. 353
    (2009), is
    similar. There, we considered an Idaho law that allowed
    public employees to elect to have union dues deducted
    from their wages but did not allow such a deduction for
    money remitted to the union’s political action committee.
    
    Id., at 355.
    We reasoned that the “the government . . .
    [was] not required to assist others in funding the expres-
    sion of particular ideas.” 
    Id., at 358;
    see also 
    id., at 355
    (“The First Amendment . . . does not confer an affirmative
    right to use government payroll mechanisms for the pur-
    pose of obtaining funds for expression”).
    Davenport and Ysursa are akin to our subsidy cases.
    Although the laws at issue in Davenport and Ysursa did
    not provide cash subsidies to the unions, they conferred a
    very valuable benefit—the right to negotiate a collective-
    bargaining agreement under which non-members would
    be obligated to pay an agency fee that the public employer
    would collect and turn over to the union free of charge. As
    in the cash subsidy cases, the laws conferred this benefit
    because it was thought that this arrangement served
    important government interests. See Abood v. Detroit Bd.
    of Ed., 
    431 U.S. 209
    , 224–226 (1977). But the challenged
    laws did not go further and provide convenient collection
    mechanisms for money to be used in political activities. In
    essence, the Washington and Idaho lawmakers chose to
    22                         MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion
    Opinion of
    of the Court
    ALITO, J.
    confer a substantial non-cash benefit for the purpose of
    furthering activities that they particularly desired to
    promote but not to provide a similar benefit for the pur-
    pose of furthering other activities. Thus, Davenport and
    Ysursa are no more relevant for present purposes than the
    subsidy cases previously discussed.15
    Potentially more analogous are cases in which a unit of
    government creates a limited public forum for private
    speech. See, e.g., Good News Club v. Milford Central
    School, 
    533 U.S. 98
    , 106–107 (2001); Rosenberger v. Rec-
    tor and Visitors of Univ. of Va., 
    515 U.S. 819
    , 831 (1995);
    Lamb’s 
    Chapel, 508 U.S., at 392
    –393. See also Legal
    Services Corporation v. Velazquez, 
    531 U.S. 533
    , 541–544
    (2001). When government creates such a forum, in either
    a literal or “metaphysical” sense, see 
    Rosenberger, 515 U.S., at 830
    , some content- and speaker-based restrictions
    may be allowed, see 
    id., at 830–831.
    However, even in
    such cases, what we have termed “viewpoint discrimina-
    tion” is forbidden. 
    Id., at 831.
       Our cases use the term “viewpoint” discrimination in a
    broad sense, see ibid., and in that sense, the disparage-
    ment clause discriminates on the bases of “viewpoint.” To
    be sure, the clause evenhandedly prohibits disparagement
    of all groups. It applies equally to marks that damn Dem-
    ocrats and Republicans, capitalists and socialists, and
    those arrayed on both sides of every possible issue. It
    denies registration to any mark that is offensive to a
    substantial percentage of the members of any group. But
    in the sense relevant here, that is viewpoint discrimina-
    tion: Giving offense is a viewpoint.
    We have said time and again that “the public expression
    ——————
    15 While these cases resemble subsidy cases insofar as the free speech
    rights of unions and their members are concerned, arrangements like
    those in these cases also implicate the free speech rights of non-union
    members. Our decision here has no bearing on that issue.
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)                 23
    Opinion
    Opinion of
    of the Court
    ALITO, J.
    of ideas may not be prohibited merely because the ideas
    are themselves offensive to some of their hearers.” Street
    v. New York, 
    394 U.S. 576
    , 592 (1969). See also Texas v.
    Johnson, 
    491 U.S. 397
    , 414 (1989) (“If there is a bedrock
    principle underlying the First Amendment, it is that the
    government may not prohibit the expression of an idea
    simply because society finds the idea itself offensive or
    disagreeable”); Hustler Magazine, Inc. v. Falwell, 
    485 U.S. 46
    , 55–56 (1988); Coates v. Cincinnati, 
    402 U.S. 611
    , 615
    (1971); Bachellar v. Maryland, 
    397 U.S. 564
    , 567 (1970);
    Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community School
    Dist., 
    393 U.S. 503
    , 509–514 (1969); Cox v. Louisiana, 
    379 U.S. 536
    , 551 (1965); Edwards v. South Carolina, 
    372 U.S. 229
    , 237–238 (1963); Terminiello v. Chicago, 
    337 U.S. 1
    ,
    4–5 (1949); Cantwell v. Connecticut, 
    310 U.S. 296
    , 311
    (1940); Schneider v. State (Town of Irvington), 
    308 U.S. 147
    , 161 (1939); De Jonge v. Oregon, 
    299 U.S. 353
    , 365
    (1937).
    For this reason, the disparagement clause cannot be
    saved by analyzing it as a type of government program in
    which some content- and speaker-based restrictions are
    permitted.16
    IV
    Having concluded that the disparagement clause cannot
    be sustained under our government-speech or subsidy
    cases or under the Government’s proposed “government-
    program” doctrine, we must confront a dispute between
    the parties on the question whether trademarks are com-
    mercial speech and are thus subject to the relaxed scrutiny
    outlined in Central Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Public
    Serv. Comm’n of N. Y., 
    447 U.S. 557
    (1980). The Govern-
    ment and amici supporting its position argue that all
    ——————
    16 We leave open the question whether this is the appropriate frame-
    work for analyzing free speech challenges to provisions of the Lanham
    Act.
    24                          MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion
    Opinion of
    of the Court
    ALITO, J.
    trademarks are commercial speech. They note that the
    central purposes of trademarks are commercial and that
    federal law regulates trademarks to promote fair and
    orderly interstate commerce. Tam and his amici, on the
    other hand, contend that many, if not all, trademarks
    have an expressive component. In other words, these
    trademarks do not simply identify the source of a product
    or service but go on to say something more, either about
    the product or service or some broader issue. The trade-
    mark in this case illustrates this point. The name “The
    Slants” not only identifies the band but expresses a view
    about social issues.
    We need not resolve this debate between the parties
    because the disparagement clause cannot withstand even
    Central Hudson review.17 Under Central Hudson, a re-
    striction of speech must serve “a substantial interest,” and
    it must be “narrowly drawn.” 
    Id., at 564–565
    (internal
    quotation marks omitted). This means, among other
    things, that “[t]he regulatory technique may extend only
    as far as the interest it serves.” 
    Id., at 565.
    The dispar-
    agement clause fails this requirement.
    It is claimed that the disparagement clause serves two
    interests. The first is phrased in a variety of ways in the
    briefs. Echoing language in one of the opinions below, the
    Government asserts an interest in preventing “ ‘un-
    derrepresented groups’ ” from being “ ‘bombarded with
    demeaning messages in commercial advertising.’ ” Brief
    for Petitioner 48 
    (quoting 808 F.3d, at 1364
    (Dyk, J.,
    concurring in part and dissenting in part)). An amicus
    supporting the Government refers to “encouraging racial
    ——————
    17 As with the framework discussed in Part III–C of this opinion, we
    leave open the question whether Central Hudson provides the appro-
    priate test for deciding free speech challenges to provisions of the
    Lanham Act. And nothing in our decision should be read to speak to
    the validity of state unfair competition provisions or product libel laws
    that are not before us and differ from §1052(d)’s disparagement clause.
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)            25
    Opinion
    Opinion of
    of the Court
    ALITO, J.
    tolerance and protecting the privacy and welfare of indi-
    viduals.” Brief for Native American Organizations as
    Amici Curiae 21. But no matter how the point is phrased,
    its unmistakable thrust is this: The Government has an
    interest in preventing speech expressing ideas that offend.
    And, as we have explained, that idea strikes at the heart
    of the First Amendment. Speech that demeans on the
    basis of race, ethnicity, gender, religion, age, disability, or
    any other similar ground is hateful; but the proudest boast
    of our free speech jurisprudence is that we protect the
    freedom to express “the thought that we hate.” United
    States v. Schwimmer, 
    279 U.S. 644
    , 655 (1929) (Holmes,
    J., dissenting).
    The second interest asserted is protecting the orderly
    flow of commerce. 
    See 808 F.3d, at 1379
    –1381 (Reyna, J.,
    dissenting); Brief for Petitioner 49; Brief for Native Amer-
    ican Organizations as Amicus Curiae 18–21. Commerce,
    we are told, is disrupted by trademarks that “involv[e]
    disparagement of race, gender, ethnicity, national origin,
    religion, sexual orientation, and similar demographic
    
    classification.” 808 F.3d, at 1380
    –1381 (opinion of Reyna,
    J.). Such trademarks are analogized to discriminatory
    conduct, which has been recognized to have an adverse
    effect on commerce. See ibid.; Brief for Petitioner 49;
    Brief for Native American Organizations as Amici Curiae
    18–20.
    A simple answer to this argument is that the dispar-
    agement clause is not “narrowly drawn” to drive out
    trademarks that support invidious discrimination. The
    clause reaches any trademark that disparages any person,
    group, or institution. It applies to trademarks like the
    following: “Down with racists,” “Down with sexists,”
    “Down with homophobes.” It is not an anti-discrimination
    clause; it is a happy-talk clause. In this way, it goes much
    further than is necessary to serve the interest asserted.
    The clause is far too broad in other ways as well. The
    26                     MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion
    Opinion of
    of the Court
    ALITO, J.
    clause protects every person living or dead as well as every
    institution. Is it conceivable that commerce would be
    disrupted by a trademark saying: “James Buchanan was a
    disastrous president” or “Slavery is an evil institution”?
    There is also a deeper problem with the argument that
    commercial speech may be cleansed of any expression
    likely to cause offense. The commercial market is well
    stocked with merchandise that disparages prominent
    figures and groups, and the line between commercial and
    non-commercial speech is not always clear, as this case
    illustrates. If affixing the commercial label permits the
    suppression of any speech that may lead to political or
    social “volatility,” free speech would be endangered.
    * *    *
    For these reasons, we hold that the disparagement
    clause violates the Free Speech Clause of the First
    Amendment. The judgment of the Federal Circuit is
    affirmed.
    It is so ordered.
    JUSTICE GORSUCH took no part in the consideration or
    decision of this case.
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)            1
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 15–1293
    _________________
    JOSEPH MATAL, INTERIM DIRECTOR, UNITED
    STATES PATENT AND TRADEMARK OFFICE,
    PETITIONER v. SIMON SHIAO TAM
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE FEDERAL CIRCUIT
    [June 19, 2017]
    JUSTICE KENNEDY, with whom JUSTICE GINSBURG,
    JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR, and JUSTICE KAGAN join, concurring
    in part and concurring in the judgment.
    The Patent and Trademark Office (PTO) has denied the
    substantial benefits of federal trademark registration to
    the mark THE SLANTS. The PTO did so under the man-
    date of the disparagement clause in 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1052(a),
    which prohibits the registration of marks that may “dis-
    parage . . . or bring . . . into contemp[t] or disrepute” any
    “persons, living or dead, institutions, beliefs, or national
    symbols.”
    As the Court is correct to hold, §1052(a) constitutes
    viewpoint discrimination—a form of speech suppression so
    potent that it must be subject to rigorous constitutional
    scrutiny. The Government’s action and the statute on
    which it is based cannot survive this scrutiny.
    The Court is correct in its judgment, and I join Parts I,
    II, and III–A of its opinion. This separate writing explains
    in greater detail why the First Amendment’s protections
    against viewpoint discrimination apply to the trademark
    here. It submits further that the viewpoint discrimination
    rationale renders unnecessary any extended treatment of
    other questions raised by the parties.
    2                       MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    I
    Those few categories of speech that the government can
    regulate or punish—for instance, fraud, defamation, or
    incitement—are well established within our constitutional
    tradition. See United States v. Stevens, 
    559 U.S. 460
    , 468
    (2010). Aside from these and a few other narrow excep-
    tions, it is a fundamental principle of the First Amend-
    ment that the government may not punish or suppress
    speech based on disapproval of the ideas or perspectives
    the speech conveys. See Rosenberger v. Rector and Visi-
    tors of Univ. of Va., 
    515 U.S. 819
    , 828–829 (1995).
    The First Amendment guards against laws “targeted at
    specific subject matter,” a form of speech suppression
    known as content based discrimination. Reed v. Town of
    Gilbert, 576 U. S. ___, ___ (2015) (slip op., at 12). This
    category includes a subtype of laws that go further, aimed
    at the suppression of “particular views . . . on a subject.”
    
    Rosenberger, 515 U.S., at 829
    . A law found to discrimi-
    nate based on viewpoint is an “egregious form of content
    discrimination,” which is “presumptively unconstitutional.”
    
    Id., at 829–830.
       At its most basic, the test for viewpoint discrimination is
    whether—within the relevant subject category—the gov-
    ernment has singled out a subset of messages for disfavor
    based on the views expressed. See Cornelius v. NAACP
    Legal Defense & Ed. Fund, Inc., 
    473 U.S. 788
    , 806 (1985)
    (“[T]he government violates the First Amendment when it
    denies access to a speaker solely to suppress the point of
    view he espouses on an otherwise includible subject”). In
    the instant case, the disparagement clause the Govern-
    ment now seeks to implement and enforce identifies the
    relevant subject as “persons, living or dead, institutions,
    beliefs, or national symbols.” 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1052(a). Within
    that category, an applicant may register a positive or
    benign mark but not a derogatory one. The law thus
    reflects the Government’s disapproval of a subset of mes-
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)           3
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    sages it finds offensive. This is the essence of viewpoint
    discrimination.
    The Government disputes this conclusion. It argues, to
    begin with, that the law is viewpoint neutral because it
    applies in equal measure to any trademark that demeans
    or offends. This misses the point. A subject that is first
    defined by content and then regulated or censored by
    mandating only one sort of comment is not viewpoint
    neutral. To prohibit all sides from criticizing their oppo-
    nents makes a law more viewpoint based, not less so. Cf.
    
    Rosenberger, supra, at 831
    –832 (“The . . . declaration that
    debate is not skewed so long as multiple voices are si-
    lenced is simply wrong; the debate is skewed in multiple
    ways”). The logic of the Government’s rule is that a law
    would be viewpoint neutral even if it provided that public
    officials could be praised but not condemned. The First
    Amendment’s viewpoint neutrality principle protects more
    than the right to identify with a particular side. It pro-
    tects the right to create and present arguments for partic-
    ular positions in particular ways, as the speaker chooses.
    By mandating positivity, the law here might silence dis-
    sent and distort the marketplace of ideas.
    The Government next suggests that the statute is view-
    point neutral because the disparagement clause applies to
    trademarks regardless of the applicant’s personal views or
    reasons for using the mark. Instead, registration is denied
    based on the expected reaction of the applicant’s audience.
    In this way, the argument goes, it cannot be said that
    Government is acting with hostility toward a particular
    point of view. For example, the Government does not
    dispute that respondent seeks to use his mark in a posi-
    tive way. Indeed, respondent endeavors to use The Slants
    to supplant a racial epithet, using new insights, musical
    talents, and wry humor to make it a badge of pride. Re-
    spondent’s application was denied not because the Gov-
    ernment thought his object was to demean or offend but
    4                      MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    because the Government thought his trademark would
    have that effect on at least some Asian-Americans.
    The Government may not insulate a law from charges of
    viewpoint discrimination by tying censorship to the reac-
    tion of the speaker’s audience. The Court has suggested
    that viewpoint discrimination occurs when the govern-
    ment intends to suppress a speaker’s beliefs, 
    Reed, supra
    ,
    at ___–___ (slip op., at 11–12), but viewpoint discrimina-
    tion need not take that form in every instance. The dan-
    ger of viewpoint discrimination is that the government is
    attempting to remove certain ideas or perspectives from a
    broader debate. That danger is all the greater if the ideas
    or perspectives are ones a particular audience might think
    offensive, at least at first hearing. An initial reaction may
    prompt further reflection, leading to a more reasoned,
    more tolerant position.
    Indeed, a speech burden based on audience reactions is
    simply government hostility and intervention in a differ-
    ent guise. The speech is targeted, after all, based on the
    government’s disapproval of the speaker’s choice of mes-
    sage. And it is the government itself that is attempting in
    this case to decide whether the relevant audience would
    find the speech offensive. For reasons like these, the
    Court’s cases have long prohibited the government from
    justifying a First Amendment burden by pointing to the
    offensiveness of the speech to be suppressed. See ante, at
    23 (collecting examples).
    The Government’s argument in defense of the statute
    assumes that respondent’s mark is a negative comment.
    In addressing that argument on its own terms, this opin-
    ion is not intended to imply that the Government’s inter-
    pretation is accurate. From respondent’s submissions, it
    is evident he would disagree that his mark means what
    the Government says it does. The trademark will have the
    effect, respondent urges, of reclaiming an offensive term
    for the positive purpose of celebrating all that Asian-
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)            5
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    Americans can and do contribute to our diverse Nation.
    Brief for Respondent 1–4, 42–43. While thoughtful per-
    sons can agree or disagree with this approach, the disso-
    nance between the trademark’s potential to teach and the
    Government’s insistence on its own, opposite, and negative
    interpretation confirms the constitutional vice of the
    statute.
    II
    The parties dispute whether trademarks are commercial
    speech and whether trademark registration should be
    considered a federal subsidy. The former issue may turn
    on whether certain commercial concerns for the protection
    of trademarks might, as a general matter, be the basis for
    regulation. However that issue is resolved, the viewpoint
    based discrimination at issue here necessarily invokes
    heightened scrutiny.
    “Commercial speech is no exception,” the Court has
    explained, to the principle that the First Amendment
    “requires heightened scrutiny whenever the government
    creates a regulation of speech because of disagreement
    with the message it conveys.” Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc.,
    
    564 U.S. 552
    , 566 (2011) (internal quotation marks omit-
    ted). Unlike content based discrimination, discrimination
    based on viewpoint, including a regulation that targets
    speech for its offensiveness, remains of serious concern in
    the commercial context. See Bolger v. Youngs Drug Prod-
    ucts Corp., 
    463 U.S. 60
    , 65, 71–72 (1983).
    To the extent trademarks qualify as commercial speech,
    they are an example of why that term or category does not
    serve as a blanket exemption from the First Amendment’s
    requirement of viewpoint neutrality. Justice Holmes’
    reference to the “free trade in ideas” and the “power of . . .
    thought to get itself accepted in the competition of the
    market,” Abrams v. United States, 
    250 U.S. 616
    , 630
    (1919) (dissenting opinion), was a metaphor. In the realm
    6                       MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    of trademarks, the metaphorical marketplace of ideas
    becomes a tangible, powerful reality. Here that real mar-
    ketplace exists as a matter of state law and our common-
    law tradition, quite without regard to the Federal Gov-
    ernment. See ante, at 2. These marks make up part of the
    expression of everyday life, as with the names of enter-
    tainment groups, broadcast networks, designer clothing,
    newspapers, automobiles, candy bars, toys, and so on. See
    Brief for Pro-Football, Inc., as Amicus Curiae 8 (collecting
    examples). Nonprofit organizations—ranging from medical-
    research charities and other humanitarian causes to
    political advocacy groups—also have trademarks, which
    they use to compete in a real economic sense for funding
    and other resources as they seek to persuade others to join
    their cause. See 
    id., at 8–9
    (collecting examples). To
    permit viewpoint discrimination in this context is to per-
    mit Government censorship.
    This case does not present the question of how other
    provisions of the Lanham Act should be analyzed under
    the First Amendment. It is well settled, for instance, that
    to the extent a trademark is confusing or misleading the
    law can protect consumers and trademark owners. See,
    e.g., FTC v. Winstead Hosiery Co., 
    285 U.S. 483
    , 493
    (1922) (“The labels in question are literally false, and . . .
    palpably so. All are, as the Commission found, calculated
    to deceive and do in fact deceive a substantial portion of
    the purchasing public”). This case also does not involve
    laws related to product labeling or otherwise designed to
    protect consumers. See 
    Sorrell, supra, at 579
    (“[T]he
    government’s legitimate interest in protecting consumers
    from commercial harms explains why commercial speech
    can be subject to greater governmental regulation than
    noncommercial speech” (internal quotation marks omit-
    ted)). These considerations, however, do not alter the
    speech principles that bar the viewpoint discrimination
    embodied in the statutory provision at issue here.
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)            7
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    It is telling that the Court’s precedents have recognized
    just one narrow situation in which viewpoint discrimina-
    tion is permissible: where the government itself is speak-
    ing or recruiting others to communicate a message on its
    behalf. See Legal Services Corporation v. Velazquez, 
    531 U.S. 533
    , 540–542 (2001); Board of Regents of Univ. of
    Wis. System v. Southworth, 
    529 U.S. 217
    , 229, 235 (2000);
    
    Rosenberger, 515 U.S., at 833
    . The exception is necessary
    to allow the government to stake out positions and pursue
    policies. See 
    Southworth, supra, at 235
    ; see also ante, at
    13–14. But it is also narrow, to prevent the government
    from claiming that every government program is exempt
    from the First Amendment. These cases have identified a
    number of factors that, if present, suggest the government
    is speaking on its own behalf; but none are present here.
    See ante, at 14–18.
    There may be situations where private speakers are
    selected for a government program to assist the govern-
    ment in advancing a particular message. That is not this
    case either. The central purpose of trademark registration
    is to facilitate source identification. To serve that broad
    purpose, the Government has provided the benefits of
    federal registration to millions of marks identifying every
    type of product and cause. Registered trademarks do so by
    means of a wide diversity of words, symbols, and mes-
    sages. Whether a mark is disparaging bears no plausible
    relation to that goal. While defining the purpose and
    scope of a federal program for these purposes can be com-
    plex, see, e.g., Agency for Int’l Development v. Alliance for
    Open Society Int’l, Inc., 570 U. S. ___, ___ (2013) (slip op.,
    at 8), our cases are clear that viewpoint discrimination is
    not permitted where, as here, the Government “expends
    funds to encourage a diversity of views from private
    speakers,” 
    Velazquez, supra, at 542
    (internal quotation
    marks omitted).
    8                      MATAL v. TAM
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    *   *    *
    A law that can be directed against speech found offen-
    sive to some portion of the public can be turned against
    minority and dissenting views to the detriment of all. The
    First Amendment does not entrust that power to the
    government’s benevolence. Instead, our reliance must be
    on the substantial safeguards of free and open discussion
    in a democratic society.
    For these reasons, I join the Court’s opinion in part and
    concur in the judgment.
    Cite as: 582 U. S. ____ (2017)           1
    Opinion of THOMAS, J.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 15–1293
    _________________
    JOSEPH MATAL, INTERIM DIRECTOR, UNITED
    STATES PATENT AND TRADEMARK OFFICE,
    PETITIONER v. SIMON SHIAO TAM
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE FEDERAL CIRCUIT
    [June 19, 2017]
    JUSTICE THOMAS, concurring in part and concurring in
    the judgment.
    I join the opinion of JUSTICE ALITO, except for Part II.
    Respondent failed to present his statutory argument
    either to the Patent and Trademark Office or to the Court
    of Appeals, and we declined respondent’s invitation to
    grant certiorari on this question. Ante, at 9. I see no
    reason to address this legal question in the first instance.
    See Star Athletica, L. L. C. v. Varsity Brands, Inc., 580
    U. S. ___, ___ (2017) (slip op., at 6).
    I also write separately because “I continue to believe
    that when the government seeks to restrict truthful
    speech in order to suppress the ideas it conveys, strict
    scrutiny is appropriate, whether or not the speech in
    question may be characterized as ‘commercial.’ ” Lorillard
    Tobacco Co. v. Reilly, 
    533 U.S. 525
    , 572 (2001) (THOMAS,
    J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment); see
    also, e.g., 44 Liquormart, Inc. v. Rhode Island, 
    517 U.S. 484
    , 518 (1996) (same). I nonetheless join Part IV of
    JUSTICE ALITO’s opinion because it correctly concludes
    that the disparagement clause, 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1052(a), is
    unconstitutional even under the less stringent test an-
    nounced in Central Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Public
    Serv. Comm’n of N. Y., 
    447 U.S. 557
    (1980).
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 15-1293

Citation Numbers: 2017 U.S. LEXIS 3872, 137 S. Ct. 1744, 198 L. Ed. 2d 366

Judges: Samuel Alito

Filed Date: 6/19/2017

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 1/13/2023

Authorities (54)

Pro Ftbl Inc v. Harjo, Suzan , 415 F.3d 44 ( 2005 )

Application of National Distillers and Chemical Corporation,... , 297 F.2d 941 ( 1962 )

Bachellar v. Maryland , 90 S. Ct. 1312 ( 1970 )

United Drug Co. v. Theodore Rectanus Co. , 39 S. Ct. 48 ( 1918 )

United States v. Schwimmer , 49 S. Ct. 448 ( 1929 )

Pro-Football, Inc. v. Harjo , 284 F. Supp. 2d 96 ( 2003 )

Spector Motor Service, Inc. v. McLaughlin , 65 S. Ct. 152 ( 1944 )

Cantwell v. Connecticut , 60 S. Ct. 900 ( 1940 )

Abrams v. United States , 40 S. Ct. 17 ( 1919 )

United States v. American Library Assn., Inc. , 123 S. Ct. 2297 ( 2003 )

Johanns v. Livestock Marketing Assn. , 125 S. Ct. 2055 ( 2005 )

Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc. , 131 S. Ct. 2653 ( 2011 )

Regan v. Taxation With Representation of Washington , 103 S. Ct. 1997 ( 1983 )

Bolger v. Youngs Drug Products Corp. , 103 S. Ct. 2875 ( 1983 )

Clinton v. Jones , 117 S. Ct. 1636 ( 1997 )

Wal-Mart Stores, Inc. v. Samara Brothers, Inc. , 120 S. Ct. 1339 ( 2000 )

Davenport v. Washington Education Ass'n , 127 S. Ct. 2372 ( 2007 )

Ysursa v. Pocatello Education Ass'n , 129 S. Ct. 1093 ( 2009 )

Pleasant Grove City v. Summum , 129 S. Ct. 1125 ( 2009 )

United States v. Stevens , 130 S. Ct. 1577 ( 2010 )

View All Authorities »