Holder, Christopher James ( 2020 )


Menu:
  •            IN THE COURT OF CRIMINAL APPEALS
    OF TEXAS
    NO. PD-1269-16
    CHRISTOPHER JAMES HOLDER, Appellant
    v.
    THE STATE OF TEXAS
    ON APPELLANT’S PETITION FOR DISCRETIONARY REVIEW
    FROM THE FIFTH COURT OF APPEALS
    COLLIN COUNTY
    YEARY, J., filed a concurring and dissenting opinion.
    CONCURRING AND DISSENTING OPINION
    I agree with the Court’s resolution of Appellant’s statutory claim. That resolution is
    consistent with our opinion last year in Sims v. State, 
    569 S.W.3d 634
    (Tex. Crim. App.
    2019). To that extent, I concur in the result the majority reaches today.
    I part ways with the Court, however, in its interpretation of Article I, Section 9 of
    the Texas Constitution. TEX. CONST. art. I, § 9. We did not originally grant review of
    Appellant’s claim predicated on Article I, Section 9, and Appellant did not raise a Fourth
    HOLDER ― 2
    Amendment claim on direct appeal. Holder v. State, No. 05-15-00818-CR, 
    2016 WL 4421362
    (Tex. App.—Dallas Aug. 19, 2016) (not designated for publication); U.S. CONST.
    amend. IV. After the petition was granted and pending resolution in this Court, Appellant
    filed a motion requesting that we remand the cause to the court of appeals for further
    consideration of his Article I, Section 9, claim in light of the United States Supreme Court’s
    intervening decision in Carpenter v. United States, 
    138 S. Ct. 2206
    (2018). Although
    Carpenter resolved only a Fourth Amendment issue, Appellant noted that this Court, in
    Hankston v. State, 
    517 S.W.3d 112
    (Tex. Crim. App. 2017), had tethered its construction
    of Article I, Section 9, to the Supreme Court’s interpretation of the Fourth Amendment.
    But rather than remand the cause, as Appellant had requested, this Court simply ordered
    the parties to file additional briefs addressing whether we should revisit our construction
    of Article I, Section 9, in view of Carpenter. Holder v. State, ___ S.W.3d ___, No. PD-
    1269-16, 
    2019 WL 5445198
    (Tex. Crim. App. 2019).
    Instead of slavishly following Carpenter, as the Court now does, I would adhere to
    the construction that we unanimously placed upon Article I, Section 9, of our State
    Constitution in Hankston. Given that our construction in Hankston was the one that we said
    “ma[d]e[] more sense” to 
    us, 517 S.W.3d at 120
    , it is far from clear to me that we should
    follow Carpenter’s lead.
    The Texas Constitution means what it means, and that meaning does not vary on the
    whim of a majority of Justices sitting at any given moment on the United States Supreme
    Court. It is instead emphatically the duty of the Judges of this Court—the court of last
    resort for criminal cases in our state—to construe our own state constitution to mean
    HOLDER ― 3
    exactly what it says, no more and no less. For that reason, an unexpected pronouncement
    from the United States Supreme Court with respect to the scope of Fourth Amendment
    protections cannot change the meaning of our analog state constitutional provision, Article
    I, Section 9, once we have authoritatively construed it. Only when the people of Texas
    amend our constitution does it change at all.
    We have long recognized our own prerogative to construe provisions of our own
    state constitution either more or less protectively of individual rights than the United States
    Supreme Court construes analogous provisions of the United States Constitution. As we
    noted in Hulit v. State, 
    982 S.W.2d 431
    , 437 (Tex. Crim. App. 1998), the scope of the
    protection of individual rights embodied in the Texas Constitution “may be lesser, greater,
    or the same as those of the federal constitution.” What this fundamental concept of
    federalism ultimately means is that “the Texas Constitution will be interpreted
    independently.” 
    Id. We further
    explained that “[t]he Supremacy Clause [of the United
    States Constitution] means that, in practical terms, persons will always be able to avail
    themselves of the greater right. * * * But it does not mean that a court, faithfully
    interpreting state laws, can only find in them protections that equal or exceed federal laws.”
    
    Id. 1 1
     In Hulit, we held that, unlike the Fourth Amendment, “the warrant clause in [Article I,] Section
    9 [of the Texas Constitution] does not mean that a warrant is indispensable to a valid search and
    
    seizure.” 982 S.W.2d at 435
    . Moreover, we have long held that Article I, Section 9, does not
    incorporate an exclusionary rule. See 
    id. at 439
    (Keller, P.J., concurring) (citing Welchek v. State,
    
    93 Tex. Crim. 271
    , 280‒81, 
    247 S.W. 524
    , 529 (1922), for the proposition that there is no
    exclusionary rule embedded in Article I, Section 9); Richardson v. State, 
    865 S.W.2d 944
    , 948 n.3
    (Tex. Crim. App. 1993) (same); Bauder v. State, 
    921 S.W.2d 696
    , 700 (Tex. Crim. App. 1996)
    (Clinton, J., concurring) (same).
    HOLDER ― 4
    In our opinion in Ford v. State, 
    477 S.W.3d 321
    , 334–35 (Tex. Crim. App. 2015),
    every participating member of this Court joined in holding that the Fourth Amendment
    permitted the State to obtain without a warrant historical cell-site-location information
    (CSLI) of four days’ duration, even while acknowledging “that Fourth Amendment
    concerns might be raised if long-term location information were acquired[.]” Observing
    that the United States Supreme Court was “primed” to take up this issue, we predicted that
    it would eventually hold that the State’s warrantless acquisition of no more than four days’
    worth of CSLI data from Ford’s service provider would be found acceptable because it
    “falls squarely inside the third-party-doctrine ball-park.” 
    Id. at 335;
    see also Love v. State,
    
    543 S.W.3d 835
    , 841 (Tex. Crim. App. 2016) (holding, on authority of Ford, that
    “Appellant’s call logs and CSLI are not . . . constitutionally protected”). Sixteen months
    later, the United States Supreme Court had still not taken up the issue, and we were
    confronted with the question whether we would construe our own constitutional analog
    any differently than we had foreseen the United States Supreme Court resolving the Fourth
    Amendment question. We opted to follow the path we thought the United States Supreme
    Court would eventually take in its Fourth Amendment jurisprudence, as we had predicted
    in Ford. 
    Hankston, 517 S.W.3d at 120
    .
    Accordingly, we held in Hankston that it would be consistent with Article I, Section
    9, for the State to obtain some twelve months of CSLI data without a warrant. 
    Id. at 114,
    121–22. We explained that “[t]here was a voluntary conveyance of the cell phone records,
    and, under the third-party doctrine, that conveyance destroyed the reasonable expectation
    of privacy in the conveyed information.” 
    Id. at 122.
    We applied the third-party doctrine to
    HOLDER ― 5
    reach this result, not because we deemed ourselves bound to interpret Article I, Section 9,
    of our own constitution in lockstep with Fourth Amendment jurisprudence, but because we
    thought it made “more sense” to construe both the Fourth Amendment and Article I,
    Section 9, in this way. 
    Id. at 120.
    Our original opinion in Hankston was unanimous.
    As it turns out, our prediction about how the United States Supreme Court would
    interpret the Fourth Amendment was wrong. In Carpenter, a majority of the United States
    Supreme Court declined to extend the third-party doctrine to cover CSLI records―at least
    for any period of time greater than seven days. 
    See 138 S. Ct. at 2217
    n.3 (“It is sufficient
    for our purposes today to hold that accessing seven days of CSLI constitutes a Fourth
    Amendment search.”). Three dissenting Justices argued vigorously, and at length, that the
    third-party doctrine applies, if anything, with even greater force in the CSLI context, and
    that a cell-phone user simply lacks any expectation of privacy in records kept by his service
    provider. 
    Id. at 2226–33
    (Kennedy, J., dissenting, joined by Thomas and Alito, JJ.). 12 This
    2
    In explaining in Carpenter the reason why he disagreed with the majority’s rejection of the third-
    party doctrine in the context of CSLI evidence, Justice Kennedy observed:
    [T]he Court maintains . . . [that] cell-site records are “unique” because they are
    “comprehensive” in their reach; allow for retrospective collection; are “easy, cheap,
    and efficient compared to traditional investigative tools”; and are not exposed to
    cell phone service providers in a meaningfully voluntary manner. [Citing majority
    
    opinion, 138 S. Ct. at 2216
    ‒228, 2220, 2223.] But many other kinds of business
    records can be so described. Bank and credit card companies keep a comprehensive
    account of almost every transaction an individual makes on a daily basis. “With
    just the click of a button, the Government can access each [company’s] deep
    repository of historical [financial] information at practically no expense.” [quoting
    majority opinion at 2218.] And the decision whether to transact with banks and
    credit card companies is no more or less voluntary than the decision whether to use
    a cell phone. Today, just as when [United States v. Miller, 
    425 U.S. 435
    (1976)]
    was decided, “‘it is impossible to participate in the economic life of contemporary
    society without maintaining a bank 
    account.’” 425 U.S. at 451
    (BRENNAN, J.,
    HOLDER ― 6
    was the position that we ourselves unanimously said made “more sense” in Hankston. Why,
    exactly, does it no longer make more sense?
    While there are procedural similarities, this case is not ultimately like Crittenden v.
    State, 
    899 S.W.2d 668
    (Tex. Crim. App. 1995). At issue in Crittenden was whether we
    should construe Article I, Section 9, the same as the Fourth Amendment with respect to the
    issue of so-called pretext stops. Three years earlier, this Court had construed the Fourth
    Amendment to embrace an objective approach to this issue. Garcia v. State, 
    827 S.W.2d 937
    (Tex. Crim. App. 1992). But the United States Supreme Court had not spoken
    authoritatively on that issue when we decided Garcia. Thus, there was no construction of
    the Fourth Amendment with respect to the issue of pretext stops for this Court to consider.
    We adopted the objective test from among competing alternatives in Garcia simply
    because we said it was the standard that made “more sense” to us.
    That being the case, when it came time to decide in Crittenden whether to deviate
    from our construction of the Fourth Amendment in interpreting Article I, Section 9, we
    adhered to the standard that had made “more sense” to us in Garcia. Crittenden, 899
    dissenting). But this Court, nevertheless, has held that individuals do not have a
    reasonable expectation of privacy in financial records.
    Carpenter, 
    138 S. Ct. 2232
    ‒33 (Kennedy, J., dissenting). This reasoning mirrors our own in Ford,
    which led us to conclude that, “like the bank customer in Miller, . . . appellant cannot meet the
    reasonable-expectation-of-privacy test.” 
    Ford, 477 S.W.3d at 331
    . See also David Stone,
    Comment, Saving America’s Privacy Rights: Why Carpenter v. United States Was Wrongly
    Decided and Why Courts Should Be Promoting Legislative Reform Rather Than Extending
    Existing Privacy Jurisprudence, 51 ST. MARY’S L.J. 223, 270 (2019) (“Mr. Carpenter was not
    searched under either of the Supreme Court’s search tests. Because Mr. Carpenter did not own the
    CSLI, he cannot win under the trespass test. Alternatively, Mr. Carpenter did not have a reasonable
    expectation of privacy in CSLI voluntarily conveyed to the cell phone company by purchasing its
    services.”).
    HOLDER 
    7 S.W.2d at 673
    & n.8. Thus, we chose to apply the objective test under Article I, Section 9,
    not as a purely logical proposition—that, because we had previously construed the Fourth
    Amendment that way, logic dictated that we must also construe Article I, Section 9, the
    same way—but because it made “more sense” to us, deciding the issue in a precedential
    vacuum, to interpret both provisions that way. 
    Id. 3 As
    it happens, the United States
    Supreme Court eventually agreed, adopting the objective test for Fourth Amendment
    purposes a year later in Whren v. United States, 
    516 U.S. 690
    (1996).
    Here, the opposite has occurred. What made more sense to all of us regarding the
    scope of the third-party doctrine—both in attempting to predict the United States Supreme
    Court’s eventual Fourth Amendment holding, in Ford, and in our own independent
    construction of Article I, Section 9, in Hankston—did not correspond with the United
    States Supreme Court’s ultimate view of the Fourth Amendment in Carpenter. That does
    not mean we are now obliged to abandon our own view of what makes “more sense,” at
    least for purposes of Article I, Section 9. Especially in light of the strong arguments
    3
    The Court emphasized in Crittenden that it was construing an aspect of search and seizure
    jurisprudence about which “the Supreme Court has not authoritatively 
    spoken.” 899 S.W.2d at 673
    n.8. In that context, the Court declared that, “[a]bsent some significant difference in the text of [the
    Fourth Amendment versus Article I, Section 9], or some historically documented difference in
    attitude between the respective drafters, there would be no apparent reason to prefer an
    interpretation of Article I, [Section] 9 any different than our preferred interpretation of the Fourth
    Amendment.” 
    Id. (Emphasis added).
    By this the Court in Crittenden did not mean to say, as the
    Court implies today, that we should always construe the two provisions in lock-step absent some
    textual or historical reason not to―our “own lights” notwithstanding. See Majority Opinion at 10
    (quoting Olson v. State, 
    484 S.W.2d 756
    , 762 (Tex. Crim. App. 1969)). Instead, the Crittenden
    footnote stands as an expression of intent, whenever we write on a clean jurisprudential slate, to
    construe Article I, Section 9, in the way we think the Supreme Court ought to construe the Fourth
    Amendment―not necessarily the way the Supreme Court may actually come to construe it later
    on. The Court today errs to understand it otherwise.
    HOLDER ― 8
    marshaled by the dissenters against the Carpenter majority’s refusal to apply the third-
    party doctrine in the CSLI context, it is not at all clear why our previous construction of
    Article I, Section 9, no longer makes “more sense” to the Court.
    The Court today professes to have changed its mind because of Chief Justice
    Roberts’s exhaustive analysis of “the privacy issues implicated by CSLI, which we did not
    do in our original Hankston opinion[.]” Majority Opinion at 21. It is not clear to me that
    the Court did not consider these arguments in Hankston―and reject them. 
    See 517 S.W.3d at 116
    (“According to Appellant, this same expectation of privacy applies even more to
    cell phones because in today’s society cell phones never leave our sides, and allowing data
    points to be created in numerous public and private locations enables the State to virtually
    reconstruct one’s past actions and deduce a tremendous amount of private information.”);
    
    id. at 121
    (“In Ford, we acknowledged, but declined to follow, the reasoning that ‘[p]eople
    cannot be deemed to have volunteered to forfeit expectations of privacy by simply seeking
    active participation in society through use of their cell phones. We were not persuaded by
    the argument that cell phone users must forego the use of technology that has become a
    pervasive and insistent part of modern, everyday life or forego the protections of the Fourth
    Amendment.”) (internal quotation marks omitted); 
    id. at 122
    n.63 (expressly declining to
    follow the lead of the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts holding that “the nature of
    cellular telephone technology and cell phone data and the character of cellular telephone
    use in our current society render the third party doctrine . . . inapposite”). But if the Court
    genuinely failed to consider these arguments in Hankston, of which it was aware, one might
    fairly wonder why.
    HOLDER ― 9
    The Court also reviews “the constitutional debates in Texas, which we did not
    previously do,” and, according to the Court, “they show no intention on the part of our
    framers for Texas citizens to have less protection from unreasonable searches and
    seizure[s] under the Texas Constitution than the United States Constitution.” Majority
    Opinion at 21. Again, one might fairly ask why the Court failed to consult relevant sources
    before, if in fact it did fail.
    More alarmingly, the Court’s categorical description of the framers’ intentions
    suggests that Hulit itself was wrongly decided―that we are not at liberty to construe
    Article I, Section 9, less protectively than the United States Supreme Court construes, or
    may eventually come to construe, the Fourth Amendment. Is that really what the Court
    means to say today? The Court does not purport to overrule Hulit, or any of the other cases
    that have in fact construed Article I, Section 9, to be less protective. 4 Indeed, the Court
    itself continues to assert in its opinion today that “there is no implied warrant requirement
    in Article I, Section 9.” Majority Opinion at 22 (citing 
    Hulit, 982 S.W.2d at 436
    ). Have we
    been wrong since Mapp v. Ohio, 
    367 U.S. 643
    (1961), to think that Article I, Section 9,
    imposes no exclusionary rule?
    The Court declares that for us to continue to apply the third-party doctrine in the
    CSLI context would “amount to us being different just because we can[.]” Majority
    Opinion at 22. But there is a big difference between “being different just because we can”
    and fairly questioning the infallibility of the United States Supreme Court. To what
    4
    See note 1, ante.
    HOLDER ― 10
    amounts to this Court’s abdication of its “own lights,” Majority Opinion at 10 (quoting
    Olson v. State, 
    484 S.W.2d 756
    , 762 (Tex. Crim. App. 1969)), I respectfully dissent.
    FILED:              March 11, 2020
    PUBLISH