In re Estate of William J. Hannifin , 2013 UT 46 ( 2013 )


Menu:
  •              This opinion is subject to revision before final
    publication in the Pacific Reporter.
    
    2013 UT 46
    IN THE
    SUPREME COURT OF THE STATE OF UTAH
    ———————
    In the Matter of the ESTATE OF WILLIAM J. HANNIFIN
    ———————
    MAX HILL, as Special Administrator of the Estate,
    Appellant,
    v.
    WILLIS NAKAI, individually and as
    Personal Representative of the Estate,
    Appellee.
    ———————
    No. 20111125
    Filed August 2, 2013
    ———————
    Third District, Salt Lake
    The Honorable Robert K. Hilder
    No. 103900808
    ———————
    Attorneys:
    Charles M. Bennett, Salt Lake City, for appellant
    Donald J. Winder, Jerald V. Hale, Salt Lake City, for appellee
    ———————
    JUSTICE LEE authored the opinion of the Court, in which
    CHIEF JUSTICE DURRANT and ASSOCIATE CHIEF JUSTICE NEHRING
    joined.
    JUSTICE DURHAM filed a dissenting opinion,
    in which JUSTICE PARRISH joined.
    ———————
    JUSTICE LEE, opinion of the Court:
    ¶1 Max Hill, in his capacity as Special Representative of the
    Estate of William J. Hannifin, appeals from a district court order
    awarding Willis Nakai a portion of that estate. Though Nakai is
    neither biologically nor legally related to Hannifin, the district
    court determined that he was nonetheless entitled to inherit under
    the doctrine of equitable adoption.
    IN RE ESTATE OF WILLIAM J. HANNIFIN
    Opinion of the Court
    ¶2 We reverse. We hold that the doctrine of equitable adop-
    tion, first recognized in In re Williams’ Estates, 
    348 P.2d 683
     (Utah
    1960), has been preempted by the detailed provisions of Utah‘s
    Probate Code. See UTAH CODE §§ 75-1-101 to -8-101. And, because
    Nakai does not qualify under the Probate Code‘s intestate succes-
    sion provisions, we reverse the decision entitling him to inherit
    from Hannifin.
    I
    ¶3 Willis Nakai is a member of the Navajo Nation. He was
    raised by his aunt from infancy to age five or six. After her death,
    he attended a series of boarding schools, though his biological
    parents were living and married to each other throughout his
    childhood. At one of these schools, the Intermountain Indian
    School (IIS) in Brigham City, Utah, Nakai met Father William J.
    Hannifin, an Episcopal priest.
    ¶4 In the summer of 1958, Hannifin had occasion to visit the
    Navajo Reservation near Aneth, Utah, where Nakai and his family
    were then residing. During this visit, Hannifin had a conversation
    with Nakai‘s mother and maternal grandparents, during which
    Nakai‘s mother asked Hannifin to take Nakai—who was fourteen
    years old at the time—and raise him as his own child. Hannifin
    agreed. Because Nakai‘s father was frequently away from home
    and not involved in family matters, he was not a party to this
    conversation.
    ¶5 Hannifin assumed this parental role when Nakai returned
    to IIS the following school year. Though Nakai subsequently
    made brief yearly visits to see his biological family, his parents
    did not assert parental control over him and did not support him
    financially. Instead, from that point forward, Hannifin provided
    Nakai an allowance, food, clothing, medical care, transportation,
    and emotional support. He monitored Nakai‘s schoolwork and
    generally provided for Nakai‘s health and welfare. Though Nakai
    initially boarded at IIS and visited Hannifin only on weekends
    and holidays, he began living with Hannifin full time after he de-
    veloped health problems during his secondary education and con-
    tinued to live there throughout his secondary and college educa-
    tion.
    ¶6 From Nakai‘s return to IIS in 1958–59 until the end of Han-
    nifin‘s life, the two referred to each other as father and son and
    2
    Cite as: 
    2013 UT 46
    Opinion of the Court
    held themselves out to the community as such. Even after Nakai
    married and moved out of Hannifin‘s house, he and Hannifin
    maintained a close relationship, with Hannifin providing Nakai
    counsel and acting as if he were grandfather and great-
    grandfather to Nakai‘s children and grandchildren. Hannifin even
    arranged for many of his assets, including his life insurance poli-
    cy, bank accounts, and investment accounts to be transferred to
    Nakai upon Hannifin‘s death.
    ¶7 Yet when Hannifin died in 2009, he was intestate and had
    no spouse and no biological descendants. Nakai, alleging that he
    and his family were Hannifin‘s only known heirs and devisees,
    petitioned to be appointed as Personal Representative of Han-
    nifin‘s estate, which petition the district court granted.
    ¶8 Max Hill, acting on behalf of himself and nineteen other
    collateral relatives of Hannifin, petitioned the court to be appoint-
    ed Special Administrator of Hannifin‘s estate for the limited pur-
    pose of contesting Nakai‘s claim to the estate. The court granted
    Hill‘s petition and, following a bench trial, held that under the
    doctrine of equitable adoption, Nakai was entitled ―to inherit
    from Father Hannifin‘s estate as though he were his legally
    adopted son.‖ The district court also awarded Nakai attorney fees,
    which Hill opposed on the grounds that Nakai was not eligible to
    serve as Personal Representative.
    ¶9 Hill filed this appeal, arguing that Utah‘s enactment of the
    Probate Code preempted the common law doctrine of equitable
    adoption. That is a question of law, which we review de novo. See
    Navajo Nation v. State (In re Adoption of A.B.), 
    2010 UT 55
    , ¶ 21, 
    245 P.3d 711
    .
    II
    ¶10 We have long recognized the axiom ―that our precedent
    must yield when it conflicts with a validly enacted statute.‖ Pat-
    terson v. Patterson, 
    2011 UT 68
    , ¶ 37, 
    266 P.3d 828
    . Statutes ―may
    preempt the common law either by governing an area in so perva-
    sive a manner that it displaces the common law‖ (field preemp-
    tion) ―or by directly conflicting with the common law‖ (conflict
    preemption). OLP, L.L.C. v. Burningham, 
    2009 UT 75
    , ¶ 16, 
    225 P.3d 3
    IN RE ESTATE OF WILLIAM J. HANNIFIN
    Opinion of the Court
    177.1 Preemption may be indicated expressly, by a stated intent to
    preempt the common law. ―More often,‖ however, ―explicit pre-
    emption language does not appear, or does not directly answer
    the question. In that event, courts must consider whether the . . .
    statute‘s structure and purpose or nonspecific statutory language
    nonetheless reveal a clear, but implicit, pre-emptive intent.‖ Bish-
    op v. GenTec Inc., 
    2002 UT 36
    , ¶ 9, 
    48 P.3d 218
     (alteration in origi-
    nal) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    ¶11 We have relied on ―the federal model for determining
    whether federal law pre-empts state law‖ to determine ―whether
    a state statute pre-empts the common law.‖ Id.; see UTAH CODE
    § 68-3-2(1) (―The rule of the common law that a statute in deroga-
    tion of the common law is to be strictly construed does not apply
    to the Utah Code.‖). Under that model, ―[f]ield preemption occurs
    when the scope of a statute indicates that [the legislature] intend-
    ed [a statute] to occupy a field‖ in such a way ―as to make reason-
    able the inference that [the legislature] left no room for the [com-
    mon law] to supplement it.‖ In re Adoption of A.B., 
    2010 UT 55
    ,
    ¶ 31 (internal quotation marks omitted). Conflict preemption, on
    the other hand, ―occurs where it is impossible . . . to comply with
    both [the common law] and [a statute], or where [the common
    law] stands as an obstacle to the accomplishment and execution of
    the full purposes and objectives of [the legislature].‖ Id. ¶ 33 (al-
    teration in original) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    ¶12 This notion of conflict preemption is reiterated in the Pro-
    bate Code. Though the Code provides that ―principles of . . . equi-
    ty supplement its provisions,‖ UTAH CODE § 75-1-103, it also con-
    tains an express caveat that principles of equity may not be in-
    voked where they are ―displaced by the particular provisions of
    th[e] code.‖ Id. A judge-made doctrine that conflicts with a statute
    is certainly ―displaced‖ by it.2
    1  See Daniels v. Gamma W. Brachytherapy, LLC, 
    2009 UT 66
    , ¶ 49,
    
    221 P.3d 256
     (―A statute preempts a common law claim by specifi-
    cally adopting a limitation or prohibition on a claim or by com-
    prehensively addressing a particular area of law such that it dis-
    places the common law.‖).
    2 The argument that equitable adoption properly ―supple-
    ment[s]‖ the Code because it operates ―parallel with‖ it infra ¶¶
    4
    Cite as: 
    2013 UT 46
    Opinion of the Court
    ¶13 We find the Code to displace the doctrine of equitable
    adoption recognized in Williams’ Estates. In that case, a couple
    took a child into their home, agreeing with the birth mother that
    they would adopt the child and ―raise, care for and treat [her] in
    all respects as their own child.‖ In re Williams’ Estates, 
    348 P.2d 683
    , 685 (Utah 1960). Though they never formally adopted the
    child, they did raise her as their own. Id. at 684. And when the
    couple died intestate, the child claimed that ―she should be
    awarded the same share of the Williamses[‗] estate as she would
    have been entitled to had they . . . fulfilled their agreement to
    adopt.‖ Id. We agreed that a child in that situation could possibly
    inherit through intestacy, noting that
    39–40, is an effective acknowledgement that the two cannot be
    reconciled. A doctrine that operates outside (parallel to) the Code
    cannot be seen as a supplement to it. That is not to say that no
    provision of the Probate Code is amenable to supplementation. It
    is merely a recognition that the provisions prescribing who can
    take through succession (and in what order) are not. They are
    clear and detailed and leave no room for common-law adaptation.
    See Riddell v. Edwards, 
    76 P.3d 847
    , 855–56 (Alaska 2003) (recogniz-
    ing that Alaska‘s Uniform Probate Code gives courts ―latitude to
    supplement statutory provisions with equitable principles‖ but
    deciding that ―the particular provisions of statutory law govern-
    ing void and voidable marriages and accrual of allowances and
    share fully covered [the circumstances of the case] and affirma-
    tively displaced the equitable remedy‖ sought (internal quotation
    marks omitted)). So the fact that we may have supplemented oth-
    er parts of the Code in the past has no bearing on our decision in
    this case. See infra ¶ 40 (citing cases where we have purportedly
    ―supplemented [the code] in . . . outcome-determinative ways‖).
    In any event, in none of these past instances have we supplement-
    ed the Code in a way that conflicts with it. See, e.g., In re Estate of
    Pepper, 
    711 P.2d 261
    , 263 (Utah 1985) (holding that a rule 60(b) mo-
    tion can vacate an otherwise final closing order, a result that is
    specifically allowed under section 75-1-304‘s assertion that ―the
    rules of civil procedure, including the rules concerning vacation of
    orders and appellate review, govern formal proceedings under
    the [Probate Code]‖ (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    5
    IN RE ESTATE OF WILLIAM J. HANNIFIN
    Opinion of the Court
    [i]t is generally recognized that where a child‘s par-
    ents agree with the adoptive parents to relinquish all
    their rights to the child in consideration of the adopt-
    ed parents‘ agreement to adopt such child, . . . and
    such agreement is fully performed by all parties con-
    nected with such contract except there is no actual
    adoption, the courts will decree specific performance
    of such contract and thereby award to the child the
    same distributive share of the adoptive parents‘ es-
    tate as it would have been entitled to had the child
    actually been adopted as agreed.
    
    Id.
    ¶14 In such circumstances, we determined that ―[a] contract to
    adopt . . . may be proved by circumstantial evidence, but such ev-
    idence must be clear and convincing.‖ 
    Id.
     at 684–85. Though we
    have not had occasion to opine on this doctrine since it was rec-
    ognized, most other jurisdictions employing the doctrine have fol-
    lowed the same path, requiring claimants to prove the existence of
    an agreement to adopt. Modern Status of Law as to Equitable Adop-
    tion or Adoption by Estoppel, 
    122 A.L.R. 5th 205
     (2012). Most also
    limit use of the doctrine to situations that benefit the equitably
    adopted child, meaning, for example, that the doctrine does not
    prevent the equitably adopted child from inheriting from natural
    parents, and typically cannot be used by an adoptive parent to in-
    herit from the equitably adopted child. 
    Id.
     Courts deem these and
    other similar restrictions proper ―since equitable adoption is only
    an equitable remedy to enforce a contract right, is not intended or
    applied to create the legal relationship of parent and child, with
    all the legal consequences of such relationship, [and] is [not]
    meant to create a legal adoption.‖ 
    Id.
    ¶15 The Probate Code, enacted fifteen years after we embraced
    equitable adoption in Williams’ Estates, is in direct conflict with the
    doctrine in three principal respects: (A) Equitable adoption allows
    children who cannot satisfy the Probate Code‘s definition of
    ―Child‖ to nonetheless participate in intestate succession as if they
    had. (B) Equitably adopted children can take by succession from
    both natural and adoptive parents—despite the Code‘s clear
    mandate to the contrary. (C) The doctrine adds confusion and
    complexity to our law‘s intestate succession scheme, in contraven-
    6
    Cite as: 
    2013 UT 46
    Opinion of the Court
    tion of the Code‘s stated purpose of streamlining and clarifying
    the distribution of a decedent‘s estate.
    ¶16 In light of these conflicts, the equitable adoption doctrine
    cannot be squared with the Probate Code; it is impossible to satis-
    fy both the requirements of the Probate Code and the elements of
    equitable adoption.3 This is a doctrine in conflict with the Code,
    which we therefore repudiate as preempted by statute.4
    A
    ¶17 At the time of our decision in Williams’ Estates, our intestate
    succession statutes did not define the terms ―child‖ or ―parent.‖
    See UTAH CODE § 74-4-1 to -24 (1953). They did not distinguish
    classes of children that could take by succession (such as natural
    and adopted children) from those that could not (like foster chil-
    dren, stepchildren, and grandchildren). The Probate Code
    changed the landscape by providing precise definitions of parties
    legally entitled to take by intestate succession. These provisions
    displaced the open-ended system within which Williams’ Estates
    was situated.5
    3 Though we typically ―reconcile the common law with statutory
    law whenever possible,‖ see infra ¶ 36, here, for all the reasons
    discussed below, reconciliation is not possible.
    4   Though a number of states that have adopted the Uniform
    Probate Code have continued to endorse equitable adoption, see
    e.g., Poncho v. Bowdoin, 
    126 P.3d 1221
    , 1226 (N.M. Ct. App. 2005);
    Johnson v. Johnson, 
    617 N.W.2d 97
    , 101 (N.D. 2000), none of these
    states, to our knowledge, have considered the key question ad-
    dressed herein—whether there are conflicts between the Code and
    the common law doctrine that sustain a finding of preemption.
    See, e.g., Calista Corp. v. Mann, 
    564 P.2d 53
    , 61 & n.18 (Alaska 1977)
    (accepting and applying the doctrine without any preemption dis-
    cussion or analysis). And absent some analysis of this pivotal is-
    sue, these precedents are unhelpful. We look to other states‘
    caselaw to help us analyze the legal questions before us, not as a
    statistical exercise of nose-counting.
    5 Admittedly, the previous version of the Probate Code detailed
    the order in which different categories of takers took through suc-
    7
    IN RE ESTATE OF WILLIAM J. HANNIFIN
    Opinion of the Court
    ¶18 The Probate Code provides that ―[a]ny part of a decedent‘s
    estate not effectively disposed of by will passes by intestate suc-
    cession to the decedent‘s heirs as provided in‖ the Code. UTAH
    CODE § 75-2-101(1). Thus, the Code establishes a detailed scheme
    that governs the priority by which certain classes of heirs are enti-
    tled to succeed to the decedent‘s estate. Under the Code, ―[a]ny
    part of the intestate estate‖ that does not pass to the decedent‘s
    spouse (because, for example, the decedent‘s spouse did not sur-
    vive him) passes ―to the decedent‘s descendants per capita at each
    generation,‖ id. § 75-2-103(1)(a), and if no surviving descendants
    exist, then to the decedent‘s parent(s), id. § 75-2-103(1)(b). And if
    neither parent survived the decedent, the estate goes to the par-
    ents‘ descendants, if any, and then, if none exist, to the decedent‘s
    grandparents or the grandparents‘ descendants. Id. § 75-2-
    103(1)(c)-(e).
    ¶19 The second group of takers, ―the decedent‘s descendants,‖
    generally includes a decedent‘s children, ―with the relationship of
    parent and child . . . being determined by the definition of child
    and parent contained in [the Probate Code].‖ Id. § 75-1-201(9).
    And according to the Code, a ―Child‖ is ―any individual entitled
    to take as a child under this code by intestate succession from the
    parent whose relationship is involved and excludes any person
    who is only a stepchild, a foster child, a grandchild, or any more
    remote descendant.‖ Id. § 75-1-201(5). ―Parent‖ similarly ―includes
    any person entitled to take, or who would be entitled to take if the
    child died without a will, as a parent under this code by intestate
    succession from the child whose relationship is in question and
    excludes any person who is only a stepparent, foster parent, or
    grandparent.‖ Id. § 75-1-201(33). And ―for purposes of intestate
    succession by, through, or from a person, an individual is the
    child of the individual‘s natural parents‖ and ―[a]n adopted indi-
    vidual is the child of the adopting parent or parents and not of the
    natural parents.‖ Id. § 75-2-114(1), (2).
    ¶20 By enacting a Probate Code with a specific definition of
    ―child‖ that excludes those ―equitably‖ adopted, the legislature
    cession. See UTAH CODE § 74-4-5 (1953). But it did not define the
    proper members of each of these categories, and it was open-
    ended in that respect. See infra ¶ 38 n.2.
    8
    Cite as: 
    2013 UT 46
    Opinion of the Court
    preempted common law doctrines that are in conflict with the re-
    sults those definitions require.6 See Christensen v. Christensen (In re
    Estate of Christensen), 
    655 P.2d 646
    , 649 (Utah 1982) (deciding that
    because the Probate Code ―makes no mention‖ of a term that
    ―figured prominently in prior statutes and case law‖ that the
    ―omission must have been deliberate,‖ particularly ―[i]n a statute
    so carefully drafted‖ and determining that ―re-engraft[ment]‖ of
    that term ―by judicial decision‖ would be ―inappropriate‖). Under
    this scheme and according to these definitions, the only methods
    of determining who is a child for intestate succession purposes are
    legal adoption and natural parentage.7 And Nakai is neither Han-
    nifin‘s legally adopted nor his natural child.8 The closest Nakai
    comes to any of the relations delineated in the Probate Code is to a
    6 See In re Estate of Peterson, 
    716 P.2d 801
    , 803 (Utah 1986) (refus-
    ing to allow a judgment creditor to be joined in probate court pro-
    ceeding as an interested party because ―the Uniform Probate Code
    expressly limit[s] the categories of interested persons that may
    present claims‖ and the creditor was ―not among those designat-
    ed‖).
    7 Perhaps the doctrine of equitable adoption ―is not premised on
    our ability to judicially define the statutory term ‗child‘ or ‗par-
    ent.‖‘ See infra ¶ 39. But that does not at all answer the question
    before us. The fact that equitable adoption countermands the stat-
    utory definitions of ―child‖ and ―parent‖ does. Because the statute
    now provides these definitions, we can no longer define those cat-
    egories as we see fit. The statutory definitions foreclose our ability
    to decide that ―justice require[s] awarding‖ a person that does not
    meet those definitions ―the same inheritance she would have re-
    ceived if‖ she did. See infra ¶ 39.
    8  It is telling that under these definitions as well as under equi-
    table adoption, Hannifin can never qualify as a ―parent.‖ Because,
    as Nakai argues, equitable adoption ―is not intended to create the
    legal relationship of parent and child . . . and does not effect a le-
    gal adoption‖, it can never be used in reverse to allow an ―adop-
    tive‖ parent to take through intestate succession from an equita-
    bly adopted child. So, under the facts before us and as another ex-
    ample of the conflict between the Code and equitable adoption,
    not only is Nakai not a child, but Hannifin is also not a parent for
    purposes of intestate succession.
    9
    IN RE ESTATE OF WILLIAM J. HANNIFIN
    Opinion of the Court
    foster child, which is a category specifically excluded from taking
    intestate. Yet he falls short even there. A foster child/parent rela-
    tionship is one marked by legal rights and responsibilities, neither
    of which existed in this case. Nakai thus can have no claim under
    the Probate Code to a distribution through intestate succession.
    ¶21 It is thus impossible to comply with both the Probate Code
    and with the principles of equitable adoption. See In re Adoption of
    A.B., 
    2010 UT 55
    , ¶ 33 (stating that conflict preemption ―occurs
    where it is impossible . . . to comply with both [the common law]
    and [a statute]‖). Because Hannifin had neither a spouse nor chil-
    dren, the Probate Code requires that his estate pass to his parents
    or, if neither survived him, to his parents‘ descendants. UTAH
    CODE § 75-2-103(1)(a)-(c). If no takers exist in those categories,
    then his estate must past to his grandparents or, if none survived
    him, to their descendants. The statutory scheme makes this chain
    of distribution both clear and mandatory. And Hill and his fellow
    relatives qualify as takers in that chain. In contrast, equitable
    adoption requires that the estate pass to Nakai, a legal stranger to
    Hannifin, leaving nothing for Hill and the others. There is no way
    to reconcile the two different sets of requirements.
    B
    ¶22 Another intractable conflict between the Probate Code and
    equitable adoption stems from section 75-2-114(1)-(2), which
    states that ―for purposes of intestate succession . . . [a]n adopted
    individual is the child of the adopting parent . . . and not of the
    natural parents.‖ This section operates to prohibit adopted chil-
    dren from taking by intestacy from both their natural parents and
    their adoptive parents. This is in direct contravention of the doc-
    trine of equitable adoption, which is purely beneficial to the child
    and in no way alters the legal relationship between the claimant
    and the decedent or between the claimant and the biological par-
    ents. See infra ¶ 43.
    ¶23 At the time of Williams’ Estates, dual succession was per-
    mitted under our common law. In Benner v. Garrick (In re Benner’s
    Estate), 
    166 P.2d 257
    , 258 (Utah 1946), we recognized that principle
    while rejecting the argument that our succession statute fore-
    closed it. In so doing, the court concluded that ―a great array of
    authority convinces us that the laws of adoption do not so limit
    10
    Cite as: 
    2013 UT 46
    Opinion of the Court
    [the succession statute] as to cause a child, on being adopted, to
    lose its right to inherit from its natural parent.‖ 
    Id.
     The referenced
    succession statute provided only that ―[i]f the decedent leaves no
    surviving husband or wife, but leaves issue, the whole estate goes
    to such issue, and if such issue consists of more than one child liv-
    ing, or one child living and the issue of one or more deceased
    children, then the estate goes in equal shares to the children liv-
    ing, or to the child living and the issue of the deceased child or
    children by right or representation.‖ UTAH CODE § 101-4-5(2)
    (1946). The rule allowing dual inheritance existed only in the
    common law; it was never codified.
    ¶24 Thus, at the time of Williams’ Estates, the Utah Code posed
    no barrier to a ―beneficial‖ law of equitable adoption that could
    establish a right of succession from an equitably adopting parent
    without foreclosing any succession rights on the part of or flowing
    from natural parents. But when our legislature enacted the Pro-
    bate Code fifteen years later, it expressly foreclosed that possibil-
    ity. It did so by enacting section 114, which prevents a child from
    inheriting from two sets of parents. See UTAH CODE § 75-2-114(1)-
    (2) (―[F]or purposes of intestate succession . . . [a]n adopted indi-
    vidual is the child of the adopting parent . . . and not of the natu-
    ral parents.‖). That is a significant legislative development in our
    law in the Probate Code and one that is in direct conflict with eq-
    uitable adoption.
    ¶25 True, section 114 is more explicit in its rejection of the rul-
    ing in In re Brenner’s Estate than in its overriding of the broad
    principle of Williams’ Estates. But the fact that the legislature could
    have preempted Williams’ Estates more explicitly is of no conse-
    quence. In any matter of statutory construction of any conse-
    quence, it will almost always be true that the legislature could
    have more clearly repudiated one party‘s preferred construction.
    But the converse is almost always true as well, as it is here: Just as
    the legislature could have explicitly discarded the doctrine by
    name, it also could have expressly preserved it, as the California
    legislature did. See CAL. PROBATE CODE § 6455 (―Nothing in this
    chapter affects or limits application of the judicial doctrine of eq-
    uitable adoption for the benefit of the child or the child‘s issue.‖).
    ¶26 The legislature‘s failure to speak more clearly does not
    provide a basis for us interpreting the unambiguous words that it
    11
    IN RE ESTATE OF WILLIAM J. HANNIFIN
    Opinion of the Court
    did use. See Badaracco v. C.I.R., 
    464 U.S. 386
    , 398 (1984) (―Courts
    are not authorized to rewrite a statute because they deem its ef-
    fects susceptible of improvement.‖). And those words are plenty
    clear enough. The Probate Code expressly forecloses a core ele-
    ment of the doctrine of equitable adoption (dual succession).9 That
    is more than enough to sustain the conclusion that the Code is in
    conflict with the common law doctrine, and thus that the latter is
    preempted.
    ¶27 We do not and cannot require the legislature to use magic
    words or express references to our precedent to preempt it. So it is
    no matter that ―[n]o provision in the Probate Code mentions . . .
    equitable adoption‖ or that ―the legislature has not specifically
    abolished equitable adoption,‖ as Nakai claims. We look at the
    words the statute does use, the results those words require, and
    the scheme that they create to decide whether our precedent has a
    continuing place in the law. See Bishop, 
    2002 UT 36
    , ¶ 9; Burning-
    ham, 
    2009 UT 75
    , ¶ 16. And here the answer is clear. Dual succes-
    sion is an inherent element of equitable adoption. Yet dual succes-
    sion is expressly foreclosed by statute. The conflict is palpable and
    explicit. Again, it is impossible to comply with both the Probate
    Code and with the judge-made doctrine of equitable adoption, as
    the former prohibits what the latter requires. And in light of this
    conflict, our only option is to abandon the doctrine of equitable
    adoption.
    9  Our holding is not that section 114 contains ―a one-person-one-
    inheritance rule.‖ See infra ¶ 44. Rather, the statute establishes a
    one-set-of-parents inheritance rule. And equitable adoption treats
    an equitable adoptee as one entitled to inherit from a decedent as
    though she were the biological or adopted child of the decedent
    without cutting off inheritance rights from actual biological or
    adoptive parents. See infra ¶ 43. That treatment, moreover, runs
    afoul of Section 114. Our construction of that section, and of the
    other intestacy provisions of the Probate Code, does nothing to
    alter the ability of ―individuals to inherit from a wide range of rel-
    atives.‖ See infra ¶ 44. It simply gives proper respect to the word
    ―relative.‖
    12
    Cite as: 
    2013 UT 46
    Opinion of the Court
    C
    ¶28 Such abandonment is the only way to maintain fidelity to
    the objectives expressly detailed in the Probate Code. See Bishop,
    
    2002 UT 36
    , ¶ 9 (stating the court considers a statute‘s stated ob-
    jective in determining preemptive intent). As the Code indicates,
    its detailed intestate succession scheme is designed:
    (a) To simplify and clarify the law concerning the af-
    fairs of decedents, missing persons . . .;
    (b) To discover and make effective the intent of a de-
    cedent in distribution of his property;
    (c) To promote a speedy and efficient system for ad-
    ministering the estate of the decedent and making
    distribution to his successors;
    (d) To facilitate use and enforcement of certain trusts;
    and
    (e) To make uniform the law among the various juris-
    dictions.
    
    Id.
     § 75-1-102(2).
    ¶29 The doctrine of equitable adoption undermines these objec-
    tives by introducing uncertainty, complexity, and inefficiency—
    the very evils the Probate Code was designed to avoid.
    ¶30 Though the equitable adoption doctrine has been on the
    books for more than fifty years, neither we nor any other Utah
    court has given it any dimension. This boundary-less quality is
    another point of incompatibility with the Probate Code, which
    values predictability and stability. Were we to retain the doctrine,
    we would have to provide predictable definition to the otherwise
    vague standard announced in Williams’ Estates. For instance, in
    future cases we would surely be called on to decide questions
    along the following lines: Must both biological parents be party to
    the agreement to adopt? What kind of evidence is required to
    prove the existence of an agreement to adopt? How long must the
    adoptive parents treat the child as their own before the child qual-
    ifies for intestate succession? Just how limited must the child‘s re-
    13
    IN RE ESTATE OF WILLIAM J. HANNIFIN
    Opinion of the Court
    lationship with his biological family be? How completely must the
    natural parents relinquish ―all their rights to the child‖?10
    ¶31 In working to populate these fields, we would only com-
    pound the problem we identify today. With each new contour
    added to the standard, we would inevitably substitute our own
    policy choice for that expressed by the legislature when it enacted
    the Probate Code. We cannot condone such substitution.11 In the
    Code the legislature decided, as a policy matter, that efficiency
    and predictability are best served by distributing the estates of
    those that die intestate in accordance with a prediction as to the
    preference of the average intestate decedent.12 And that prediction
    follows biological and legal relationship lines.13 We have no au-
    10 The dissent suggests that equitable adoption doesn‘t conflict
    with the Probate Code because the statute‘s ―invit[ation]‖ to sup-
    plement the Probate Code with legal and equitable principles is
    evidence that ―the legislature evidently is willing to tolerate a de-
    gree of complication in furtherance of a just and equitable out-
    come.‖ See infra ¶ 46. But the legislature can be seen as making
    that determination only where it left room for such supplementa-
    tion. Here it left no such room.
    11  See Harper v. Lucas (In re Estate of Lucas), No. ADM 1327-03,
    
    2005 WL 674682
    , at *7–8 (D.C. Super. March 22, 2005) (―The legis-
    lature of the District of Columbia has . . . provided a comprehen-
    sive set of laws for intestate succession . . . . This Court is of the
    opinion that it should not use its equity power to disturb the Dis-
    trict‘s statutory scheme. . . . Whether to permit inheritance by one
    who is neither the natural nor the adopted child of an intestate is a
    policy issue for the legislative branch.‖).
    12  See UNIF. PROBATE CODE, art. II, pt. 1 gen. cmt. (1969) (stating
    that the Probate Code is a gap filler meant ―to reflect the normal
    desire of the owner of the wealth as to the disposition of his prop-
    erty at death‖); Joel R. Glucksman, Intestate Succession in New Jer-
    sey, Does it Conform to Popular Expectations?, 12 COLUM. J. L. & SOC.
    PROBS. 253, 266 (1976) (stating that intestacy laws ―pattern what
    people desire to do in distributing an estate‖).
    13 The question whether the decedent in this case ―would likely
    have preferred to leave his estate to an individual whom the de-
    cedent raised as his own child rather than to distant relatives,‖
    14
    Cite as: 
    2013 UT 46
    Opinion of the Court
    thority to second-guess that decision.14 Doing so would substitute
    our preference for that of the legislature. It would also override
    the presumptive preference of the decedent, who is entitled to
    presume that absent a will his estate will pass in accordance with
    the detailed scheme enacted by the legislature, and not with the
    second-guesses of a court.15
    ¶32 Thus, equitable adoption ―stands as an obstacle to the ac-
    complishment and execution of the full purposes and objectives of
    [the legislature]‖ in enacting the Probate Code. In re Adoption of
    A.B., 
    2010 UT 55
    , ¶ 33. The two cannot coexist. And when a
    infra ¶ 47, is a matter beyond our capacity to resolve on this rec-
    ord. As an appellate court we are in no position to engage in such
    speculation. And in any event the question is withheld from us by
    the terms of the Probate Code.
    14 It is certainly true, as the dissent suggests, that ―the legislature
    can amend the statute to direct a different outcome in future cas-
    es‖ if it ―disapproves‖ of the way we tinker with its statutory en-
    actments. See infra ¶35. But the availability of a legislative self-
    help remedy is of little consequence. We are tasked with interpret-
    ing the legislature‘s handiwork by our best lights. It is not enough
    to offer a merely plausible construction in the anticipation that the
    legislature will override us if we mistake its intent.
    It may be that ―[s]tate courts and state legislatures function in
    dialogue with one another.‖ See infra ¶ 35. But in this dialogue
    and in this context, when the legislature speaks, we must listen.
    We cannot properly speak over the legislature‘s voice on this mat-
    ter. And though we may be free to ―call the attention of the legis-
    lature to statutes in need of clarification or modernization,‖ see
    infra ¶ 35, we should not force such changes on the legislature by
    judicial mandate.
    15 The dissent posits that equitable adoption may represent the
    wishes of some decedents and may not prolong all estate proceed-
    ings. See infra ¶¶ 47–48. But this hedging is significant; it ultimate-
    ly supports the conclusion that equitable adoption adds uncer-
    tainty and complexity to the intestacy scheme.
    15
    IN RE ESTATE OF WILLIAM J. HANNIFIN
    JUSTICE DURHAM, dissenting
    statute and common law principle butt heads, the common law
    must yield.
    III
    ¶33 We accordingly jettison the doctrine of equitable adoption
    as a vestige of a common-law friendly intestacy regime that has
    been overtaken by statute. Thus, we hold that the administration
    of Hannifin‘s estate is subject to the express terms of the Probate
    Code, including terms governing matters of distribution and rep-
    resentation. We reverse and remand for further proceedings con-
    sistent with this opinion.
    ——————
    JUSTICE DURHAM, dissenting:
    ¶34 I disagree with the majority‘s conclusion that it is ―impos-
    sible‖ to follow both the doctrine of equitable adoption and Utah‘s
    version of the Uniform Probate Code (Probate Code or Code). See
    supra ¶ 16.
    ¶35 State courts and state legislatures function in dialogue with
    one another and serve as checks on one another‘s power—
    alternately reinforcing, calling into question, and even reversing
    the other‘s law-making activities. In the words of one commenta-
    tor, we live in a ―world where common and statutory law are wo-
    ven together in a complex fabric.‖ David L. Shapiro, Continuity
    and Change in Statutory Interpretation, 
    67 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 921
    , 937
    (1992). When courts fill interstices in statutory law in a manner the
    legislature disapproves of, the legislature can amend the statute to
    direct a different outcome in future cases. See, e.g., Gressman v.
    State [forthcoming] (noting that in response to the district court‘s
    holding, the legislature amended the Post-Conviction Remedies
    Act to clarify that claims expire on the claimant‘s death). Similar-
    ly, the legislature can overrule or preempt common law doctrines
    by statute. See, e.g., Bishop v. GenTec Inc., 
    2002 UT 36
    , ¶ 12, 
    48 P.3d 218
     (holding that the Liability Reform Act preempted in part the
    common law doctrine of respondeat superior). Although courts
    cannot overrule statutory law on the basis of policy, they are re-
    sponsible for determining the constitutionality of challenged stat-
    utes. See, e.g., Gallivan v. Walker, 
    2002 UT 89
    , ¶¶ 64, 83, 
    54 P.3d 1069
     (holding that the multi-county signature requirement for ini-
    tiatives violated the uniform operation of laws clause and the fed-
    eral equal protection clause). Additionally, courts can call the at-
    16
    CITE AS: 
    2013 UT 46
    JUSTICE DURHAM, dissenting
    tention of the legislature to statutes in need of clarification or
    modernization. See, e.g., McArthur v. State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co.,
    
    2012 UT 22
    , ¶¶ 40–47, 
    274 P.3d 981
     (Durham, J., concurring) (urg-
    ing the legislature to revisit the uninsured motorist statute).1
    ¶36 Given the dynamic nature of the state law-making process,
    we assume, absent a contrary indication, that the legislature in-
    tends its statutes to work in tandem with our case law, and we
    reconcile the common law with statutory law whenever possible.
    See Olseth v. Larson, 
    2007 UT 29
    , ¶ 39, 
    158 P.3d 532
     (―We presume
    the Legislature is aware of our case law . . . .‖); see also Bishop, 
    2002 UT 36
    , ¶ 10 (―[T]he common law must necessarily give way‖ to
    statutory law only when the two are ―in conflict‖ or when the leg-
    islature intended to preempt the common law.). Conflict preemp-
    tion occurs only ―where it is impossible . . . to comply with both
    [the common law] and [statutory] requirements, or where [the
    common law] stands as an obstacle to the accomplishment and
    execution of the full purposes and objectives of [the legislature].‖
    Navajo Nation v. State (In re Adoption of A.B.), 
    2010 UT 55
    , ¶ 33, 
    245 P.3d 711
     (first alteration in original) (internal quotation marks
    omitted).
    ¶37 When the legislature enacted the Probate Code thirty-eight
    years ago, 
    1975 Utah Laws 579
    –715, it included the following sec-
    tion, which has not been amended: ―Unless displaced by the par-
    ticular provisions of this code, the principles of law and equity
    supplement its provisions,‖ UTAH CODE § 75-1-103. The legislature
    instructed the judiciary not to infer preemption just because the
    legislature had spoken on a subject. Rather, courts are to find
    preemption only where the Probate Code directly ―displace[s]‖ a
    common law doctrine. At the time the Code was enacted with this
    presumption against preemption, equitable adoption had been the
    law in Utah for fifteen years. In re Williams’ Estates, 
    348 P.2d 683
    (Utah 1960). Yet nothing in the original Probate Code or its subse-
    quent amendments either addresses or conflicts with equitable
    adoption.
    1 Evidentiary and procedural rule-making is another arena
    where the courts and the legislature interact, with the supreme
    court having primary authority and the legislature the power to
    amend rules. See UTAH CONST. art. 8, § 4.
    17
    IN RE ESTATE OF WILLIAM J. HANNIFIN
    JUSTICE DURHAM, dissenting
    I. THE PROBATE CODE‘S DEFINITIONS OF ―CHILD‖
    AND ―PARENT‖ DO NOT UNDERMINE THE
    DOCTRINE OF EQUITABLE ADOPTION
    ¶38 The majority seems to recognize that equitable adoption
    was valid as a common law doctrine before the Code was enacted.
    See supra ¶¶ 17, 24. In the majority‘s view, equitable adoption and
    the previous probate code could coexist because the previous
    probate code did not define the terms ―child‖ or ―parent.‖2 The
    majority holds that the Uniform Probate Code‘s definitions of
    ―child‖ and ―parent,‖ quoted above in paragraph 19, are preemp-
    tive. See supra ¶¶ 19–21.
    ¶39 Contrary to the majority‘s view, these definitions are not
    preemptive because the doctrine of equitable adoption is not
    premised on our ability to judicially define the statutory term
    ―child‖ or ―parent.‖ The version of the probate code in effect
    when Williams’ Estates was decided provided for intestate succes-
    sion by a decedent‘s ―child‖ or ―issue.‖ UTAH CODE § 74-4-5(1)–(2)
    (1953). We did not reach our holding in Williams’ Estates by judi-
    cially defining these statutory terms, as the majority suggests. See
    supra ¶ 20. Instead, we exercised our equitable power to hold that,
    even though the claimant was not a ―child‖ or ―issue‖ under the
    statute, justice required awarding her the same inheritance she
    would have received if she had been adopted. See In re Williams’
    Estates, 
    348 P.2d 683
    , 684 (Utah 1960). Nothing in the Uniform
    Probate Code definitions changes our ability to do that.3 Equitable
    adoption has always operated in parallel with the probate code,
    providing a non-statutory, equitable right to inherit as if the
    claimant were the child of the decedent. See 
    id.
    2  The majority refers to the previous version of the probate code
    as an ―open-ended system.‖ Supra ¶ 17. This characterization is
    surely exaggerated. The probate code in effect when Williams’ Es-
    tates was decided addressed intestate succession in as much detail
    as the Code provisions quoted in paragraph 18. Compare UTAH
    CODE § 75-2-103 (2013) with UTAH CODE § 74-4-5 (1953).
    3 Even if equitable adoption were a judicial method of interpret-
    ing the statutory term ―child,‖ it would be difficult to find
    preemptive intent in the Code‘s exclusion of foster children and
    grandchildren because Williams’ Estates did not involve these cat-
    egories of individuals.
    18
    CITE AS: 
    2013 UT 46
    JUSTICE DURHAM, dissenting
    ¶40 The majority further holds that equitable adoption conflicts
    with the Probate Code because it leads to a different distribution
    of estate assets than the intestacy provisions would otherwise dic-
    tate. 
    Supra ¶ 21
    . But supplemental legal and equitable principles—
    explicitly invited by the legislature in Utah Code section 75-1-
    103—almost always alter the outcomes of the cases to which they
    are applied. Otherwise, there would be no reason to apply them.
    Courts in Utah and other states that have adopted the Uniform
    Probate Code have supplemented it in several outcome-
    determinative ways. See Berneau v. Martino, 
    2009 UT 87
    , ¶ 10, 
    223 P.3d 1128
     (allowing the equitable discovery rule to toll the three-
    year statute of limitations required in the Probate Code); Morgan
    v. Zion First Nat’l Bank (In re Estate of Pepper), 
    711 P.2d 261
    , 263
    (Utah 1985) (holding that final closing orders in a probate pro-
    ceeding can be vacated through a rule 60(b) motion, despite the
    fact that section 75-3-1001 of the probate code ―discharges a per-
    sonal representative from further claim or demand after a final
    closing order has been entered‖); In re Estate of Butler, 
    444 So. 2d 477
    , 479 (Fla. Dist. Ct. App. 1984) (estopping the first wife of de-
    cedent from asserting her inheritance rights as against the dece-
    dent‘s second wife); In re Estate of Peter C., 
    488 A.2d 468
    , 470 (Me.
    1985) (holding that the common law rule that a guardian is in a
    fiduciary relationship to his ward was not abrogated by the adop-
    tion of the Uniform Probate Code even though the code does not
    shoulder guardians with fiduciary responsibilities); In re Estate of
    Foster, 
    699 P.2d 638
    , 645 (N.M. Ct. App. 1985) (applying the equi-
    table rule ―authoriz[ing] an award of attorney fees for services
    rendered which confer a benefit upon the estate‖); In re Estate of
    O’Keefe, 
    583 N.W.2d 138
    , 140 (S.D. 1998) (holding that the circuit
    court had the equitable authority to partially disqualify a benefi-
    ciary from inheriting from an estate because of his fraudulent
    acts); see also In re Estate of Wagley, 
    760 P.2d 316
    , 319-20 (Utah 1988)
    (holding that a claim of quantum meruit was appropriate in a
    probate case because under section 103, ―principles of law and
    equity supplement the provisions of the [Utah Uniform Probate
    Code] unless displaced by particular provisions of the Code‖).
    ¶41 More specifically, several states that have enacted the Uni-
    form Probate Code recognize equitable adoption. See, e.g., Calista
    Corp. v. Mann, 
    564 P.2d 53
    , 61 & n.18 (Alaska 1977) (holding that
    Alaska‘s version of Utah Code section 75-1-103 permitted the
    court to recognize equitable adoption); In re Estate of Jenkins, 
    904 P.2d 1316
    , 1320 (Colo. 1995) (en banc) (acknowledging that the
    state recognizes equitable adoption); Jolley v. Seamco Laboratories,
    19
    IN RE ESTATE OF WILLIAM J. HANNIFIN
    JUSTICE DURHAM, dissenting
    Inc., 
    828 So. 2d 1050
    , 1051 (Fla. Dist. Ct. App. 2002) (same); Johnson
    v. Johnson, 
    617 N.W.2d 97
    , 101 (N.D. 2000) (same). I am aware of
    no case in which a litigant has argued or a court has held that eq-
    uitable adoption is incompatible with the Uniform Probate Code.
    ¶42 Because the doctrine of equitable inheritance has never re-
    lied on the absence of a definition of ―child‖ or ―parent‖ in the
    probate code, and because equitable principles are almost always
    outcome-determinative where applied, I would hold that the Uni-
    form Probate Code‘s definitions of ―child‖ and ―parent‖ do not
    conflict with the doctrine of equitable adoption.
    II. THE PROBATE CODE‘S RULE THAT ADOPTED
    CHILDREN CANNOT INHERIT FROM THEIR BIOLOGICAL
    PARENTS IS IRRELEVANT TO THE DOCTRINE OF
    EQUITABLE ADOPTION
    ¶43 The majority also finds preemption based on the Probate
    Code‘s rule that ―for purposes of intestate succession . . . [a]n
    adopted individual is the child of the adopting parent . . . and not
    of the natural parents.‖ UTAH CODE § 75-2-114(1)-(2); see supra ¶¶
    22–27. The majority correctly states that claimants who inherit
    under the doctrine of equitable adoption could also inherit from
    their biological parents because ―the doctrine of equitable adop-
    tion . . . is purely beneficial to the child and in no way alters the
    legal relationship between the claimant and the decedent or be-
    tween the claimant and the biological parents.‖ Supra ¶ 22; see
    Tracy Bateman Farrell, Annotation, Modern Status of Law as to Eq-
    uitable Adoption or Adoption by Estoppel, 
    122 A.L.R.5th 205
    , § 2[a]
    (2004). I agree with this assessment. But the necessary implication
    of the ―purely beneficial‖ nature of equitable adoption is that
    Utah Code section 75-2-114(2) is irrelevant to our preemption in-
    quiry. In a case of equitable adoption, there is no ―adopted per-
    son‖ and no ―adopting parent.‖
    ¶44 The majority seems to have derived its own version of a
    fairness principle from this Code section that would prevent indi-
    viduals from inheriting both from their biological parents and
    from other adults who perform parental duties. However, the in-
    testacy statutes allow individuals to inherit from a wide range of
    relatives. The Probate Code does not contain a one-person-one-
    inheritance rule. Section 75-2-114 simply clarifies the effect of a
    20
    CITE AS: 
    2013 UT 46
    JUSTICE DURHAM, dissenting
    statutory adoption—which has no relation to the inaptly named
    doctrine of equitable adoption4—on intestate succession.
    III. THE STATED OBJECTIVES OF THE PROBATE CODE
    ARE NOT IN CONFLICT WITH THE DOCTRINE OF
    EQUITABLE ADOPTION
    ¶45 I disagree with the majority‘s emphatic conclusion that eq-
    uitable adoption frustrates the following ―underlying purposes
    and policies‖ of the Probate Code:
    (a) To simplify and clarify the law concerning the affairs of
    decedents, missing persons, protected persons, minors, and
    incapacitated persons;
    (b) To discover and make effective the intent of a decedent
    in distribution of his property;
    (c) To promote a speedy and efficient system for adminis-
    tering the estate of the decedent and making distribution to
    his successors; . . .
    (e) To make uniform the law among the various jurisdic-
    tions.
    UTAH CODE § 75-1-102(2).
    ¶46 The majority‘s strongest point is that equitable inheritance
    adds uncertainty to the determination of an intestate decedent‘s
    heirs, in frustration of objective (a). A claim of equitable adoption
    does indeed require a court to consider evidence for and against
    the claim. But any of the legal and equitable principles with which
    the legislature has invited courts to supplement the Probate Code
    could be viewed as adding ―uncertainty, complexity, and ineffi-
    ciency.‖ See supra ¶ 29. The legislature evidently is willing to tol-
    erate a degree of complication in furtherance of a just and equita-
    ble outcome.5
    4 The presence of the word ―adoption‖ in the phrase ―equitable
    adoption‖ falsely suggests a relationship between this doctrine
    and statutory adoption. I prefer the term ―equitable inheritance‖
    because it is more descriptive of the specific relief that ought to be
    available to claimants in limited circumstances and does not sug-
    gest itself as a basis for other rights and duties associated with
    adoption.
    5  As a side note, I do not share the majority‘s general skepticism
    of state common-law development. See supra ¶¶ 30–31. Incremen-
    21
    IN RE ESTATE OF WILLIAM J. HANNIFIN
    JUSTICE DURHAM, dissenting
    ¶47 The remaining objectives could be furthered or hindered by
    equitable adoption, depending on the circumstances of individual
    cases. As to objective (b), the majority notes that the ―presumptive
    preference‖ of a decedent who dies intestate is for assets to be dis-
    tributed according to the Probate Code. Supra ¶ 31. However, a
    decedent could also rely on the common law doctrine of equitable
    adoption found in Williams’ Estates, which has been binding law
    in Utah for over fifty years. Furthermore, in a case like the present
    one, a decedent would likely have preferred to leave his estate to
    an individual whom the decedent raised as his own child rather
    than to distant relatives with whom he might not have had any
    personal relationship.
    ¶48 As to objective (c), equitable adoption will likely prolong
    many but not all estate proceedings in which it is claimed. In this
    case, if the viability of the doctrine had not been challenged, it
    may have been speedier and more efficient to award the entire es-
    tate to Mr. Nakai than to trace the decedent‘s bloodlines to distant
    relatives, painstakingly calculate each relative‘s share, and dis-
    tribute the estate (including personal and real property) among
    nineteen individuals.
    ¶49 Regarding objective (e), the goal of uniformity would be
    furthered slightly more by retaining the doctrine of equitable
    adoption than by overruling it. Approximately half of the states
    recognize equitable adoption, but of the state courts to have di-
    rectly considered the doctrine, significantly more than half have
    adopted it. See Tracy Bateman Farrell, Annotation, Modern Status
    of Law as to Equitable Adoption or Adoption by Estoppel, 
    122 A.L.R.5th 205
     (2004). This trend suggests that equitable adoption will con-
    tinue to grow in acceptance.
    ¶50 Equitable adoption does not categorically frustrate the
    purposes of the Probate Code. Neither these stated objectives nor
    the other Code provisions analyzed above provide a basis for
    overruling the doctrine. Because no ―particular provisions‖ of the
    Probate Code have ―displaced‖ equitable adoption, see UTAH
    CODE § 75-1-103, I would allow the doctrine to continue to coexist
    with statutory law, as it has done for over fifty years. Given the
    majority‘s foreclosure of this outcome, however, I would encour-
    tal change through resolution of the questions posed by individu-
    al cases is the sine qua non of the common law. See Judith S. Kaye,
    State Courts at the Dawn of a New Century, 
    70 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1
    , 5
    (1995).
    22
    CITE AS: 
    2013 UT 46
    JUSTICE DURHAM, dissenting
    age the legislature to consider the policy arguments in favor of its
    specific inclusion in the Code.
    ——————
    23