PHH Corporation v. CFPB , 881 F.3d 75 ( 2018 )


Menu:
  •  United States Court of Appeals
    FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA CIRCUIT
    Argued May 24, 2017                 Decided January 31, 2018
    No. 15-1177
    PHH CORPORATION, ET AL.,
    PETITIONERS
    v.
    CONSUMER FINANCIAL PROTECTION BUREAU,
    RESPONDENT
    On Petition for Rehearing En Banc
    Theodore B. Olson argued the cause for petitioners. With
    him on the briefs were Helgi C. Walker, Lucas C. Townsend,
    Mitchel H. Kider, David M. Souders, Thomas M. Hefferon, and
    William M. Jay.
    Andrew J. Pincus, Stephen C.N. Lilley, Matthew A.
    Waring, Kate Comerford Todd, and Steven P. Lehotsky were
    on the brief for amicus curiae The Chamber of Commerce of
    the United States of America in support of petitioners.
    David K. Willingham, Michael D. Roth, Jeffrey M.
    Hammer, and Kelly L. Perigoe were on the brief for amici
    curiae RD Legal Funding, LLC, et al. in support of petitioners.
    2
    Joseph R. Palmore and Bryan J. Leitch were on the brief
    for amici curiae American Bankers Association, et al. in
    support of petitioners and vacatur.
    David T. Case and Phillip L. Schulman were on the brief
    for amicus curiae The National Association of Realtors7 in
    support of petitioners and reversal of the June 4, 2015 order of
    the Director of the Consumer Financial Protection Bureau.
    Jay N. Varon and Jennifer M. Keas were on the brief for
    amici curiae American Land Title Association, et al. in support
    of petitioners.
    Joshua D. Hawley, Attorney General, Office of the
    Attorney General for the State of Missouri, and D. John Sauer,
    State Solicitor, were on the brief for amici curiae the States of
    Missouri, et al. in support of petitioners.
    Kirk D. Jensen, Joseph M. Kolar, and Alexander S.
    Leonhardt were on the brief for amicus curiae The Consumer
    Mortgage Coalition in support of petitioner.
    Marc J. Gottridge, Allison M. Wuertz, Ilya Shapiro, and
    Thaya Brook Knight were on the brief for amicus curiae The
    Cato Institute in support of petitioners.
    Brian Melendez was on the brief for amicus curiae ACA
    International in support of petitioners.
    C. Boyden Gray, Adam R.F. Gustafson, James R. Conde,
    Gregory Jacob, Sam Kazman, and Hans Bader were on the
    brief for amici curiae State National Bank of Big Spring, et al.
    in support of petitioners.
    3
    Hashim M. Mooppan, Attorney, U.S. Department of
    Justice, argued the cause as amicus curiae United States of
    America. On the brief were Douglas N. Letter, Mark B. Stern,
    Daniel Tenny, and Tara S. Morrissey, Attorneys. Ian H.
    Gershengorn, Attorney, entered an appearance.
    Lawrence DeMille-Wagman, Senior Litigation Counsel,
    Consumer Financial Protection Bureau, argued the cause for
    respondent. With him on the brief was John R. Coleman,
    Deputy General Counsel.
    George Jepsen, Attorney General, Office of the Attorney
    General for the State of Connecticut, and John Langmaid,
    Assistant Attorney General, were on the brief for The States of
    Connecticut, et al. in support of respondent.
    Thomas C. Goldstein, Eric Citron, Tejinder Singh, and
    Deepak Gupta were on the brief for amici curiae Americans For
    Financial Reform, et al. in support of respondent.
    Elizabeth B. Wydra, Brianne J. Gorod, and Simon Lazarus
    were on the brief for amici curiae Current and Former Members
    of Congress in support of respondent.
    Scott L. Nelson and Allison M. Zieve were on the brief for
    amici curiae Public Citizen, Inc., et al. in support of respondent.
    Julie Nepveu was on the brief for amici curiae AARP and
    AARP Foundation in support of respondent.
    Deepak Gupta was on the brief for amici curiae Financial
    Regulation Scholars in support of respondent.
    4
    Katharine M. Mapes, Jessica R. Bell, and Jeffrey M. Bayne
    were on the brief for amici curiae Separation of Powers Scholars
    in support of Consumer Financial Protection Bureau.
    Before: GARLAND *, Chief Judge, HENDERSON, ROGERS,
    TATEL, BROWN ∗∗, GRIFFITH, KAVANAUGH, SRINIVASAN,
    MILLETT, PILLARD, WILKINS, and KATSAS *, Circuit Judges and
    RANDOLPH, Senior Circuit Judge.
    Opinion for the Court filed by Circuit Judge PILLARD.
    Concurring opinion filed by Circuit Judge TATEL, with
    whom Circuit Judges MILLETT and PILLARD join.
    Concurring opinion filed by Circuit Judge WILKINS, with
    whom Circuit Judge ROGERS joins.
    Opinion concurring in the judgment filed by Circuit Judge
    GRIFFITH.
    Dissenting opinion filed by Circuit Judge HENDERSON.
    Dissenting opinion filed by Circuit Judge KAVANAUGH,
    with whom Senior Circuit Judge RANDOLPH joins.
    Dissenting opinion filed by Senior Circuit Judge
    RANDOLPH.
    *
    Chief Judge Garland and Circuit Judge Katsas did not participate in
    this matter.
    ∗∗
    Circuit Judge Brown was a member of the en banc court but retired
    before issuance of this opinion.
    5
    PILLARD, Circuit Judge:
    We granted en banc review to consider whether the federal
    statute providing the Director of the Consumer Financial
    Protection Bureau (CFPB) with a five-year term in office,
    subject to removal by the President only for “inefficiency,
    neglect of duty, or malfeasance in office,” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (c)(3), is consistent with Article II of the Constitution,
    which vests executive power “in a President of the United
    States of America” charged to “take Care that the Laws be
    faithfully executed,” U.S. Const. art. II, § 1, cl. 1; id. § 3.
    Congress established the independent CFPB to curb fraud and
    promote transparency in consumer loans, home mortgages,
    personal credit cards, and retail banking. See 
    12 U.S.C. § 5481
    (12). The Supreme Court eighty years ago sustained the
    constitutionality of the independent Federal Trade
    Commission, a consumer-protection financial regulator with
    powers analogous to those of the CFPB. Humphrey’s Executor
    v. United States, 
    295 U.S. 602
     (1935). In doing so, the Court
    approved the very means of independence Congress used here:
    protection of agency leadership from at-will removal by the
    President. The Court has since reaffirmed and built on that
    precedent, and Congress has embraced and relied on it in
    designing independent agencies. We follow that precedent
    here to hold that the parallel provision of the Dodd-Frank Wall
    Street Reform and Consumer Protection Act shielding the
    Director of the CFPB from removal without cause is consistent
    with Article II.
    Introduction
    The 2008 financial crisis destabilized the economy and left
    millions of Americans economically devastated. Congress
    studied the causes of the recession to craft solutions; it
    determined that the financial services industry had pushed
    6
    consumers into unsustainable forms of debt and that federal
    regulators had failed to prevent mounting risks to the economy,
    in part because those regulators were overly responsive to the
    industry they purported to police. Congress saw a need for an
    agency to help restore public confidence in markets: a
    regulator attentive to individuals and families. So it established
    the Consumer Financial Protection Bureau.
    Congress’s solution was not so much to write new
    consumer protection laws, but to collect under one roof existing
    statutes and regulations and to give them a chance to work.
    Congress determined that, to prevent problems that had
    handicapped past regulators, the new agency needed a degree
    of independence. Congress gave the CFPB a single Director
    protected against removal by the President without cause. That
    design choice is challenged here as an unconstitutional
    impediment to the President’s power.
    To analyze the constitutionality of            the   CFPB’s
    independence, we ask two questions:
    First, is the means of independence permissible? The
    Supreme Court has long recognized that, as deployed to shield
    certain agencies, a degree of independence is fully consonant
    with the Constitution. The means of independence that
    Congress chose here is wholly ordinary: The Director may be
    fired only for “inefficiency, neglect of duty, or malfeasance in
    office,” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (c)(3)—the very same language the
    Supreme Court approved for the Federal Trade Commission
    (FTC) back in 1935. Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 619, 629-32
    ; see 
    15 U.S.C. § 41
    . The CFPB’s for-cause removal
    requirement thus leaves the President no less removal authority
    than the provision sustained in Humphrey’s Executor; neither
    PHH nor dissenters disagree. The mild constraint on removal
    of the CFPB Director contrasts with the cumbersome or
    7
    encroaching removal restrictions that the Supreme Court has
    invalidated as depriving the President of his Article II authority
    or otherwise upsetting the separation of powers. In Free
    Enterprise Fund v. Public Company Accounting Oversight
    Board, 
    561 U.S. 477
     (2010), the Court left in place ordinary
    for-cause protection at the Securities and Exchange
    Commission (SEC)—the same protection that shields the FTC,
    the CFPB, and other independent agencies—even as it
    invalidated an unusually restrictive second layer of for-cause
    protection of the SEC’s Public Company Accounting
    Oversight Board (PCAOB) as an interference with Article II.
    In its only other decisions invalidating removal restrictions, the
    Supreme Court disapproved of means of independence not at
    issue here, specifically, Congress’s assigning removal power to
    itself by requiring the advice and consent of the Senate in
    Myers v. United States, 
    272 U.S. 52
     (1926), and a joint
    resolution of Congress in Bowsher v. Synar, 
    478 U.S. 714
    (1986). The Supreme Court has never struck down a statute
    conferring the standard for-cause protection at issue here.
    Second, does “the nature of the function that Congress
    vested in” the agency call for that means of independence?
    Wiener v. United States, 
    357 U.S. 349
    , 353 (1958); see also
    Morrison v. Olson, 
    487 U.S. 654
    , 687, 691 n.30 (1988). The
    CFPB is a financial regulator that applies a set of preexisting
    statutes to financial services marketed “primarily for personal,
    family, or household purposes.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5481
    (5)(A); see
    also 
    id.
     §§ 5481(4), (6), (15). Congress has historically given
    a modicum of independence to financial regulators like the
    Federal Reserve, the FTC, and the Office of the Comptroller of
    the Currency. That independence shields the nation’s economy
    from manipulation or self-dealing by political incumbents and
    enables such agencies to pursue the general public interest in
    the nation’s longer-term economic stability and success, even
    where doing so might require action that is politically
    8
    unpopular in the short term. In Humphrey’s Executor, the
    Supreme Court unanimously sustained the requirement of
    cause to remove members of the FTC, a consumer protection
    agency with a broad mandate to prevent unfair methods of
    competition in commerce. The FTC, “charged with the
    enforcement of no policy except the policy of the law,”
    Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 624
    , could be independent
    consistent with the President’s duty to take care that the law be
    faithfully executed. The CFPB’s focus on the transparency and
    fairness of financial products geared toward individuals and
    families falls squarely within the types of functions granted
    independence in precedent and history. Neither PHH nor our
    dissenting colleagues have suggested otherwise.
    The ultimate purpose of our constitutional inquiry is to
    determine whether the means of independence, as deployed at
    the agency in question, impedes the President’s ability under
    Article II of the Constitution to “take Care that the Laws be
    faithfully executed.” U.S. Const. art. II, § 3. It is beyond
    question that “there are some ‘purely executive’ officials who
    must be removable by the President at will if he is to be able to
    accomplish his constitutional role.” Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 690
    .
    Nobody would suggest that Congress could make the Secretary
    of Defense or Secretary of State, for example, removable only
    for cause. At the same time, the Court has consistently
    affirmed the constitutionality of statutes “conferring good-
    cause tenure on the principal officers of certain independent
    agencies.” Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 493
    .
    The Supreme Court has distinguished those removal
    restrictions that are compatible with the President’s
    constitutionally assigned role from those that run afoul of
    Article II in the line of removal-power cases running from
    Myers, 
    272 U.S. 52
    , through Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. 602
    , Wiener, 
    357 U.S. 349
    , Bowsher, 
    478 U.S. 714
    , Morrison,
    9
    
    487 U.S. 654
    , and Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. 477
    . The
    Court has repeatedly held that “a ‘good cause’ removal
    standard” does not impermissibly burden the President’s
    Article II powers, where “a degree of independence from the
    Executive . . . is necessary to the proper functioning of the
    agency or official.” Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at
    691 n.30, 686-96;
    see Wiener, 
    357 U.S. at 356
    ; Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 631
    . Armed with the power to terminate such an
    “independent” official for cause, the President retains “ample
    authority to assure” that the official “is competently performing
    his or her statutory responsibilities.” Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 692
    .
    Petitioners in this case, PHH Corporation, PHH Mortgage
    Corporation, PHH Home Loans, LLC, Atrium Insurance
    Corporation, and Atrium Reinsurance Corporation
    (collectively, PHH), would have us cabin the Court’s
    acceptance of removal restrictions by casting Humphrey’s
    Executor as a narrow exception to a general prohibition on any
    removal restriction—an exception it views as permitting the
    multi-member FTC but not the sole-headed CFPB. The
    distinction is constitutionally required, PHH contends, because
    “multi-member commissions contain their own internal checks
    to avoid arbitrary decisionmaking.” Pet’rs’ Br. 23.
    PHH’s challenge is not narrow. It claims that independent
    agencies with a single leader are constitutionally defective
    while purporting to spare multi-member ones. But the
    constitutional distinction PHH proposes between the CFPB’s
    leadership structure and that of multi-member independent
    agencies is untenable. That distinction finds no footing in
    precedent, historical practice, constitutional principle, or the
    logic of presidential removal power. The relevance of “internal
    checks” as a substitute for at-will removal by the President is
    no part of the removal-power doctrine, which focuses on
    10
    executive control and accountability to the public, not the
    competing virtues of various internal agency design choices.
    Congress and the President have historically countenanced
    sole-headed financial regulatory bodies. And the Supreme
    Court has upheld Congress’s assignment of even unmistakably
    executive responsibilities—criminal investigation and
    prosecution—to a sole officer protected from removal at the
    President’s will. Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 686-96
    .
    Wide margins separate the validity of an independent
    CFPB from any unconstitutional effort to attenuate presidential
    control over core executive functions. The threat PHH’s
    challenge poses to the established validity of other independent
    agencies, meanwhile, is very real. PHH seeks no mere course
    correction; its theory, uncabined by any principled distinction
    between this case and Supreme Court precedent sustaining
    independent agencies, leads much further afield. Ultimately,
    PHH makes no secret of its wholesale attack on independent
    agencies—whether collectively or individually led—that, if
    accepted, would broadly transform modern government.
    Because we see no constitutional defect in Congress’s
    choice to bestow on the CFPB Director protection against
    removal except for “inefficiency, neglect of duty, or
    malfeasance in office,” we sustain it.
    Background
    The 2008 financial crisis cost millions of Americans their
    jobs, savings, and homes. The federal commission that
    Congress and the President chartered to investigate the
    recession found that, by 2011, “[a]bout four million families
    have lost their homes to foreclosure and another four and a half
    million have slipped into the foreclosure process or are
    seriously behind on their mortgage payments.” Financial
    Crisis Inquiry Commission, The Financial Crisis Inquiry
    11
    Report, at xv (2011). All told, “[n]early $11 trillion in
    household wealth has vanished, with retirement accounts and
    life savings swept away.” 
    Id.
     In Congress’s view, the 2008
    crash represented a failure of consumer protection. The
    housing bubble “was precipitated by the proliferation of poorly
    underwritten mortgages with abusive terms,” issued “with little
    or no regard for a borrower’s understanding of the terms of, or
    their ability to repay, the loans.” S. Rep. No. 111-176, at 11-
    12 (2010). Federal bank regulators had given short shrift to
    consumer protection as they focused (unsuccessfully) on the
    “safety and soundness” of the financial system and, post-crisis,
    on the survival of the biggest financial firms. Id. at 10.
    Congress concluded that this “failure by the prudential
    regulators to give sufficient consideration to consumer
    protection . . . helped bring the financial system down.” Id. at
    166.
    Congress responded to the crisis by including in the Dodd-
    Frank Wall Street Reform and Consumer Protection Act, Pub.
    L. 111-203, 
    124 Stat. 1376
     (July 21, 2010), a new regulator:
    the Consumer Financial Protection Bureau. Congress gave the
    new agency a focused mandate to improve transparency and
    competitiveness in the market for consumer financial products,
    consolidating authorities to protect household finance that had
    been previously scattered among separate agencies in order to
    end the “fragmentation of the current system” and “thereby
    ensur[e] accountability.” S. Rep. No. 111-176, at 11.
    The CFPB administers eighteen preexisting, familiar
    consumer-protection laws previously overseen by the Federal
    Reserve and six other federal agencies, virtually all of which
    were also independent. These laws seek to curb fraud and
    deceit and to promote transparency and best practices in
    consumer loans, home mortgages, personal credit cards, and
    retail banking. See 
    12 U.S.C. § 5481
    (12). The CFPB is
    12
    charged “to implement and, where applicable, enforce Federal
    consumer financial law consistently for the purpose of ensuring
    that all consumers have access to markets for consumer
    financial products and services” that “are fair, transparent, and
    competitive.” 
    Id.
     § 5511(a). Additionally, the CFPB has
    authority to prohibit any “unfair, deceptive, or abusive act or
    practice under Federal law in connection with any transaction
    with a consumer for a consumer financial product or service,
    or the offering of a consumer financial product or service.” Id.
    § 5531(a).
    To lead this new agency, Congress provided for a single
    Director to be appointed by the President and confirmed by the
    Senate. Id. §§ 5491(b)(1)-(2). Congress designed an agency
    with a single Director, rather than a multi-member body, to
    imbue the agency with the requisite initiative and decisiveness
    to do the job of monitoring and restraining abusive or
    excessively risky practices in the fast-changing world of
    consumer finance. See, e.g., S. Rep. No. 111-176, at 11. A
    single Director would also help the new agency become
    operational promptly, as it might have taken many years to
    confirm a full quorum of a multi-member body. See 155 Cong.
    Rec. 30,826-27 (Dec. 9, 2009) (statement of Rep. Waxman)
    (noting that a single director “can take early leadership in
    establishing the agency and getting it off the ground”).
    The Director serves a five-year term, with the potential of
    a holdover period pending confirmation of a successor. 1 12
    1
    Congressional inaction or delayed confirmation would not
    necessarily extend the period of for-cause protection. Oral Arg. Tr.
    48-49. Cf. Swan v. Clinton, 
    100 F.3d 973
    , 988 (D.C. Cir. 1996)
    (“[E]ven if the [National Credit Union Administration] statute were
    interpreted to grant removal protection to Board members during
    their appointed terms[,] . . . this protection does not extend to
    holdover members.”).
    
    13 U.S.C. §§ 5491
    (c)(1)-(2). The President may remove the
    Director “for inefficiency, neglect of duty, or malfeasance in
    office,” i.e., for cause. 
    Id.
     § 5491(c)(3). By providing the
    Director with a fixed term and for-cause protection, Congress
    sought to promote stability and confidence in the country’s
    financial system.
    Congress also determined “that the assurance of adequate
    funding, independent of the Congressional appropriations
    process, is absolutely essential to the independent operations of
    any financial regulator.” S. Rep. No. 111-176, at 163.
    Congress has provided similar independence to other financial
    regulators, like the Federal Reserve, the Federal Deposit
    Insurance Corporation, the Office of the Comptroller of the
    Currency, the National Credit Union Administration, and the
    Federal Housing Finance Agency, which all have complete,
    uncapped budgetary autonomy. See infra Part I.C.2. Congress
    authorized the CFPB to draw from a statutorily capped pool of
    funds in the Federal Reserve System rather than to charge
    industry fees or seek annual appropriations from Congress as
    do some other regulators. The Federal Reserve is required to
    transfer “the amount determined by the Director [of the CFPB]
    to be reasonably necessary to carry out the authorities of the
    Bureau,” up to twelve percent of the Federal Reserve’s total
    operating expenses. 
    12 U.S.C. §§ 5497
    (a)(1)-(2). If the
    Bureau requires funds beyond that capped allotment, it must
    seek them through congressional appropriation. 
    Id.
     § 5497(e).
    The Real Estate Settlement Procedures Act of 1974
    (RESPA) is one of the eighteen preexisting statutes the CFPB
    now administers. See 
    12 U.S.C. §§ 2601-2617
    . RESPA aims
    at, among other things, “the elimination of kickbacks or referral
    fees that tend to increase unnecessarily the costs of certain [real
    estate] settlement services.” 
    Id.
     § 2601(b)(2). To that end,
    RESPA’s Section 8(a) prohibits giving or accepting “any fee,
    14
    kickback, or thing of value pursuant to any agreement or
    understanding” to refer business involving a “real estate
    settlement service.” Id. § 2607(a). The term “thing of value”
    is “broadly defined” and includes “the opportunity to
    participate in a money-making program.”              
    12 C.F.R. § 1024.14
    (d). Another provision of RESPA, Section 8(c)(2),
    states that “[n]othing in this section shall be construed as
    prohibiting . . . the payment to any person of a bona fide salary
    or compensation or other payment for goods or facilities
    actually furnished or for services actually performed.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 2607
    (c).
    In this case, the CFPB Director interpreted those
    provisions of RESPA as applied to PHH’s mortgage insurance
    and reinsurance transactions. Mortgage insurance protects
    lenders in the event a borrower defaults on a mortgage loan.
    Mortgage lenders often require riskier borrowers to purchase
    such insurance as a condition of approving a loan. See
    Director’s Decision at 3. In turn, insurers may obtain
    reinsurance, transferring to the reinsurer some of their risk of
    loss in exchange for a portion of the borrower’s monthly
    insurance premiums. Borrowers do not ordinarily shop for
    mortgage insurance, let alone reinsurance; rather, they are
    referred to insurers of the lender’s choosing, to whom they then
    pay monthly premiums. See 
    id.
     During the period at issue, the
    only mortgage reinsurers in the market were “captive”—that is,
    they existed to reinsure loans originated by the mortgage
    lenders that owned them. See 
    id. at 13
    . In a captive reinsurance
    arrangement, a mortgage lender refers borrowers to a mortgage
    insurer, which then pays a kickback to the lender by using the
    lender’s captive reinsurer.
    On January 29, 2014, the CFPB filed a Notice of Charges
    against PHH, a large mortgage lender, and its captive reinsurer,
    Atrium. The CFPB alleged that “[t]he premiums ceded by
    15
    [mortgage insurers] to PHH through Atrium: (a) were not for
    services actually furnished or performed, or (b) grossly
    exceeded the value of any such services,” and that the
    premiums were instead “made in consideration of PHH’s
    continued referral of mortgage insurance business.” Notice of
    Charges at 17-18.
    The CFPB borrowed an administrative law judge (ALJ)
    from the Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC) to
    adjudicate the charges. The ALJ issued a Recommended
    Decision concluding that PHH and Atrium violated RESPA
    because they had not demonstrated that the reinsurance
    premiums Atrium collected from insurers were reasonably
    related to the value of its reinsurance services. The ALJ
    recommended that the Director order disgorgement of about
    $6.4 million. Director’s Decision at 9.
    On review of the ALJ’s recommendation, the CFPB
    Director read RESPA to support a broader finding of
    misconduct and a substantially larger remedy. The Director
    held that a payment is “bona fide” and thus permitted under
    Section 8(c)(2) only if it is “solely for the service actually being
    provided on its own merits,” and not “tied in any way to a
    referral of business.” Director’s Decision at 17. Thus, even if
    the reinsurance premiums had been reasonably related to the
    value of the reinsurance services that Atrium provided, PHH
    and Atrium could still be liable under the Director’s reading of
    RESPA insofar as their tying arrangement funneled valuable
    business to Atrium that it would not have garnered through
    open competition. The Director also held that RESPA’s three-
    year statute of limitations does not apply to the agency’s
    administrative enforcement proceedings (only to “actions” in
    court) and that RESPA violations accrue not at the moment a
    loan closes with a tying arrangement in place, but each time
    monthly premiums are paid out pursuant to such a loan
    16
    agreement. 
    Id. at 11, 22
    . Those interpretations raised the
    disgorgement amount to more than $109 million.
    This court stayed the Director’s order pending review. In
    October 2016, a three-judge panel vacated the Director’s
    decision and remanded for further proceedings. 
    839 F.3d 1
    , 10
    (D.C. Cir. 2016). A divided panel’s majority held that
    providing for-cause protection to the sole director of an
    independent agency violates the Constitution’s separation of
    powers. Severing the for-cause provision from the rest of the
    Dodd-Frank Act, the majority effectively turned the CFPB into
    an instrumentality of the President with a Director removable
    at will. See 
    id. at 12-39
    .
    The panel was unanimous, however, in overturning the
    Director’s interpretation of RESPA. It held that Section 8
    permits captive reinsurance arrangements so long as mortgage
    insurers pay no more than reasonable market value for
    reinsurance. See 839 F.3d at 41-44. And, even if the Director’s
    contrary interpretation (that RESPA prohibits tying
    arrangements) were permissible, the panel held, it was an
    unlawfully retroactive reversal of the federal government’s
    prior position. See id. at 44-49. Finally, according to the panel,
    a three-year statute of limitations applies to both administrative
    proceedings and civil actions enforcing RESPA. See id. at 50-
    55.
    Judge Henderson joined the panel’s opinion on the
    statutory questions but dissented from its constitutional holding
    on the ground that it was unnecessary in her view, and so
    inappropriate under the doctrine of avoidance, to reach the
    constitutional removal-power question. Id. at 56-60.
    The en banc court vacated the panel decision in its entirety.
    Following oral argument, the full court, including Judge
    Henderson, unanimously concluded that we cannot avoid the
    17
    constitutional question. That is because the disposition of
    PHH’s claims, reinstating the panel’s statutory holding, results
    in a remand to the CFPB. Further action by the CFPB
    necessitates a decision on the constitutionality of the Director’s
    for-cause removal protection. We accordingly decide only that
    constitutional question. The panel opinion, insofar as it related
    to the interpretation of RESPA and its application to PHH and
    Atrium in this case, is accordingly reinstated as the decision of
    the three-judge panel on those questions.
    We also decline to reach the separate question whether the
    ALJ who initially considered this case was appointed
    consistently with the Appointments Clause. Our order granting
    review invited the parties to address the Appointments Clause
    implications for this case only “[i]f the en banc court” in Lucia
    v. SEC, 
    832 F.3d 277
     (D.C. Cir. 2016), concluded that an SEC
    ALJ is an inferior officer rather than an employee. We did not
    so conclude. Instead, after argument in that case, the en banc
    court denied the petition for review. Lucia v. SEC, 
    868 F.3d 1021
     (D.C. Cir. 2017), cert. granted, __ S. Ct. __, 
    2018 WL 386565
     (Jan. 12, 2018).
    Today, we hold that federal law providing the Director of
    the CFPB with a five-year term in office, subject to removal by
    the President only for “inefficiency, neglect of duty, or
    malfeasance in office,” is consistent with the President’s
    constitutional authority.
    Analysis
    PHH challenges the removal protection of the Consumer
    Financial Protection Bureau’s Director, arguing that it
    unconstitutionally upsets the separation of powers. But the
    CFPB’s structure respects the powers and limits of each branch
    of government. Congress’s decision to establish an agency led
    by a Director removable only for cause is a valid exercise of its
    18
    Article I legislative power. The for-cause removal restriction
    fully comports with the President’s Article II executive
    authority and duty to take care that the consumer financial
    protection laws within the CFPB’s purview be faithfully
    executed. The panel’s grant of PHH’s due process claim
    illustrates how the exercise of legislative and executive powers
    to establish and empower the CFPB are backstopped by the
    Article III courts’ obligation to protect individual liberty when
    government overreaches.
    Our analysis focuses on whether Congress’s choice to
    include a for-cause removal provision impedes the President’s
    ability to fulfill his constitutional role. Two principal
    considerations inform our conclusion that it does not. First, the
    familiar for-cause protection at issue broadly allows the
    President to remove the Director for “inefficiency, neglect of
    duty, or malfeasance in office,” leaving the President ample
    tools to ensure the faithful execution of the laws. Second, the
    functions of the CFPB and its Director are not core executive
    functions, such as those entrusted to a Secretary of State or
    other Cabinet officer who we assume must directly answer to
    the President’s will. Rather, the CFPB is one of a number of
    federal financial regulators—including the Federal Trade
    Commission, the Federal Reserve, the Federal Deposit
    Insurance Corporation, and others—that have long been
    permissibly afforded a degree of independence. The CFPB
    matches what the Supreme Court’s removal-power cases have
    consistently approved. Accepting PHH’s claim to the contrary
    would put the historically established independence of
    financial regulators and numerous other independent agencies
    at risk.
    None of the theories advanced by PHH supports its claim
    that the CFPB is different in kind from the other independent
    agencies and, in particular, traditional independent financial
    19
    regulators. The CFPB’s authority is not of such character that
    removal protection of its Director necessarily interferes with
    the President’s Article II duty or prerogative. The CFPB is
    neither distinctive nor novel in any respect that calls its
    constitutionality into question. Because none of PHH’s
    challenges is grounded in constitutional precedent or principle,
    we uphold the agency’s structure.
    I. Precedent and History Establish                    the
    Constitutionality of the CFPB
    The Constitution makes no explicit provision for
    presidential removal of duly appointed officers, but the
    Supreme Court has long recognized that “the executive power
    include[s] a power to oversee executive officers through
    removal.” Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 492
    . The Court
    has found the removal power implied in aid of the executive
    power, which the Constitution vests “in a President of the
    United States of America” charged to “take Care that the Laws
    be faithfully executed.” U.S. Const. art. II, § 1, cl. 1; id. § 3.
    The Court’s decisions, from Myers to Free Enterprise Fund,
    also acknowledge the legitimacy, in appropriate circumstances,
    of an agency’s independence from the President’s removal of
    its leadership without cause. And history teaches that financial
    regulators are exemplars of appropriate and necessary
    independence.      Congress’s decision to afford removal
    protection to the CFPB Director puts the agency squarely
    within the bounds of that precedent and history, fully consonant
    with the Constitution.
    A. Precedent
    The Court has consistently upheld ordinary for-cause
    removal restrictions like the one at issue here, while
    invalidating only provisions that either give Congress some
    20
    role in the removal decision or otherwise make it abnormally
    difficult for the President to oversee an executive officer.
    In the first modern removal-power decision, Myers v.
    United States, the Court held that Congress could not condition
    presidential removal of certain postmasters on the Senate’s
    advice and consent, explaining that the President has “the
    exclusive power of removing executive officers of the United
    States whom he has appointed by and with the advice and
    consent of the Senate.” 
    272 U.S. at 106
    . Without interpreting
    the Take Care Clause as such, see Jack Goldsmith & John F.
    Manning, The Protean Take Care Clause, 164 U. Penn. L. Rev.
    1835, 1840-41 (2016), the Court in Myers appeared to assume
    the Clause dictated illimitable removal power in the President.
    PHH deploys that conception of illimitable removal power
    against the CFPB.
    But the Supreme Court since Myers has cabined that
    decision’s apparent reach, recognizing the constitutionality of
    some measure of independence for agencies with certain kinds
    of functions. The Court in Morrison, Wiener, and Humphrey’s
    Executor explicitly and repeatedly upheld for-cause removal
    restrictions in a range of contexts where the Constitution
    tolerates a degree of independence from presidential control.
    The Court’s latest removal-power decision, Free Enterprise
    Fund, applied the same analysis developed in those cases to
    strike an especially onerous set of removal restraints. The
    Court held that those double-layered restrictions, taken
    together, interfered with the President’s oversight of faithful
    execution of the securities laws, but it left in place the SEC
    Commissioners’ ordinary for-cause protection—the same
    protection at issue here.
    The Court’s removal-power doctrine supports Congress’s
    application of a modest removal restriction to the CFPB, a
    21
    financial regulator akin to the independent FTC in Humphrey’s
    Executor and the independent SEC in Free Enterprise Fund,
    with a sole head like the office of independent counsel in
    Morrison.
    It was only nine years after Myers, in Humphrey’s
    Executor, that the Court unanimously upheld a provision of the
    Federal Trade Commission Act protecting FTC
    Commissioners from removal except for “inefficiency, neglect
    of duty, or malfeasance in office.” 
    295 U.S. at 619, 632
    .
    Humphrey’s Executor explained that Myers was limited; it
    required only that the President be able to remove purely
    executive officers without congressional involvement. 
    Id. at 628
    . By contrast, where administrators of “quasi legislative or
    quasi judicial agencies” are concerned, the Constitution does
    not require that the President have “illimitable power” of
    removal. 
    Id. at 629
    . The Humphrey’s Executor Court drew
    guidance from the founding era, when James Madison
    (otherwise a strong proponent of the removal power) argued
    that an official who “partakes strongly of the judicial character
    . . . should not hold . . . office at the pleasure of the Executive
    branch of the Government.” 5 The Writings of James Madison
    413 (Hunt ed., 1904); see Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 631
    . Because Congress may require quasi-legislative and
    quasi-judicial administrators “to act in discharge of their duties
    independently of executive control,” it may “forbid their
    removal except for cause” during a fixed term in office. 
    Id. at 629
    .
    A generation later, an again-unanimous Court in Wiener v.
    United States, 
    357 U.S. at 352-55
    , per Justice Frankfurter,
    explicitly reaffirmed Humphrey’s Executor and held that
    neither the rationale supporting the President’s removal power
    nor the history of that power dating back to the First Congress
    required that the President always enjoy unconstrained
    22
    authority to remove leadership of every kind of agency at his
    will. Wiener concerned the War Claims Commission, which
    had been set up to compensate certain personal injuries and
    property losses at the hands of the enemy in World War II.
    Both President Eisenhower (in Wiener) and President
    Roosevelt (in Humphrey’s Executor) wanted the leaders of the
    respective agencies “to be their men,” removable at will, but in
    each case Congress had opted for and the Court sustained a
    modicum of independence. 
    Id. at 354
    .
    In Wiener, Justice Frankfurter expressly took into account
    the “thick chapter” of “political and judicial history” of
    controversy over the President’s removal power that the Court
    had canvassed at length in Myers. 
    357 U.S. at 351
    . The Wiener
    Court rejected President Eisenhower’s broad, categorical
    understanding of Myers as largely drawn from its dictum and—
    in light of Humphrey’s Executor—appropriately “short-lived.”
    
    Id. at 352
    . Commenting that “the versatility of circumstances
    often mocks a natural desire for definitiveness,” 
    id.,
     Wiener
    squarely denied that the President had a power of removal that
    Congress could not limit under any circumstance, “no matter
    the relation of the executive to the discharge of [the official’s]
    duties and no matter what restrictions Congress may have
    imposed regarding the nature of their tenure.” 
    Id.
     Rather, with
    attention to the sort of agency involved, Humphrey’s Executor
    had “narrowly confined the scope of the Myers decision” to
    purely executive officers, not members of quasi-judicial
    bodies. 
    Id.
    The Wiener Court identified “the most reliable factor” in
    deciding whether a removal restriction comported with the
    President’s constitutional authority to be “the nature of the
    function that Congress vested” in the agency. 
    Id. at 353
    ; see
    Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 631
     (“Whether the power of
    the President to remove an officer shall prevail[,] . . . precluding
    23
    a removal except for cause will depend upon the character of
    the office . . . .”). The Court distinguished core executive
    agents who must be fully responsive to the President’s
    preferences from those whose tasks call for a degree of
    independence “from Executive interference.” Wiener, 
    357 U.S. at 353
    . What mattered in Wiener was the “intrinsic
    judicial character of the task with which the [War Crimes]
    Commission was charged”: Congress had directed the
    Commission to “‘adjudicate according to law’ the classes of
    claims defined in the statute” entirely on their merits, free of
    personal or partisan pressures. 
    Id. at 355
    . That directive
    prevented the President from interfering at will with the
    leadership of the Commission. The legislation establishing the
    Commission made plain, even in the absence of an express for-
    cause removal provision, that “Congress did not wish to have
    hang over the Commission the Damocles’ sword of removal by
    the President for no reason other than that he preferred to have
    on that Commission men of his own choosing.” 
    Id. at 356
    .
    Though the Court in Humphrey’s Executor and Wiener
    thus emphasized the “quasi-legislative” and “quasi-judicial”
    character of the relevant offices, more recently the Court in
    Morrison v. Olson downplayed those particular
    characterizations of independent agencies while continuing to
    narrowly read Myers as disapproving “an attempt by Congress
    itself to gain a role in the removal of executive officials other
    than its established powers of impeachment and conviction.”
    
    487 U.S. at 686
    . Morrison posed more directly the question
    whether a removal restriction “interfere[d] with the President’s
    exercise of the ‘executive power’ and his constitutionally
    appointed duty to ‘take care that the laws be faithfully
    executed’ under Article II.” 
    Id. at 690
    . According to Morrison,
    the references in the earlier removal-power cases to the
    “character” of the relevant offices could best be understood as
    describing “the circumstances in which Congress might be
    24
    more inclined to find that a degree of independence from the
    Executive, such as that afforded by a ‘good cause’ removal
    standard, is necessary to the proper functioning of the agency
    or official” in fulfilling its duties. 
    Id.
     at 691 n.30. The Court
    explained that its decision in Humphrey’s Executor to sustain
    the independence that Congress thought appropriate for the
    FTC, with its “‘quasi-legislative’ or ‘quasi-judicial’” character,
    reflected the Court’s “judgment that it was not essential to the
    President’s proper execution of his Article II powers that [the
    FTC] be headed up by individuals who were removable at
    will.” Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 690-91
    .
    Morrison viewed as constitutionally relevant Congress’s
    determination that the role and character of a special
    independent prosecutor called for some autonomy from the
    President. Echoing Wiener, the Court in Morrison again
    rejected as “dicta” the “implication” drawn from Myers that the
    President’s removal power should in every circumstance be
    understood as “all-inclusive.” 
    Id. at 687
    . Instead, Morrison
    read Humphrey’s Executor and its progeny to allow Congress
    to provide limited removal protection for some administrative
    bodies, whose leadership Congress “intended to perform their
    duties ‘without executive leave and . . . free from executive
    control.’” Id. n.25 (alteration in original) (quoting Humphrey’s
    Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 628
    ). The Morrison Court evaluated the
    independent counsel’s for-cause protection accordingly.
    The independent counsel concededly performed functions
    that were traditionally “executive,” but Morrison pinpointed
    “the real question” as “whether the removal restrictions are of
    such a nature that they impede the President’s ability to
    perform his constitutional duty.” 
    Id. at 691
    . Analyzing “the
    functions of the officials in question . . . in that light,” 
    id.,
     the
    Court found the removal protection to be constitutional,
    recognizing it as “essential, in the view of Congress, to
    25
    establish the necessary independence of the office.” 
    Id. at 693
    .
    To be sure, the office of independent counsel was potent: It
    was empowered to prosecute high-ranking federal officials for
    violations of federal criminal law. Nevertheless, its removal
    protection did not unconstitutionally impinge on executive
    power. The Court “simply [did] not see how the President’s
    need to control the exercise of [the independent counsel’s]
    discretion is so central to the functioning of the Executive
    Branch as to require as a matter of constitutional law that the
    counsel be terminable at will by the President.” 
    Id. at 691-92
    .
    The Court noted that the President retained “ample authority”
    to review the independent counsel’s performance and that,
    because the independent counsel was removable by the
    Attorney General for good cause, the President’s removal
    power had not been “completely stripped.” 
    Id. at 692
    .
    The Supreme Court has thus recognized that Congress
    may value and deploy a degree of independence on the part of
    certain executive officials. At least so long as Congress does
    not disturb the constitutional balance by arrogating to itself a
    role in removing the relevant executive officials, see Bowsher,
    
    478 U.S. at 726
    ; Myers, 
    272 U.S. at 161
    , the Constitution
    admits of modest removal constraints where “the character of
    the office” supports making it somewhat “free of executive or
    political control,” Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 687
    , 691 n.30. The
    Court has sustained Congress’s determinations that removal
    restrictions were appropriate to protect the independence of
    heads of agencies devoted specifically to special prosecution in
    Morrison, claims adjudication in Wiener, and market
    competition and consumer protection in Humphrey’s Executor.
    Without questioning that there are certain agencies that
    Congress cannot make even modestly independent of the
    President, the Court accepted the removal restriction in each of
    those three cases as appropriate protection against the
    “‘coercive influence’ of the [at-will] removal power” that
    26
    otherwise “would ‘threaten the independence of the [agency].’”
    Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 690, 688
    ; see Wiener, 
    357 U.S. at 356
    ;
    Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 629-30
    .
    Invalidating a provision shifting removal power over the
    Comptroller General from the President to Congress, the
    Supreme Court in Bowsher v. Synar again insisted on a narrow
    reading of Myers—at odds with the reading PHH advances
    here. The Supreme Court treated Myers as holding only “that
    congressional participation in the removal of executive officers
    is unconstitutional.” 
    478 U.S. at 725
    . To have an executive
    officer “answerable only to Congress would, in practical terms,
    reserve in Congress control over the execution of the laws” in
    violation of the constitutional separation of powers. 
    Id. at 726
    .
    Setting aside the removal scheme before it, the Court in
    Bowsher made clear that Humphrey’s Executor and its progeny
    “involved an issue not presented either in the Myers case or in
    this case”—i.e., the constitutional validity of a statute leaving
    the removal power under the President’s control, but
    authorizing its exercise “only ‘for inefficiency, neglect of duty,
    or malfeasance in office.’” 
    Id. at 724-25
     (quoting Humphrey’s
    Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 628-29
    ). Bowsher thus acknowledged
    the constitutionality of for-cause limitation on the removal
    power when the President retains the power to find cause. The
    culprit violating the separation of powers in Bowsher was
    Congress’s aggrandizement of its own control over executive
    officers.
    The Supreme Court’s most recent removal-power
    decision, Free Enterprise Fund, invalidated a “highly unusual”
    removal restriction because it interfered with the President’s
    ability to “remove an officer . . . even if the President
    determines that the officer is neglecting his duties or
    discharging them improperly.” 
    561 U.S. at 484, 505
    . The
    problem was not congressional encroachment, but damage to
    27
    the President’s ability to supervise executive officers: “‘Even
    when a branch does not arrogate power to itself,’ . . . it must
    not ‘impair another in the performance of its constitutional
    duties.’” 
    Id. at 500
     (quoting Loving v. United States, 
    517 U.S. 748
    , 757 (1996)). “The President cannot ‘take Care that the
    Laws be faithfully executed’ if he cannot oversee the
    faithfulness of the officers who execute them.” 
    561 U.S. at 484
    . Free Enterprise Fund distinguishes ordinary for-cause
    requirements from abnormally constraining restrictions that
    impair the President’s constitutional oversight prerogative.
    At issue in Free Enterprise Fund was an extreme variation
    on the traditional good-cause removal standard: a provision of
    the Sarbanes-Oxley Act that afforded members of the Public
    Company Accounting Oversight Board, an agency within the
    Securities and Exchange Commission, unusually strong
    protection from removal. See 
    561 U.S. at 486
    . As in Morrison,
    the Court focused its inquiry on whether the President retains
    “power to oversee executive officers through removal.” 
    Id. at 492
    . The challenged provisions shielded the PCAOB with
    “two layers of for-cause [protection from] removal—including
    at one level a sharply circumscribed definition of what
    constitutes ‘good cause,’ and rigorous procedures that must be
    followed prior to removal.” 
    Id. at 505
    . It provided that
    PCAOB members could be removed only by a formal order of
    the SEC, and only “for good cause shown.” 
    Id. at 486-87, 505
    .
    But this was no garden-variety cause standard: It required a
    pre-removal finding, “on the record” and “after notice and
    opportunity for a hearing,” of a Board member’s willful
    violation of the Sarbanes-Oxley Act itself, the PCAOB’s own
    rules, or the securities laws, or willful abuse of Board member
    authority, or a lack of “reasonable justification or excuse” for
    failure to enforce compliance. 
    Id. at 486
    ; 
    15 U.S.C. § 7217
    (d)(3). On top of that, the SEC’s Commissioners—
    tasked with removing such delinquent Board members—were
    28
    themselves protected from presidential removal except for
    inefficiency, neglect of duty, or malfeasance in office. Free
    Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 487
    .
    The scheme challenged in Free Enterprise Fund was
    defective because the Court found that it “withdraws from the
    President any decision on whether good cause exists” and thus
    “impair[s]” the President’s “ability to execute the laws—by
    holding his subordinates accountable for their conduct.” 
    Id. at 495-96
    . The Court distinguished Humphrey’s Executor and
    Morrison as involving “only one level of protected tenure
    separat[ing] the President from an officer exercising executive
    power.” 
    Id. at 495
    . When Congress provides agency heads
    with for-cause protection against removal by the President, the
    Court held, it must define “cause” in such a way as to leave the
    President leeway to sufficiently “oversee” these heads to
    prevent misconduct. 
    Id. at 492-93
    . The problem with the
    PCAOB’s protection, then, was that the President did not retain
    that oversight. Specifically, “multilevel” for-cause protection
    rendered the President unable to “remove an officer . . . even if
    the President determines that the officer is neglecting his duties
    or discharging them improperly.” 
    Id. at 484
    . The Court’s
    solution to that problem was to retain one level of for-cause
    protection and remove the other. 
    Id. at 514
    . Thus, the Board
    members who serve under the SEC Commissioners may be
    removed by the Commissioners without cause, but the SEC
    Commissioners’ for-cause protection remains in place.
    The traditional for-cause protection enjoyed by the SEC
    Commissioners—and the officials in Morrison, Wiener, and
    Humphrey’s Executor—remains untouched by and
    constitutionally valid under Free Enterprise Fund. When an
    official is so protected, the President may not remove her or
    him for personal or partisan reasons, or for no reason at all.
    But, because such a cause requirement does not prevent
    29
    removal by reason of incompetence, neglect of duty, or
    malfeasance, it may apply without impairing the President’s
    ability to assure the faithful execution of the law. See
    Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 691-92
    ; Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 495-96
    .
    Free Enterprise Fund did not, contrary to PHH’s
    suggestion, narrow Humphrey’s Executor or give Myers newly
    expansive force. See Pet’rs’ Br. 21-22 & n.4. The Court’s
    “modest” point was “not to take issue with for-cause
    limitations in general,” but rather that the unprecedented
    restriction on the President’s ability to remove a member of the
    PCAOB hobbled his power to oversee executive officers. 
    561 U.S. at 501
    . As the Supreme Court had already made clear,
    “the only issue actually decided in Myers was that ‘the
    President had power to remove a postmaster of the first class,
    without the advice and consent of the Senate as required by act
    of Congress.’” Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at
    687 n.24 (quoting
    Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 626
    ); see Wiener, 
    357 U.S. at 351-52
    . Free Enterprise Fund, for its part, cites Myers only
    for general restatements of law, all of which are consistent with
    Morrison, Wiener, and Humphrey’s Executor. The opinion
    emphasizes, for example, that “[s]ince 1789, the Constitution
    has been understood to empower the President to keep
    [executive] officers accountable—by removing them from
    office, if necessary,” and quotes Myers for the accepted
    principle that “the President . . . must have some ‘power of
    removing those for whom he can not continue to be
    responsible.’” Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 483, 493
    (quoting Myers, 
    272 U.S. at 117
    ). At the same time, Free
    Enterprise Fund recognizes the functional values of those for-
    cause protections the Court has sustained as consistent with the
    President’s Take Care duty: An FTC “‘independent in
    character,’ [and] ‘free from political domination or control,’”
    in Humphrey’s Executor; “the necessary independence of the
    30
    office” of the independent counsel in Morrison; and “the
    rectitude” of officers administering a fund to compensate for
    war losses in Wiener. Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 502
    (quoting Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 619
    ; Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 693
    ; Wiener, 
    357 U.S. at 356
    ).
    Thus, the Court has upheld statutes that, like the
    challenged provision of the Dodd-Frank Act, “confer[] good-
    cause tenure on the principal officers of certain independent
    agencies.” Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 493
    . Decisions
    from Humphrey’s Executor to Free Enterprise Fund have
    approved standard for-cause removal restrictions where
    Congress deems them necessary for the effectiveness of certain
    types of agencies, provided that the President remains able to
    remove the agency heads for acting inefficiently, without good
    faith, or for neglecting their duties. The “real question” to ask,
    in considering such a statute, “is whether the removal
    restrictions are of such a nature that they impede the President’s
    ability to perform his constitutional duty,” taking account of
    the “functions of the officials in question.” Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 691
    . The question for us, then, is whether the requirement
    that the President have cause before removing a Director of the
    CFPB unconstitutionally interferes with the President’s Article
    II powers.
    B. History
    “The subject [of the President’s removal authority] was
    not discussed in the Constitutional Convention.” Myers, 
    272 U.S. at 109-10
     (1926). But there was a diversity of opinion on
    the subject at the founding, and early examples of
    heterogeneity in agency design bear that out. Financial
    regulation, in particular, has long been thought to be well
    served by a degree of independence.
    31
    Congressional alertness to the distinctive danger of
    political interference with financial affairs, dating to the
    founding era, began the longstanding tradition of affording
    some independence to the government’s financial functions.
    See Amicus Br. of Separation of Powers Scholars 4-10.
    Whereas the secretaries of the two other original departments
    (War and Foreign Affairs) were broadly chartered to “perform
    and execute such duties as shall from time to time be enjoined
    on or intrusted to [them] by the President of the United States,”
    Act of July 27, 1789, ch. 4, § 1, 
    1 Stat. 28
    , 29; Act of Aug. 7,
    1789, ch. 7, § 1, 
    1 Stat. 49
    , 50, Congress specified the
    responsibilities of the Treasury Secretary and other officers in
    the Treasury Department in some detail, see Act of Sept. 2,
    1789, ch. 12, §§ 2-6, 
    1 Stat. 65
    , 65-67. See Gerhard Casper, An
    Essay in Separation of Powers: Some Early Versions and
    Practices, 
    30 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 211
    , 241 (1989) (noting
    that, under the statutes of 1789 establishing the three “great
    departments” of government, “[o]nly the departments of State
    and War were completely ‘executive’ in nature”).
    The Comptroller of the Treasury, notably, was charged
    with “direct[ing] prosecutions for all delinquencies of officers
    of the revenue; and for debts that are, or shall be due to the
    United States,” 
    id.
     at § 3, 1 Stat. at 66, and his decisions were
    deemed “final and conclusive,” Act of Mar. 3, 1795, § 4, 
    1 Stat. 443
    , 443. He could be removed if found to “offend against any
    of the prohibitions of this act.” 1 Stat. at 67. It is unclear
    whether the Comptroller was also thought to be removable by
    the President for other reasons, but James Madison, who was
    generally opposed to removal protections, said he believed
    “there may be strong reasons why an officer of this kind should
    not hold his office at the pleasure of the Executive branch of
    the Government.” 1 Annals of Cong. 612 (1789). The nature
    of the Comptroller’s office and independence eventually
    changed, but it is evident that the Comptroller was, from
    32
    inception, meant to exercise an unusual degree of independent
    judgment. See Lawrence Lessig, Readings by Our Unitary
    Executive, 
    15 Cardozo L. Rev. 175
    , 184 (1993) (explaining that
    the President had “no directory control over the Comptroller
    General” and that “the Framers and the early congresses treated
    this independence as flowing from the nature of the
    Comptroller’s duties”); Charles Tiefer, The Constitutionality of
    Independent Officers as Checks on Abuses of Executive Power,
    
    63 B.U. L. Rev. 59
    , 73-75 (1983) (explaining that the
    Comptroller was “clearly . . . expected to exercise independent
    judgment”).
    At the dawn of the modern-day federal banking system,
    Congress continued to afford some independence to financial
    regulators as it set up the Office of the Comptroller of the
    Currency. See Nat’l Bank Act of 1863, 
    12 Stat. 665
    , 665-66
    (1863); Nat’l Bank Act of 1864, 
    13 Stat. 99
     (1864). Since the
    office’s inception, the Comptroller of the Currency has been
    removable only if the President sends the Senate “reasons” for
    removing him. 
    12 U.S.C. § 2
    . Whatever the type of reason it
    requires, the statute without question constrains the
    presidential removal power. The U.S. Code accordingly
    classifies the Comptroller of the Currency as an “independent
    regulatory agency” along with all the other removal-
    constrained independent agencies. 
    44 U.S.C. § 3502
    (5); see
    also 
    12 U.S.C. § 1
    (b)(1) (prohibiting the Treasury Secretary
    from interfering with the Comptroller); 
    2 Op. O.L.C. 129
    (1978) (concluding that the Comptroller has independent
    litigation authority).
    The independence of financial regulators remains a
    prominent pattern today. The Federal Reserve Board is led by
    governors who can be removed only for cause during their
    fourteen-year terms. 
    12 U.S.C. § 242
    . The reason is simple:
    The Federal Reserve must “provide for the sound, effective,
    33
    and uninterrupted operation of the banking system,” and
    Congress found that a degree of independence was needed to
    “increase the ability of the banking system to promote
    stability.” H.R. Rep. No. 74-742, at 1 (1935). By insulating
    the Board from presidential control and political pressures,
    Congress sought to ensure that the Federal Reserve would
    “reflect, not the opinion of a majority of special interests, but
    rather the well considered judgment of a body that takes into
    consideration all phases of national economic life.” 
    Id. at 6
    .
    The Federal Trade Commission stands as another example
    of an independent financial regulator in the modern era—one
    expressly approved by the Supreme Court. When the FTC was
    created, the Senate Committee Report described the need for
    independence as ensuring “a continuous policy . . . free from
    the effect of . . . changing incumbency” in the White House.
    51 Cong. Rec. 10,376 (1914). Congress reasoned that, as the
    country passed “through a depression,” a new consumer
    protection agency with a degree of independence would “give
    reassurance rather than create doubt.” Id.; see also 
    id.
     (“The
    powers [of the FTC] must be large, but the exercise of the
    powers will not be against honest business, but will be
    persuasive and correctional . . . .”). In Humphrey’s Executor,
    the Supreme Court expressly approved of Congress’s choice to
    insulate this new consumer protection agency via a for-cause
    removal provision. 
    295 U.S. at 619, 632
    .
    These examples typify other federal financial regulators,
    such as the Commodity Futures Trading Commission, the
    Federal Deposit Insurance Corporation, the Federal Housing
    Finance Authority, the National Credit Union Administration,
    and the Securities and Exchange Commission, which are
    considered independent whether or not for-cause removal
    protection is specified by statute. See Henry B. Hogue et al.,
    Cong. Research Serv., R43391, Independence of Federal
    34
    Financial Regulators: Structure, Funding, and Other Issues 1,
    15 (2017).      This makes sense because Congress has
    consistently deemed “[i]nsulation from political concerns” to
    be “advantageous in cases where it is desirable for agencies to
    make decisions that are unpopular in the short run but
    beneficial in the long run,” such as, for example, “the Fed’s
    monetary policy decisions.” 
    Id.
     at 5 n.16. History and
    tradition, as well as precedent, show that Congress may
    appropriately give some limited independence to certain
    financial regulators.
    C. Application to the CFPB
    The for-cause protection shielding the CFPB’s sole
    Director is fully compatible with the President’s constitutional
    authority.
    Congress validly decided that the CFPB needed a measure
    of independence and chose a constitutionally acceptable means
    to protect it. First, the removal restriction here is wholly
    ordinary—the verbatim protection approved by the Supreme
    Court back in 1935 in Humphrey’s Executor and reaffirmed
    ever since. The provision here neither adds layers of protection
    nor arrogates to Congress any role in removing an errant
    official. Second, the CFPB Director’s autonomy is consistent
    with a longstanding tradition of independence for financial
    regulators, and squarely supported by established precedent.
    The CFPB’s budgetary independence, too, is traditional among
    financial regulators, including in combination with typical
    removal constraints. PHH’s constitutional challenge flies in
    the face of the Supreme Court’s removal-power cases, and calls
    into question the structure of a host of independent agencies
    that make up the fabric of the administrative state.
    35
    There is nothing constitutionally suspect about the CFPB’s
    leadership structure. Morrison and Humphrey’s Executor
    stand in the way of any holding to the contrary. And there is
    no reason to assume an agency headed by an individual will be
    less responsive to presidential supervision than one headed by
    a group. It is surely more difficult to fire and replace several
    people than one. And, if anything, the Bureau’s consolidation
    of regulatory authority that had been shared among many
    separate independent agencies allows the President more
    efficiently to oversee the faithful execution of consumer
    protection laws. Decisional responsibility is clear now that
    there is one, publicly identifiable face of the CFPB who stands
    to account—to the President, the Congress, and the people—
    for all its consumer protection actions. The fact that the
    Director stands alone atop the agency means he cannot avoid
    scrutiny through finger-pointing, buck-passing, or sheer
    anonymity. What is more, in choosing a replacement, the
    President is unhampered by partisan balance or ex-officio
    requirements; the successor replaces the agency’s leadership
    wholesale. Nothing about the CFPB stands out to give us pause
    that it—distinct from other financial regulators or independent
    agencies more generally—is constitutionally defective.
    1. For-Cause Removal
    Applying the Court’s precedents to this case, we begin by
    observing that the CFPB Director is protected by the very same
    standard, in the very same words—“inefficiency, neglect of
    duty, or malfeasance in office”—as the Supreme Court
    sustained in Humphrey’s Executor. Compare 
    15 U.S.C. § 41
    ,
    with 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (c)(3). Again, the challenged statute
    imposes no additional layer of particularly onerous protection,
    per Free Enterprise Fund, nor indeed any other restriction on
    removal. And Congress has not given itself authority to
    participate in the President’s removal decision, which was fatal
    36
    to the removal mechanisms in Myers and Bowsher. The
    CFPB’s for-cause protection is therefore unlike any removal
    restriction that the Court has ever invalidated as impermissibly
    restricting executive authority. In every case reviewing a
    congressional decision to afford an agency ordinary for-cause
    protection, the Court has sustained Congress’s decision,
    reflecting the settled role that independent agencies have
    historically played in our government’s structure. See
    Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 688
    ; Wiener, 
    357 U.S. at 356
    ;
    Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 629-30
    ; see also Free
    Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 509
     (leaving in place “a single
    level of good-cause tenure” for SEC Commissioners); 
    id. at 510
     (suggesting that Congress might choose to make PCAOB
    members removable directly by the President “for good
    cause”).
    In analyzing where Congress may deploy such for-cause
    protection, the Supreme Court looks to “the character of the
    office” and the “proper functioning of the agency or official.”
    Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 687
    , 691 n.30; see Wiener, 
    357 U.S. at 353
     (emphasizing the “nature of the function” of the agency);
    Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 631
     (pointing to the
    “character of the office”). As seen through that lens, the
    CFPB’s function is remarkably similar to that of the FTC, a
    consumer protection agency that has operated for more than a
    century with the identical for-cause protection, approved by a
    unanimous Supreme Court. Compare 
    12 U.S.C. §§ 5511-12
    ,
    5532, 5534, 5562-64, with Federal Trade Commission Act of
    1914, 
    15 U.S.C. §§ 45-46
    ; see Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. 477
    ; Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. 602
    .
    Indeed, the independence of financial regulators—
    chronicled above, see supra Part I.B—is so well established by
    tradition and precedent that courts have assumed these
    agencies’ heads have removal protection even in the absence
    37
    of clear statutory text so directing. See Free Enterprise Fund,
    
    561 U.S. at 487
     (treating SEC Commissioners as removable
    only for cause). It has long been “generally accepted that the
    President may remove a[n SEC] commissioner [only] for
    inefficiency, neglect of duty, or malfeasance in office.” SEC v.
    Bilzerian, 
    750 F. Supp. 14
    , 16 (D.D.C. 1990) (citing SEC v.
    Blinder, Robinson & Co., Inc., 
    855 F.2d 677
    , 681 (10th Cir.
    1988), and H. Rep. No. 2070, 86th Cong., 2d Sess. 14 (1960)).
    And in Swan v. Clinton, for example, this court assumed that
    board members of the National Credit Union Association have
    removal protection because “people will likely have greater
    confidence in financial institutions if they believe that the
    regulation of these institutions is immune from political
    influence.” 
    100 F.3d 973
    , 983 (D.C. Cir. 1996).
    PHH’s attempt to single out the CFPB from other financial
    regulators, including the FTC, is unpersuasive. PHH asserts
    that, when the Court decided Humphrey’s Executor, the FTC
    “had no substantive rulemaking powers” and “could not order
    ‘retrospective’ remedies.” Pet’rs’ Reply Br. 6. But the FTC at
    that time did have broad powers to interpret and enforce the
    law. See generally, e.g., Federal Trade Comm’n v. Western
    Meat Co., 
    272 U.S. 554
     (1926). Moreover, many independent
    agencies (including the FTC) now exercise rulemaking and
    remedial powers like those of the CFPB. See Nat’l Petroleum
    Refiners Ass’n v. FTC, 
    482 F.2d 672
    , 698 (D.C. Cir. 1973)
    (holding that the Federal Trade Commission Act conferred
    substantive rulemaking powers); Magnuson-Moss Warranty-
    Federal Trade Commission Improvement Act, Pub. L. No. 93-
    637, § 205(a), 
    88 Stat. 2183
    , 2200-01 (1975) (codified as
    amended at 
    15 U.S.C. § 45
    (m)(1)(A)) (authorizing FTC to
    “commence a civil action to recover a civil penalty in a district
    court of the United States”).
    38
    Apart from the panel of this court whose decision we
    vacated, courts have uniformly understood Humphrey’s
    Executor to support the constitutionality of for-cause removal
    protection for the current FTC and certain other agencies with
    rulemaking and enforcement powers. See Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at
    692 & n.31 (noting that the FTC and other independent
    agencies “exercise civil enforcement powers”). Well before
    the Supreme Court in Free Enterprise Fund assumed the
    unchallenged constitutionality of SEC Commissioners’ for-
    cause protection, for instance, the Tenth Circuit sustained it,
    observing that Humphrey’s Executor “stands generally for the
    proposition that Congress may, without violating Article II,
    authorize an independent agency to bring civil law enforcement
    actions where the President’s removal power was restricted.”
    Blinder, Robinson, & Co., 
    855 F.2d at 682
    . And, in FEC v.
    NRA Political Victory Fund, this court noted that Humphrey’s
    Executor and Morrison confirmed the constitutionality of the
    Federal Election Commission, which is “patterned on the
    classic independent regulatory agency” and can both make
    rules and order retrospective remedies. 
    6 F.3d 821
    , 826 (D.C.
    Cir. 1993); see also 
    52 U.S.C. §§ 30107
    (a)(8), 30109 (setting
    out the FEC’s enforcement power).
    PHH asks us to cast aside the CFPB’s pedigree in Supreme
    Court precedent upholding this very type of independence and
    its lineage in historical practice regarding financial regulators.
    PHH focuses instead on dicta in Myers that speak of executive
    removal power as seemingly “illimitable.” Humphrey’s
    Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 627-28
    . Within less than a decade,
    however, the Supreme Court unanimously rejected that dicta in
    Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 628-29
    , and unanimously
    did so again in Wiener, 
    357 U.S. at 351-52
    . In the ensuing
    decades, while it has cited Myers’s unexceptional holding
    prohibiting congressional involvement in removal of executive
    officials, the Court has continued to disavow the broad dicta on
    39
    which PHH principally relies. See, e.g, Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 686-87
    ; see also Bowsher, 
    478 U.S. at 724-25
    ; Free Enterprise
    Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 483, 493, 502
    . Law and history put the
    CFPB, led by a Director shielded from removal without cause,
    on safe ground.
    2. Budgetary Independence
    Congress’s commitment to independence for financial
    regulators is also reflected in the CFPB’s budgetary set-up.
    PHH and some of its amici protest Congress’s choice to allow
    the CFPB to claim funds from the Federal Reserve rather than
    through the congressional appropriations process. See Pet’rs’
    Br. 26-28; Amicus Br. of Chamber of Commerce 8-9. But
    Congress can, consistent with the Appropriations Clause,
    create governmental institutions reliant on fees, assessments,
    or investments rather than the ordinary appropriations process.
    See Am. Fed’n of Gov’t Emps., AFL-CIO, Local 1647 v. Fed.
    Labor Relations Auth., 
    388 F.3d 405
    , 409 (3d Cir. 2004).
    Using that authority, Congress has consistently exempted
    financial regulators from appropriations: The Federal Reserve,
    the Federal Deposit Insurance Corporation, the Office of the
    Comptroller of the Currency, the National Credit Union
    Administration, and the Federal Housing Finance Agency all
    have complete, uncapped budgetary autonomy. See, e.g., 
    12 U.S.C. § 243
     (Federal Reserve); see also Hogue, Independence
    of Federal Financial Regulators, at 26-27.
    The way the CFPB is funded fits within the tradition of
    independent financial regulators. The Bureau draws a
    statutorily capped amount from the Federal Reserve, which
    formerly administered many of the consumer-protection laws
    now largely under the CFPB’s purview. See Identification of
    Enforceable Rules and Orders, 
    76 Fed. Reg. 43,569
    -01,
    43,570-71 (July 21, 2011). That feature aims to help the CFPB
    40
    to avoid agency capture that Congress believed had beset the
    agencies that previously administered the CFPB’s statutes, in
    part because those agencies depended on industry fees. See
    Rachel E. Barkow, Insulating Agencies: Avoiding Capture
    Through Institutional Design, 
    89 Tex. L. Rev. 15
    , 44-45
    (2010); Oren Bar-Gill & Elizabeth Warren, Making Credit
    Safer, 
    157 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1
    , 93 (2008).
    The CFPB’s independent funding source has no
    constitutionally salient effect on the President’s power. The
    Supreme Court has recently dismissed issues including “who
    controls the agency’s budget requests and funding” as
    “bureaucratic minutiae”—questions of institutional design
    outside the ambit of the separation-of-powers inquiry. Free
    Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 499-500
    . The fact that “the
    director need not ask the President for help negotiating
    appropriations from Congress,” Pet’rs’ Br. 27, is neither
    distinctive nor impermissible. Just as financial regulators
    ordinarily are independent of the congressional appropriations
    process, so, too, they typically are exempt from presidential
    budgetary oversight. See, e.g., 
    12 U.S.C. § 250
    . That ensures
    the measure of permissible independence instituted by for-
    cause protection is not effectively eroded by virtue of
    budgetary dependence on the President. The requirement that
    the CFPB seek congressional approval for funding beyond the
    statutory cap makes it more constrained in this regard than
    other financial regulators.
    PHH suggests that, even if budgetary independence and
    for-cause removal protection are not separately
    unconstitutional, their combination might be. See Pet’rs’ Br.
    28 (citing Ass’n of Am. R.Rs. v. U.S. Dep’t of Transp., 
    721 F.3d 666
    , 673 (D.C. Cir. 2013), vacated on other grounds, 
    135 S. Ct. 1225
     (2015)). But that combination is not novel. See, e.g.,
    
    12 U.S.C. § 243
     (Federal Reserve’s budgetary independence);
    41
    
    id.
     § 242 (Federal Reserve’s for-cause removal protection); id.
    § 16 (Office of the Comptroller of the Currency’s budgetary
    independence); id. § 2 (Office of the Comptroller of the
    Currency’s removal protection). And, in any event, for two
    unproblematic structural features to become problematic in
    combination, they would have to affect the same constitutional
    concern and amplify each other in a constitutionally relevant
    way. Thus, as we have noted, “Free Enterprise Fund deemed
    invalid a regime blending two limitations on the President’s
    removal power.” Ass’n of Am. R.Rs., 721 F.3d at 673. No
    similar amplification is present here. The CFPB’s budgetary
    independence primarily affects Congress, which has the power
    of the purse; it does not intensify any effect on the President of
    the removal constraint.
    The CFPB thus fits comfortably within precedent and
    tradition supporting the independence of the financial
    regulators that safeguard the economy. Whether it is
    considered alone or in combination with the independent
    funding provision, the requirement that the CFPB Director be
    removed only for cause does not unconstitutionally constrain
    the President.
    3. Multi-Member vs. Single-Director
    We are nevertheless urged that the constitutionality of for-
    cause removal turns on a single feature of the agency’s design:
    whether it is led by an individual or a group. But this line of
    attack finds no home in constitutional law.
    To begin with, that contention flies in the face of
    Morrison, which, contrary to PHH’s suggestions, remains valid
    and binding precedent. Morrison upheld the constitutionality
    of for-cause removal protection for an individual agency head
    who exercised substantial executive authority. The fact that the
    independent counsel was a solo actor played no role in either
    42
    the Court’s decision for an eight-member majority or Justice
    Scalia’s dissent; neither saw that fact as a ground of distinction
    from the multi-member agencies sustained in Humphrey’s
    Executor and Wiener. 2
    PHH’s emphasis on the CFPB’s leadership by a Director
    rather than a board defies historical practice as well. The
    Comptroller of the Currency, for example—an independent
    federal financial regulator with statutory removal protection
    dating back 150 years—is also headed by a single director,
    2
    The independent counsel’s inferior-officer status is not ground for
    distinguishing Morrison from this case. The Appointments Clause
    separately identifies the permissible appointing mechanisms for principal
    and inferior officers, U.S. Const. art. II, § 2, cl. 2, because of such officers’
    differing routes of accountability to the President: Principal officers are
    directly accountable, while inferior officers are indirectly accountable
    through the principal officer to whom they report. While that distinction is
    constitutionally relevant to the President’s appointments power, it is not
    determinative of the removal-power question. That is because the removal
    inquiry asks not whether an official exercises significant governmental
    authority, but whether a measure of independence in the exercise of such
    power interferes with the President’s constitutional duty and prerogative to
    oversee the executive branch and take care that the laws are faithfully
    executed. The degree of removal constraint effected by a single layer of
    for-cause protection is the same whether that protection shields a principal
    or inferior officer. In either case, the President—or a principal officer acting
    as the President’s agent—may not fire the independent officer except for
    cause. Indeed, the objective of the independent counsel statute was to
    protect the counsel’s independence, not only from the President’s direct
    interference, but also from interference by the President’s agent, the
    Attorney General.          The question whether a removal restriction
    unconstitutionally constrains presidential power thus does not track whether
    the shielded official is a principal or inferior officer. Even the mildest
    degree of removal protection of certain subordinate officers—such as the
    Secretary of the Navy or the Chief of Staff to the Secretary of State—could
    pose a constitutional problem, whereas Supreme Court precedent treats
    ordinary for-cause protection of some principal officers, such as members
    of the Federal Trade Commission or the SEC, to be permissible.
    43
    insulated from removal. See 
    12 U.S.C. § 2
    . Other historical
    examples of sole-headed independent agencies similarly
    counter PHH’s claim. See supra Part I.B; H.R. Conf. Rep. No.
    103-670, at 89-90 (1994) (explaining that sole administrator of
    Social Security Administration would enhance “management
    efficiency” and reduce “inappropriate influence”). Historical
    practice of independent agencies, including the earliest
    examples of independent financial regulators which operated
    under single heads, suffices to place the CFPB on solid footing.
    Fundamentally, Congress’s choice—whether an agency
    should be led by an individual or a group—is not
    constitutionally scripted and has not played any role in the
    Court’s removal-power doctrine. As discussed above, the
    cases focus on “whether the removal restrictions are of such a
    nature that they impede the President’s ability to perform his
    constitutional duty,” Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 691
    , or, put
    otherwise, whether the President’s “ability to execute the
    laws—by holding his subordinates accountable for their
    conduct—is impaired,” Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 496
    .
    Preserving lines of accountability within the executive branch
    ensures that the public can “determine on whom the blame or
    the punishment of a pernicious measure, or series of pernicious
    measures ought really to fall.” The Federalist No. 70, at 476
    (Alexander Hamilton) (J. Cooke ed. 1961). On this measure,
    the constitutionality of the CFPB’s structure is unaffected by
    the fact that it is led by a single Director.
    As a practical matter, considering the impact on
    presidential power, the line of accountability at the CFPB is at
    least as clear to the observing public as at multi-headed
    independent agencies, and the President’s control over the
    CFPB Director is at least as direct. PHH has not identified any
    reason to think that a single-director independent agency is any
    less responsive than one led by multiple commissioners or
    44
    board members. If anything, the President’s for-cause removal
    prerogative may allow more efficient control over a solo head
    than a multi-member directorate. Consider the case of
    Humphrey’s Executor. There, President Roosevelt attempted
    to remove an FTC Commissioner based on policy
    disagreements. Of course, the Supreme Court put a stop to the
    President’s effort to sway the agency, upholding the
    Commissioner’s removal protection. 
    295 U.S. at 625-26
    . But
    had the Court not so held, perhaps that would not have been the
    last of the personnel changes at the FTC. Removal of just one
    Commissioner by the President might not have had any
    substantial effect on the multi-member body’s direction, which
    he so strongly disfavored. The President might have had to
    remove multiple Commissioners in order to change the
    agency’s course.
    By contrast, the CFPB Director’s line of accountability to
    the President is clear and direct. Before Congress established
    the Bureau, multiple agencies—most of them independent—
    had jurisdiction over consumer financial protection, and that
    dispersion hampered executive ability to diagnose and respond
    to problems. The creation of the CFPB, with the centralization
    of previously scattered powers under common leadership,
    enhanced public accountability and simplified the President’s
    ability to communicate policy preferences and detect failings.
    Now, if the President finds consumer protection enforcement
    to be lacking or unlawful, he knows exactly where to turn. If
    the offending conduct is rooted in the Director’s failure to carry
    out the prescribed work of the agency, the President can
    remove the Director for “inefficiency, neglect of duty, or
    malfeasance in office.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (c). The President
    need only remove and replace a single officer in order to
    transform the entire CFPB and the execution of the consumer
    protection laws it enforces. Thus, just as the Framers
    “consciously decid[ed] to vest Executive authority in one
    45
    person rather than several” so as to “focus, rather than to
    spread” responsibility and thereby “facilitat[e] accountability”
    to the people, Clinton v. Jones, 
    520 U.S. 681
    , 712 (1997)
    (Breyer, J., concurring), Congress’s creation of an independent
    agency led by a single Director would appear to facilitate the
    agency’s accountability to the President.
    Eschewing the relevant doctrinal inquiry—whether an
    agency’s independence impermissibly interferes with
    presidential power—PHH nonetheless seeks some other home
    in the precedent for its argument that a single-headed
    independent agency is unlawful. PHH places great stock in the
    Court’s observation in Humphrey’s Executor that the FTC is
    “called upon to exercise the trained judgment of a body of
    experts.” Pet’rs’ Br. 22-23 (quoting Humphrey’s Executor,
    
    295 U.S. at 624
    ). It claims an absence of any such body here.
    In reality, Congress created a multi-member body of experts to
    check the CFPB Director: the Financial Stability Oversight
    Council (FSOC). See 
    12 U.S.C. § 5321
    . The Council brings
    together the nation’s leading financial regulators, including the
    Secretary of the Treasury and the Chairman of the Federal
    Reserve, to constrain risk in the financial system. 
    Id.
     §
    5321(b). The FSOC may stay or veto any CFPB regulation that
    threatens the “safety and soundness” of the national economy.
    Id. § 5513.
    As a legal matter, the passing reference to a “body” of
    experts in Humphrey’s Executor arose in the course of the
    Court’s statutory holding, not its constitutional analysis.
    Before reaching the constitutional question—whether FTC
    Commissioners may be given for-cause protection consistently
    with the separation of powers—the Court needed to discern
    whether the statute in question actually required for-cause
    removal. To do so, the Court asked whether the express
    statutory term allowing removal “by the President for
    46
    inefficiency, neglect of duty, or malfeasance in office” carried
    a negative implication barring the President from removing
    Commissioners for other reasons or for no reason at all. 
    295 U.S. at 619
    . The Court reasoned that the FTC’s composition
    as a “body of experts” “made clear” that “the intention of
    Congress” was to limit removal to the enumerated causes. 
    Id. at 623-24
    . Independence from presidential control, Congress
    believed, would facilitate the Commission’s access to apolitical
    expertise and its exercise of neutral judgment. Even as to the
    statutory question, the Court emphasized the Commissioners’
    expertise more than their number: “The commission is to be
    nonpartisan; and it must, from the very nature of its duties, act
    with entire impartiality. It is charged with the enforcement of
    no policy except the policy of the law.” 
    Id. at 624
    . PHH further
    suggests that the terms “quasi-legislative” and “quasi-judicial”
    in Humphrey’s Executor implicitly emphasize collective
    leadership, because legislatures and appellate courts have more
    than one member. Oral Arg. Tr. at 40-42. But those terms refer
    to the functions and powers of the agency, not its singular or
    plural head. See Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 629
    . The
    fact that district judges sit alone, for example, makes them no
    less judicial.
    As an alternative theory why an agency’s leadership
    structure might be constitutionally relevant to presidential
    power, PHH points out that the CFPB Director’s five-year term
    means that some future President might not get to appoint a
    CFPB Director, whereas Presidents typically have an
    opportunity to appoint at least some members of multi-member
    commissions, or to select a member to act as chair. Pet’rs’ Br.
    25. But the constitutionality of for-cause protection does not
    turn on whether the term is five years or four. None of the
    leaders of independent financial-regulatory agencies serves a
    term that perfectly coincides with that of the President, and
    many have longer terms than the CFPB Director. See Hogue,
    47
    Independence of Federal Financial Regulators, at 14 (“Five-
    year terms are the most common . . . but some positions have
    longer terms.”); Marshall J. Breger & Gary J. Edles,
    Established by Practice: The Theory and Operation of
    Independent Federal Agencies, 
    52 Admin. L. Rev. 1111
    , 1137
    (2000) (describing terms as “typically extend[ing] beyond the
    four-year presidential term”). As noted, the seven governors
    of the Federal Reserve Board are appointed to serve staggered
    fourteen-year terms unless removed for cause. See 
    12 U.S.C. § 242
    . Further examples abound. The members of the
    Consumer Product Safety Commission, the FTC, and the Merit
    Systems Protection Board have seven-year terms, 
    15 U.S.C. § 2053
    ; 
    15 U.S.C. § 41
    ; 
    5 U.S.C. § 1202
    , the Federal Deposit
    Insurance Corporation’s five directors each has a six-year term,
    
    12 U.S.C. § 1812
    , so, too, do the National Credit Union
    Administration’s three members, 12 U.S.C. §§ 1752a(b), (c);
    and the National Transportation Safety Board’s members serve
    five-year terms, 
    49 U.S.C. § 1111
    . The Social Security
    Commissioner appointed by President George W. Bush to a
    six-year term served into the second term of President Barack
    Obama.
    Across independent agencies, there is also wide variation
    as to the means of appointment and term of various
    chairpersons.     The members of the Federal Election
    Commission, for instance, serve six-year terms, and the Chair,
    rather than being presidentially appointed, rotates among the
    members annually. 
    52 U.S.C. §§ 30106
    (a)(2), (5). The
    International Trade Commission’s Chair, which changes
    biannually, must alternate between political parties without
    regard to who is in the White House. 
    19 U.S.C. § 1330
    . And
    among agencies with chairs chosen by the President, not all
    may be replaced by the President for any reason at any time.
    The Chair of the Federal Reserve serves a fixed four-year term,
    48
    and the Federal Deposit Credit Insurance Corporation’s Chair
    serves a five-year term. 
    12 U.S.C. § 242
    ; 
    id.
     § 1812(b)(1).
    We are not aware of any court that has viewed the
    existence, strength, or particular term of agency chairs or
    members to be relevant to the constitutionality of an
    independent agency. The Constitution has never been read to
    guarantee that every President will be able to appoint all, or
    even a majority of, the leaders of every independent agency, or
    to name its chair. And what practical effect the terms of any
    particular agency’s members or chair might have on a
    President’s agenda remains context-dependent and unclear.
    See Hogue, Independence of Federal Financial Regulators, at
    8-9 & n.36 (explaining that the statutory or practical authority
    of such chairs varies widely); Senate Committee on
    Governmental Affairs, Study on Federal Regulation, S. Doc.
    No. 95-91, vol.5, at 35 (1977) (“[T]he President would have
    only a limited opportunity to affect the leadership of any given
    commission; most of the time, hold-overs from a prior
    administration could be expected to be part of the
    membership.”). PHH assumes that this factor always cuts one
    way. In reality, the diversity of circumstance helps illustrate
    why PHH errs in treating commission structure as
    constitutionally decisive.
    Notably, when the President does get to replace the CFPB
    Director, he is not restricted by ex-officio requirements to
    appoint incumbent officeholders, or by a partisan-balance
    mandate to select individuals who do not even belong to his
    political party. See, e.g., 15 U.S.C. § 78d(a) (not more than
    three of five SEC Commissioners shall be members of the same
    political party); 
    12 U.S.C. § 1812
    (a)(2) (not more than three of
    the five members of the FDIC’s Board of Directors may be
    members of the same political party, and one must have State
    bank supervisory experience); 
    12 U.S.C. § 242
     (the Chairman
    49
    and two Vice Chairmen of the Federal Reserve are designated
    from among its Board of Governors). At bottom, the ability to
    remove a Director when cause to do so arises and to appoint a
    replacement provides “ample authority to assure that the
    [Director] is competently performing his or her statutory
    responsibilities.” Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 692
    . After all, the
    terms “inefficiency, neglect of duty, or malfeasance in office”
    are “very broad.” Bowsher, 
    478 U.S. at 729
    . Given these
    realities, a single level of for-cause protection for heads of
    certain appropriate agencies is constitutionally permissible
    despite the possibility that some future President will lack a
    regularly occurring vacancy to fill.
    We find no reason in constitutional precedent, history, or
    principle to invalidate the CFPB’s independence. The
    Supreme Court has sustained for-cause protection for the heads
    of certain administrative agencies—even if they perform a mix
    of regulatory, investigative, prosecutorial, and adjudicatory
    functions—as compatible with the President’s essential duty to
    assure faithful execution of the law. The CFPB led by a single
    Director is as consistent with the President’s constitutional
    authority as it would be if it were led by a group. Like other
    independent federal financial regulators designed to protect the
    public interest in the integrity and stability of markets from
    short-term political or special interests, the CFPB is without
    constitutional defect.
    II. Broader Theories of Unconstitutionality
    PHH goes further than trying to problematize the CFPB’s
    leadership structure with reference to the logic or language of
    the Supreme Court’s removal-power cases; it offers several
    broader theories of unconstitutionality. None of PHH’s novel
    objections to the Director’s for-cause protection squares with
    the Constitution or precedent. And PHH’s disputed factual
    50
    premises about the effects of agency design choices underscore
    that, while such considerations may be useful fodder for policy-
    making by Congress, they are not grounds for courts to reshape
    the constitutional removal power.
    First, breaking with traditional separation-of-powers
    analysis and precedent, PHH and its amici assail the CFPB as
    somehow too powerful. See Pet’rs’ Br. 24; Amicus Br. of
    Chamber of Commerce 8-11. But nothing about the focus or
    scope of the agency’s mandate renders it constitutionally
    questionable; indeed, the Bureau’s powers have long been
    housed in and enforced by agency officials protected from
    removal without cause. That fact underscores our fundamental
    point: The exercise of those powers by an independent official
    does not interfere with the President’s constitutional role.
    Second, the CFPB’s sole directorship is not historically
    anomalous. And, in any event, congressional innovation in the
    CFPB’s internal structure would not alone render the agency
    constitutionally invalid.
    Third, PHH’s notion that a multi-member structure would
    safeguard liberty, writ large, because it would check or slow or
    stop the CFPB from carrying out its duties is a non-sequitur
    from the perspective of precedent, which focuses on
    President’s authority and the separation of powers.
    Finally, our decision to sustain the challenged for-cause
    provision cannot reasonably be taken to invite Congress to
    make all federal agencies (or various combinations thereof)
    independent of the President. The President’s plenary
    authority over his cabinet and most executive agencies is
    obvious and remains untouched by our decision. It is PHH’s
    unmoored theory of liberty that threatens to lead down a
    dangerously slippery slope.
    51
    A. Scope of Agency Power
    PHH argues that, because the CFPB Director wields “vast
    authority” over the American economy, he cannot be protected
    from the President. Pet’rs’ Br. 28. Both the factual and the
    legal premises of that argument are unsupported.
    To begin with the factual assertion, the CFPB’s power and
    influence are not out of the ordinary for a financial regulator
    or, indeed, any type of independent administrative agency. The
    Bureau enforces anti-fraud rules in the consumer finance
    context; it does not unilaterally exercise broad regulatory
    power over the financial system. Its authority reaches only
    entities providing “consumer financial product[s] or
    service[s],” limited to those offered to individual consumers
    “primarily for personal, family, or household purposes.” See
    
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (a); 
    id.
     §§ 5481(4), (5), (6), (15). It does not
    address, for example, business-to-business or institutional debt
    or investments. In that respect, it contrasts with the 1935-era
    FTC—upheld by the Court in Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at
    620—that had authority, with limited exceptions, over
    commerce generally.
    That the CFPB is headed by a single Director does not
    render the scope of its responsibilities anomalous or
    problematic. Independence has long been associated with
    financial regulators with wide latitude to oversee and steady
    financial markets and the national economy. See supra Part
    I.B. Independent financial regulators have been headed either
    by one person, as with the Comptroller of the Treasury and the
    Comptroller of the Currency, or by a group, as with the Federal
    Reserve. The CFPB’s authority to ensure the fairness of
    family- and household-facing financial products does not
    somehow pose unprecedented dangers rendering every
    historical analogue inapt.
    52
    As for PHH’s legal premise that the scope of the CFPB’s
    regulatory authority is constitutionally relevant, Humphrey’s
    Executor turned not on the breadth of the FTC’s jurisdiction or
    on its social and economic impact, but on its character as a
    financial and commercial regulator. The Supreme Court
    described the FTC as “an administrative body created by
    Congress to carry into effect legislative policies embodied in
    the statute in accordance with the legislative standard therein
    prescribed, and to perform other specified duties as a legislative
    or as a judicial aid.” Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 628
    .
    PHH relies on Morrison’s description of the independent
    counsel as having only “limited jurisdiction and tenure and
    lacking policymaking or significant administrative authority.”
    
    487 U.S. at 691
    . Those limitations were significant in
    Morrison because the independent counsel’s criminal-law-
    enforcement functions were quintessentially “executive” in
    nature; the Court placed emphasis on features of the
    independent counsel that would clearly distinguish her from,
    for example, an independent Attorney General. See 
    id.
     The
    Court spelled out the independent counsel’s functions to make
    plain that they were not “so central to the functioning of the
    Executive Branch as to require as a matter of constitutional law
    that the counsel be terminable at will by the President.” 
    Id. at 691-92
    . But that is not to suggest that it is appropriate to tally
    up the number of laws an agency is charged with administering
    in order to determine whether it may be independent. Cf.
    Pet’rs’ Reply Br. 2. Indeed, the independent counsel had all of
    federal criminal law at her disposal. Rather, the Court has
    analyzed the function of the office in question and where it
    stood in relation to particular types of governmental power,
    including those like criminal prosecution that are indisputably
    and solely executive.
    In sum, under the requisite functional analysis, the CFPB’s
    authority is more cabined than either the FTC’s or the
    53
    independent counsel’s, and the agency is part of a longstanding
    tradition, dating back to the founding of the Republic, of
    financial regulators with a modicum of independence from
    presidential will.
    B. Novelty
    PHH further argues that the CFPB’s structure is
    constitutionally suspect because it is novel. We reject both
    premises—that whatever novelty the CFPB may represent calls
    into question its constitutionality, and that the CFPB is in any
    relevant respect unprecedented.
    Even if the CFPB were anomalous, PHH points to nothing
    that makes novelty itself a source of unconstitutionality.
    Novelty “is not necessarily fatal; there is a first time for
    everything.” Nat’l Fed’n of Indep. Bus. v. Sebelius, 
    567 U.S. 519
    , 549 (2012) (opinion of Roberts, C.J.); see also Mistretta
    v. United States, 
    488 U.S. 361
    , 385 (1989) (addressing the
    constitutionality of the Sentencing Commission and noting that
    “[o]ur constitutional principles of separated powers are not
    violated . . . by mere anomaly or innovation”). The
    independent counsel, the Sentencing Commission, and the FTC
    were each “novel” when initiated, but all are constitutional. In
    the precedents PHH invokes, novelty alone was insufficient to
    establish a constitutional defect.
    For instance, in NLRB v. Noel Canning, the Supreme Court
    interpreted the President’s express constitutional authorization
    to “fill up all Vacancies that may happen during the Recess of
    the Senate.” 
    134 S. Ct. 2550
    , 2556 (2014); see U.S. Const. art.
    II, § 2, cl. 3. An historical practice of recess appointments
    “since the beginning of the Republic” aided in “expounding
    terms [and] phrases”—“Recess of the Senate” and “Vacancies
    that may happen”—and the Court treated “practice as an
    important interpretive factor.” 
    134 S. Ct. at 2560
     (quoting
    54
    Letter from James Madison to Spencer Roane (Sept. 2, 1819),
    in 8 The Writings of James Madison 450 (Hunt ed., 1908)). But
    novelty did not create the constitutional question or define the
    constitutional violation.
    In Free Enterprise Fund, the Supreme Court quoted a
    dissenter in this court stating that “lack of historical precedent”
    for dual-layered protection may be “the most telling indication
    of [a] severe constitutional problem.” 
    561 U.S. at 505
     (quoting
    Free Enterprise Fund v. Public Co. Accounting Oversight Bd.,
    
    537 F.3d 667
    , 699 (D.C. Cir. 2008) (Kavanaugh, J.,
    dissenting)). But it did so only after explaining how, under its
    own precedent, the unusual set-up of the Public Company
    Accounting Oversight Board directly impaired the President’s
    “ability to execute the laws.” 
    561 U.S. at 500-01
    . Other
    constitutional principles beyond novelty must establish why a
    specific regime is problematic.
    A constrained role for novelty in constitutional doctrine is
    well justified.     Our political representatives sometimes
    confront new problems calling for tailored solutions. The 2008
    financial crisis, which Congress partially attributed to a
    colossal failure of consumer protection, was surely such a
    situation. The Constitution was “intended to endure for ages to
    come, and, consequently, to be adapted to the various crises of
    human affairs.” McCulloch v. Maryland, 
    17 U.S. 316
    , 415
    (1819). The judiciary patrols constitutional boundaries, but it
    does not use the Constitution merely to enforce old ways. Even
    if we agreed that the CFPB’s structure were novel, we would
    not find it unconstitutional on that basis alone.
    As for the descriptive premise of the novelty argument—
    that the CFPB’s sole-director structure makes it historically
    exceptional, Pet’rs’ Br. 23—we again must disagree. For
    starters, there is no appreciable difference between the
    55
    historical pedigree of single-member and multi-member
    independent agencies. The most notable early examples in
    either category (and the only pre-Twentieth Century ones) are
    sole-headed financial regulators: the Comptroller of the
    Treasury, dating back to the late-Eighteenth Century; and the
    Office of the Comptroller of the Currency, established in the
    mid-Nineteenth. See Act of Sept. 2, 1789, ch. 12, § 3, 1 Stat.
    at 66; Nat’l Bank Act of 1863, 12 Stat. at 665-66.
    Other examples of single-headed independent agencies
    include the Social Security Administration, which was placed
    under a single director in 1994, see 
    42 U.S.C. § 902
    (a), and the
    Office of Special Counsel established under a sole director in
    1978, the same year as the Office of Independent Counsel
    upheld in Morrison, see 
    5 U.S.C. § 1211
    ; Civil Service Reform
    Act of 1978, Pub. L. No. 95-454, 
    92 Stat. 1111
     (1978).
    Congress established the sole-headed, for-cause-protected
    Federal Housing Finance Agency in 2008, in response to
    similar concerns as gave rise to the CFPB. See 
    12 U.S.C. § 4512
    . This longstanding tradition provides historical pedigree
    to the CFPB, and refutes the contention that the CFPB’s single-
    director structure is anything new. See supra Parts I.B., I.C.3.
    PHH and its amici try to undermine these analogues by
    asserting that Presidents have consistently objected to single-
    headed independent agencies. See Amicus Br. of United States
    17-19. As an initial matter, no contemporaneous objection was
    voiced by the President or any dissenting faction within
    Congress to placing the CFPB itself under a Director rather
    than a board. PHH’s contention is further belied by history.
    President Lincoln, for instance, signed without objection an act
    rendering the Comptroller of the Currency removable only with
    advice and consent of the Senate. Steven G. Calabresi &
    Christopher S. Yoo, The Unitary Executive During the Second
    Half-Century, 26 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 667, 734 (2003);
    56
    George Wharton Pepper, Family Quarrels: The President, The
    Senate, The House 111 (1931); see Nat’l Bank Act of 1863, 
    12 Stat. 665
    , 665-66 (1863). And President George H.W. Bush
    approved that Congress had decided to “retain[] current law
    which provides that the Special Counsel may only be removed
    for inefficiency, neglect of duty, or malfeasance.” George
    H.W. Bush, Remarks on Signing the Whistleblower Protection
    Act of 1989 (Apr. 10, 1989), http://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/
    ws/?pid=16899.
    Evidence proffered to show presidential contestation is
    recent, sparse, and nonspecific. See Amicus Br. of United
    States 17-19. Executive objections to removal restrictions have
    not made clear whether they opposed protecting a sole agency
    head in particular, or for-cause protections more generally. See
    Statement by President William J. Clinton Upon Signing H.R.
    4277, 1994 U.S.C.C.A.N. 1624 (Aug. 15, 1994) (Clinton
    administration objection to Social Security Administration
    under a sole, independent administrator on the ground that “the
    provision that the President can remove the single
    Commissioner only for neglect of duty or malfeasance in office
    raises a significant constitutional question”); Mem. Op. for the
    Gen. Counsel, Civil Serv. Comm’n, 
    2 Op. O.L.C. 120
    , 120
    (1978) (Carter administration objection to creation of Office of
    Special Counsel because it exercised “functions [that] are
    executive in character,” such as investigation and prosecution);
    President Ronald Reagan, Mem. of Disapproval on a Bill
    Concerning Whistleblower Protection, 2 Pub. Papers 1391,
    1392 (Oct. 26, 1988) (Reagan administration objection to law
    creating Office of Special Counsel because it “purports to
    insulate the Office from presidential supervision and to limit
    the power of the President to remove his subordinates from
    office”). The scant and ambivalent record of executive-branch
    contestation thus does not detract from the tradition of sole-
    headed agencies as precedents for the CFPB.
    57
    We are also unpersuaded by efforts to distinguish away
    agencies like the Social Security Administration and the Office
    of Special Counsel on the ground that they lack authority to
    bring law enforcement actions against private citizens. See
    Amicus Br. of United States 17-18. Those agencies perform
    important and far-reaching functions that are ordinarily
    characterized as executive. The Social Security Administration
    runs one of the largest programs in the federal government,
    overseeing retirement, disability, and survivors’ benefits,
    handling millions of claims and trillions of dollars. And the
    Office of Special Counsel enforces workplace rules for federal
    government employers and employees. Casting these agencies
    as somehow less important than the CFPB does not show them
    to be less “executive” in nature. The CFPB’s single Director
    is not an historical anomaly.
    C. Freestanding Liberty
    Moving beyond precedent and practice, PHH and its amici
    ask us to compare single-headed and group-led agencies’
    relative contributions to “liberty.” The CFPB, headed by an
    individual Director, is constitutionally invalid, they say,
    because it diminishes the President’s firing authority without
    substituting a different, ostensibly liberty-protecting
    mechanism—collective leadership. See, e.g., Pet’rs’ Br. 2. If
    a majority of an agency’s leadership group must agree before
    the agency can take any action, the agency might be slower and
    more prone to compromise or inaction. A sole-headed agency,
    by contrast, might be nimble and resolute. Because multiple
    heads might make the CFPB less likely to act against the
    financial services industry it regulates, group leadership is,
    according to PHH, constitutionally compelled.
    There is no question that “structural protections against
    abuse of power [a]re critical to preserving liberty.” Bowsher,
    58
    
    478 U.S. at 730
    ; see also Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 501
     (quoting Bowsher, 
    478 U.S. at 730
    ).               Agencies’
    accountability to the President and the people, bolstered by the
    removal power, can ultimately protect liberty. But by arguing
    that sole-headed and group-headed agencies differ in terms of
    “liberty” without identifying any differential effect on
    accountability, PHH proposes a ground for our decision that
    lacks doctrinal footing and conflicts with Morrison’s approval
    of a sole-headed independent agency. Morrison, Wiener, and
    Humphrey’s Executor hold that unbridled removal power in the
    President’s hands is not a universal requirement for
    constitutional accountability; those cases thus underscore that
    such unbridled power is not in all contexts necessary to serve
    liberty or the myriad other constitutional values that undergird
    the separation of powers. Broad observations about liberty-
    enhancing effects are not themselves freestanding
    constitutional limitations.
    PHH’s brand of argument depends on a series of
    unsupported leaps. First, it treats a broad purpose of the
    separation of powers—safeguarding liberty—as if it were a
    judicially manageable constitutional standard. But, as criteria
    for judicial decision,
    the purposes of the separation of powers are too general
    and diverse to offer much concrete guidance. Among
    other things, the separation of powers and the
    accompanying checks and balances promote
    efficiency, energy, stability, limited government,
    control of factions, deliberation, the rule of law, and
    accountability. . . . [I]n the absence of any specific
    textual home or pattern of historical practice or judicial
    precedent, one could reasonably move from these
    broad and often-conflicting purposes to any number of
    59
    fair conclusions about . . . almost any freestanding
    separation of powers question.
    John F. Manning, Foreword: The Means of Constitutional
    Power, 
    128 Harv. L. Rev. 1
    , 56-57 (2014). As sustained by the
    Supreme Court, for-cause removal restrictions presumptively
    respect all of the “general and diverse” goals of separation of
    powers, see 
    id. at 56
    , including liberty. Once the Supreme
    Court is satisfied that a removal restriction leaves the President
    adequate control of the executive branch’s functions, the Court
    does not separately attempt to re-measure the provision’s
    potential effect on liberty or any other separation-of-powers
    objective.
    Another of PHH’s leaps is its assumption that the CFPB’s
    challenged characteristics diminish “liberty,” writ large. It
    remains unexplained why we would assess the challenged
    removal restriction with reference to the liberty of financial
    services providers, and not more broadly to the liberty of the
    individuals and families who are their customers. Congress
    determined that, without the Dodd-Frank Act and the CFPB,
    the activities the CFPB is now empowered to regulate
    contributed to the 2008 economic crisis and Americans’
    devastating losses of property and livelihood. Financial Crisis
    Inquiry Commission, The Financial Crisis Inquiry Report, at
    xv-xvii. Congress understood that markets’ contribution to
    human liberty derives from freedom of contract, and that such
    freedom depends on market participants’ access to accurate
    information, and on clear and reliably enforced rules against
    fraud and coercion. Congress designed the CFPB with those
    realities in mind.
    More fundamentally, PHH’s unmoored liberty analysis is
    no part of the inquiry the Supreme Court’s cases require: As
    Part I explains, the key question in the Court’s removal-power
    60
    cases is whether a challenged restriction either aggrandizes the
    power of another branch or impermissibly interferes with the
    duty and authority of the President to execute the laws. The
    CFPB Director’s for-cause restriction does neither. That result
    is liberty-protecting; it respects Congress’s chosen means to
    cleanse consumer financial markets of deception and fraud, and
    respects the President’s authority under the challenged law to
    ensure that the CFPB Director performs his or her job
    competently and in accordance with the law. The traditional
    for-cause protection leaves the President “ample authority” to
    supervise the agency. Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 692
    .
    If the CFPB Director runs afoul of statutory or
    constitutional limits, it is the President’s prerogative to
    consider whether any excesses amount to cause for removal,
    the Financial Stability Oversight Council’s expert judgment
    whether to step in to protect markets, and the courts’ role to
    hem in violations of individual rights. The now-reinstated
    panel holding that invalidated the disgorgement penalties
    levied against PHH (a holding expressly approved by three
    additional members of the en banc court, see Concurring Op.
    (Tatel, J.)), illustrates how courts appropriately guard the
    liberty of regulated parties when agencies overstep. The fact
    that the CFPB is led by one Director, rather than several
    commissioners, does not encroach on the President’s
    constitutional power and duty to supervise the enforcement of
    the law.
    D. The Cabinet and the Slippery Slope
    Finally, PHH mounts a slippery-slope argument against
    the CFPB. Sustaining the CFPB’s structure as constitutionally
    permissible, PHH argues, could threaten the President’s control
    over the Cabinet. Pet’rs’ Reply Br. 7.
    61
    We disagree.       “[T]here are undoubtedly executive
    functions that, regardless of the enactments of Congress, must
    be performed by officers subject to removal at will by the
    President.” Bowsher, 
    478 U.S. at 762
     (White, J., dissenting);
    see Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 690
     (same). Should Congress ever
    seek to provide the Cabinet with for-cause protection against
    removal, at least two principled distinctions would differentiate
    this case from a challenge to such a law.
    First, the Supreme Court’s removal-power precedent,
    which we follow here, makes the nature of the agency’s
    function the central consideration in whether Congress may
    grant it a measure of independence. The Court has held, time
    and again, that while the Constitution broadly vests executive
    power in the President, U.S. Const. art. II, § 1, cl. 1, that does
    not require that the President have at-will authority to fire every
    officer. Doctrine and history squarely place the CFPB Director
    among those officials who may constitutionally have for-cause
    protection. At the same time, there are executive officials
    whom the President must be able to fire at will. See generally
    Marbury v. Madison, 
    5 U.S. 137
    , 166 (1803) (“[W]here the
    heads of departments are the political or confidential agents of
    the executive, merely to execute the will of the President, or
    rather to act in cases in which the executive possesses a
    constitutional or legal discretion, nothing can be more perfectly
    clear than that their acts are only politically examinable.”).
    Those would surely include Cabinet members—prominently,
    the Secretaries of Defense and State—who have open-ended
    and sweeping portfolios to assist with the President’s core
    constitutional responsibilities. See generally Myers, 
    272 U.S. at 141
     (suggesting that “ministerial” acts of Secretary of State
    were “entirely to be distinguished from his duty as a
    subordinate to the President in the discharge of the President’s
    political duties which could not be controlled”). Executive
    functions specifically identified in Article II would be a good
    62
    place to start in understanding the scope of that executive core:
    It includes, at least, the President’s role as Commander in
    Chief, and the foreign-affairs and pardon powers. U.S. Const.
    art. II, § 2; see Zivotofsky ex rel. Zivotofsky v. Clinton, 
    566 U.S. 189
    , 211 (2012) (“The President has broad authority in the field
    of foreign affairs.”). Although this case does not require us to
    catalogue every official on either side of the constitutional line,
    we emphasize that certain governmental functions may not be
    removal-restricted.
    Second, Cabinet-level officers traditionally are close
    presidential advisers and allies. Under the 25th Amendment,
    Cabinet officials have the power (by majority vote and with the
    Vice President’s assent) to remove the President temporarily
    from office. See U.S. Const. amend. XXV, § 4; Freytag v.
    Comm’r of Internal Revenue, 
    501 U.S. 868
    , 887 (1991)
    (suggesting that the 25th Amendment, which refers to “the
    principal officers of the executive departments,” refers to
    “Cabinet-level entities”). We do not believe that the heads of
    independent agencies are executive-agency principals eligible
    under the 25th Amendment to vote on a President’s incapacity.
    Cabinet officials are also, by statute, in the presidential line of
    succession, see 
    3 U.S.C. § 19
    (d)(1), and their agencies are
    specifically denoted as “Executive departments,” 
    5 U.S.C. § 101
    . There is thus little prospect that Congress could require
    the President to tolerate a Cabinet that is not fully and directly
    accountable to him.
    Indeed, the slipperiest slope lies on the other side of the
    mountain. PHH argues that, regardless of whether Humphrey’s
    Executor itself turned on the FTC’s multi-member character,
    we should reject any independent agency that does not
    precisely mimic the agency structure that the Court approved
    in that case. See Pet’rs’ Br. 22. PHH gleans from Free
    Enterprise Fund the proposition that “when a court is asked ‘to
    63
    consider a new situation not yet encountered by the [Supreme]
    Court,’ there must be special mitigating ‘circumstances’ to
    justify ‘restrict[ing the President] in his ability to remove’ an
    officer.” Pet’rs’ Br. 22 (quoting 
    561 U.S. at 483-84
    ). The
    Court held no such thing. And if we were to embrace an
    analysis invalidating any independent agency that does not
    mirror the 1935-era FTC, our decision would threaten many, if
    not all, modern-day independent agencies, perhaps including
    the FTC itself. See Pet’rs’ Reply Br. 6 (noting that the FTC did
    not claim rulemaking authority until 1962).
    PHH suggests that so-called “[h]istorical[]” multi-member
    independent agencies are different in kind—and thus would be
    safe even if the CFPB were invalidated—because “their own
    internal checks” somehow substitute for a check by the
    President. Pet’rs’ Br. 23. The argument is that multi-member
    agency leadership could check or slow or stop agency action
    even when the President could not, and that such a check, in
    turn, protects liberty. PHH’s newly devised theory posits that
    freestanding liberty is the goal, and that various agency design
    features might be a means—alternative to illimitable
    presidential control but nonetheless somehow mandated by
    Article II—to ensure that liberty. That theory lacks grounding
    in precedent or principle. See supra Part I.C.3. In Free
    Enterprise Fund, for example, the fact that the PCAOB and the
    SEC were both multi-member bodies did not salvage the
    Board’s dual-layered removal limitation.
    If PHH’s version of liberty were the test—elevating
    regulated entities’ liberty over those of the rest of the public,
    and requiring that such liberty be served by agencies designed
    for maximum deliberation, gradualism, or inaction—it is
    unclear how such a test could apply to invalidate only the
    CFPB. That test would seem equally to disapprove other
    features of many independent agencies. Consider, for example,
    64
    efficiency-promoting features like a strong chairperson, low
    quorum requirement, small membership, shared professional
    or partisan background, and electronic or negative-option
    voting. Even a multi-member independent agency might have
    features that offset that body’s theoretical gradualism and, in
    practice, achieve the efficiency that PHH’s liberty analysis
    condemns. Would such an agency be susceptible to challenge
    under PHH’s theory as threatening to liberty?
    By the same token, it is also unclear why a doctrine
    embracing PHH’s brand of freestanding liberty analysis would
    not constitutionally obligate Congress to affirmatively impose
    additional internal checking mechanisms on all independent
    agencies. Many familiar processes and structures—such as
    partisan or sectoral balance, requirements of large and broadly
    representative membership; high quorum, supermajority or
    unanimity rules; or even mandatory in-person meetings and
    votes—might foster deliberation and check action as much if
    not more than mere multi-member leadership. Reading the
    Constitution, as PHH does, to require courts to impose group
    leadership at independent agencies would appear to throw open
    many other institutional design features to judicial second-
    guessing. For good reason, PHH’s freestanding liberty analysis
    is not, and has never been, the law.
    The reality that independent agencies have many and
    varied design features underscores that there is no one,
    constitutionally compelled template. Academic analyses to
    which PHH and dissenters point for the proposition that a
    multi-headed structure is the sine qua non of these agencies’
    constitutional validity, see Dissenting Op. at 28-29
    (Kavanaugh, J.), do not support their theory. Those materials
    are more descriptive than prescriptive. And, contrary to the
    dissenters’ suggestions, they do not treat multiple membership
    as indispensable. Rather, scholars identify various indicia of
    65
    agency independence that demonstrate the rich diversity of
    institutional design. See Kirti Datla & Richard L. Revesz,
    Deconstructing Independent Agencies (and Executive
    Agencies), 
    98 Cornell L. Rev. 769
    , 774 (2013) (“Congress
    can—and does—create agencies with many different
    combinations of indicia of independence . . . .”); Barkow,
    Insulating Agencies, 89 Tex. L. Rev. at 16-18 (urging a
    functionalist analysis beyond the “obsessive focus on removal
    as the touchstone of independence”—and emphasizing the
    “failure of banking agencies to guard against lending abuses”
    as a reason for agency independence); Lisa Schultz Bressman
    & Robert B. Thompson, The Future of Agency Independence,
    
    63 Vand. L. Rev. 599
    , 607-10 (2010) (describing “[f]inancial
    agencies . . . [as] among the most prominent independent
    agencies” and independent agencies as having “some variety in
    design,” with some generally “share[d]” attributes); Breger &
    Edles, Established by Practice, 52 Admin L. Rev at 1113-14
    (“[W]e review the structure and internal operations of
    independent agencies, not[ing] several similarities and
    differences among them . . . .”); 
    id. at 1137-38
     (describing
    many “modern” independent agencies as adopting “the
    commission form” but describing “the protection . . . against
    removal ‘for cause’” as the “critical element of
    independence”); The President’s Committee on Administrative
    Management, Report of the Committee with Studies of
    Administrative Management in the Federal Government 216
    (1937) (theorizing that there are “[s]ome regulatory tasks” that,
    per “popular belief,” “ought to be performed by a group,” while
    others call for “regional representation”); 
    id.
     (emphasizing the
    importance of agency independence to ensure that certain
    regulatory functions are “kept free from the pressures and
    influences of political domination”); see also Free Enterprise
    Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 547
     (Breyer, J., dissenting) (describing
    “[a]gency independence [a]s a function of several different
    factors” and finding the “absence” of one—in the case of the
    66
    SEC, an express “for cause” provision—“not fatal to agency
    independence”). Today’s independent agencies are diverse in
    structure and function.     They have various indicia of
    independence, including differing combinations of
    independent litigation and adjudication authority, budgetary
    independence, autonomy from review by the Office of
    Management and Budget, and the familiar removal restrictions.
    See Datla & Revesz, Deconstructing Independent Agencies, 98
    Cornell L. Rev. at 772.
    The particular design choice that PHH here highlights—
    whether to create a single-director or multi-member agency—
    implicates policy determinations that we must leave to
    Congress. There are countless structural options that might be
    theorized as promoting more or less thorough deliberation
    within agencies. Our own judgments of contested empirical
    questions about institutional design are not grounds for
    deeming such choices constitutionally compelled. After all,
    “[t]he court should . . . not stray beyond the judicial province
    to explore the procedural format or to impose upon the agency
    its own notion of which procedures are ‘best’ or most likely to
    further some vague, undefined public good”—including
    “liberty,” however defined. Vermont Yankee Nuclear Power
    Corp. v. Nat. Res. Def. Council, Inc., 
    435 U.S. 519
    , 549 (1978).
    Even accepting deliberative virtues of multi-member
    bodies under certain conditions, other structural choices serve
    other virtues of equal importance. We should not require
    Congress always to privilege the putative liberty-enhancing
    virtues of the multi-member form over other capabilities
    Congress may choose, such as efficiency, steadiness, or
    nuanced attention to market developments that also, in
    different ways, may serve the liberty of the people. That is why
    the Supreme Court has acknowledged congressional latitude to
    fashion agencies in different ways, recognizing that the
    67
    “versatility of circumstances often mocks a natural desire for
    definitiveness.” Wiener, 
    357 U.S. at 352
    .
    Judicial review of agency design choices must focus on
    ensuring that Congress has not “interfere[d] with the
    President’s exercise of the ‘executive power’ and his
    constitutionally appointed duty to ‘take care that the laws be
    faithfully executed’ under Article II.” Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 690
    , 691 n.30. Internal agency dynamics to which PHH points
    have little to do with the President’s ultimate duty to ensure
    that the laws are faithfully executed.
    A constitutional analysis that condemns the CFPB’s for-
    cause removal provision provides little assurance against—
    indeed invites—the judicial abolition of all independent
    agencies. PHH and dissenters do not dispel that concern. In
    PHH’s view, the Supreme Court’s entire line of precedent
    beginning with Humphrey’s Executor was wrongly decided.
    See Pet’rs’ Br. 22 n.4 (preserving argument for overrule of
    Morrison and Humphery’s Executor); see also Dissenting Op.
    at 61 n.18 (Kavanaugh, J.) (noting PHH’s preservation of that
    argument). PHH’s course calls into question the legitimacy of
    every independent agency. We instead follow Supreme Court
    precedent to sustain the challenged Act of Congress.
    Conclusion
    Applying binding Supreme Court precedent, we see no
    constitutional defect in the statute preventing the President
    from firing the CFPB Director without cause. We thus uphold
    Congress’s choice.
    The Supreme Court’s removal-power decisions have, for
    more than eighty years, upheld ordinary for-cause protections
    of the heads of independent agencies, including financial
    regulators. That precedent leaves to the legislative process, not
    68
    the courts, the choice whether to subject the Bureau’s
    leadership to at-will presidential removal. Congress’s decision
    to provide the CFPB Director a degree of insulation reflects its
    permissible judgment that civil regulation of consumer
    financial protection should be kept one step removed from
    political winds and presidential will. We have no warrant here
    to invalidate such a time-tested course.          No relevant
    consideration gives us reason to doubt the constitutionality of
    the independent CFPB’s single-member structure. Congress
    made constitutionally permissible institutional design choices
    for the CFPB with which courts should hesitate to interfere.
    “While the Constitution diffuses power the better to secure
    liberty, it also contemplates that practice will integrate the
    dispersed powers into a workable government.” Youngstown
    Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 
    343 U.S. 579
    , 635 (1952)
    (Jackson, J., concurring).
    The petition for review is granted in part and denied in
    part, and the case is remanded to the agency for further
    proceedings.
    TATEL, Circuit Judge, with whom Circuit Judges MILLETT and
    PILLARD join, concurring: Finding no way to avoid the
    constitutional question, the en banc court reinstates the panel
    opinion’s statutory holdings. Were this court to address the
    statutory questions, which are fully briefed, I would have
    resolved them differently. Specifically, I would have
    concluded that (1) the Bureau reasonably interpreted RESPA
    to impose liability on PHH, (2) the applicable statute of
    limitations reaches back five years to cover PHH’s conduct,
    and (3) the Bureau’s prospective injunction against PHH is
    permissible, even if its retrospective disgorgement penalties are
    not.
    First, the Bureau’s interpretation of RESPA. Section 8(c)
    states that “[n]othing in this section shall be construed as
    prohibiting . . . the payment to any person of a bona fide salary
    or compensation or other payment for goods or . . . services
    actually performed.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 2607
    (c) (emphasis added).
    The CFPB interpreted this provision to insulate from liability
    just payments for referral services made “solely for the service
    actually being provided on its own merits,” Director’s Decision
    at 17—that is, that “bona fide” payments excludes payments
    whose purpose is to serve as a quid pro quo for referrals.
    PHH argues that Section 8(c) unambiguously permits
    regulated entities to give or receive kickbacks in the form of
    reinsurance arrangements as long as the kickbacks do not
    exceed the reasonable market value for reinsurance services. In
    other words, PHH insists that “bona fide” admits of only one
    meaning—that a “payment is ‘bona fide’ if it bears a reasonable
    relationship to the value of the services actually provided in
    return.” Pet’rs’ Br. 43.
    But Section 8(c)’s use of the phrase “bona fide” is not
    unambiguous. Neither it nor any other provision of RESPA
    defines the term, and looking to its “ordinary or natural
    2
    meaning”—as we must when the statute supplies no definition
    of its own, FDIC v. Meyer, 
    510 U.S. 471
    , 476 (1994)—likewise
    fails to resolve the ambiguity. To the contrary, dictionary
    definitions reflect a range of meanings encompassed by the
    term, including the very definition adopted by the Bureau. See
    Webster’s New Collegiate Dictionary 125 (1973) (“Made in
    good faith without fraud or deceit . . . , made with earnest intent
    . . . , neither specious nor counterfeit.”); Black’s Law
    Dictionary 223 (4th Ed. Rev’d 1968) (“In or with good faith;
    honestly, openly, and sincerely; without deceit or fraud . . . real,
    actual, genuine, and not feigned.”). The existence of these
    varied definitions, “each making some sense under the statute,
    itself indicates” the statute’s ambiguity. National Railroad
    Passenger Corp. v. Boston & Maine Corp., 
    503 U.S. 407
    , 418
    (1992).
    Moreover, the Bureau’s interpretation of “bona fide” is
    perfectly reasonable, as the previous citations to both
    Webster’s and Black’s demonstrate. Indeed, PHH does not
    argue to the contrary, other than to claim that because RESPA
    has some criminal applications—none relevant here—the rule
    of lenity requires that any statutory ambiguity be resolved in
    PHH’s favor. The Supreme Court, however, has done just the
    opposite, deferring to an agency’s interpretation of a statute
    even though the Court recognized that violations of the statute
    could carry criminal penalties. Babbitt v. Sweet Home Chapter
    of Communities for a Greater Oregon, 
    515 U.S. 687
    , 704 n.18
    (1995) (noting that the Court has “never suggested that the rule
    of lenity should provide the standard for reviewing facial
    challenges to administrative regulations whenever the
    governing statute authorizes criminal enforcement”). Though
    there is some dispute about whether Chevron deference
    remains appropriate for agency interpretations of statutes with
    both civil and criminal applications, see Whitman v. United
    States, 
    135 S. Ct. 352
    , 352–54 (2014) (Scalia, J., respecting the
    3
    denial of certiorari) (calling Babbitt into question (citing
    Leocal v. Ashcroft, 
    543 U.S. 1
    , 11–12 n.8 (2004))), our court
    continues to adhere to the view that it is, see Competitive
    Enterprise Institute v. Department of Transportation, 
    863 F.3d 911
    , 915 n.4 (D.C. Cir. 2017) (“We apply the Chevron
    framework to this facial challenge even though violating [the
    statute] can bring criminal penalties.”). Even were Chevron
    inapplicable, given my view that the agency’s interpretation
    was correct as well as reasonable, PHH has failed to show that
    the statute is sufficiently ambiguous as to merit application of
    the rule of lenity. “[T]he rule of lenity only applies if, after
    considering text, structure, history, and purpose, there remains
    a grievous ambiguity or uncertainty in the statute, such that the
    Court must simply guess as to what Congress intended.” United
    States v. Castleman, 
    134 S. Ct. 1405
    , 1416 (2014) (quoting
    Barber v. Thomas, 
    560 U.S. 474
    , 488 (2010)). Because RESPA
    Section 8 is ambiguous, and because the Bureau’s
    interpretation is reasonable, I would have held that PHH is
    liable under the statute.
    There remains the question of how far back the Bureau can
    reach in seeking to impose liability on regulated entities.
    Specifically, the question is whether administrative actions to
    enforce RESPA’s ban on referral fees are subject to the specific
    three year statute of limitations contained in RESPA, 
    12 U.S.C. § 2614
    , as PHH argues, or whether, as the Bureau contends,
    they are subject only to the general five year statute of
    limitations on any action or administrative proceeding for
    “enforcement of any civil fine, penalty, or forfeiture” contained
    in 
    28 U.S.C. § 2462
    . Given that RESPA provides that “[a]ny
    action” to enforce the ban on referral fees initiated by the
    Bureau must be brought within three years, 
    12 U.S.C. § 2614
    ,
    the question turns on whether the word “action” encompasses
    both court and administrative actions.
    4
    RESPA’s plain text favors the Bureau’s view that the
    provision limits the timing of only court actions, not
    administrative actions like the one at issue here. The clause
    expressly refers to actions that “may be brought in the United
    States district court” and specifies that such actions are
    generally subject to a one year statute of limitations, except that
    “actions brought by the Bureau, the Secretary, the Attorney
    General of any State, or the insurance commissioner of any
    State may be brought within 3 years.” 
    Id.
     Given that state
    attorneys general and insurance commissioners have no
    authority to bring administrative enforcement actions, even if
    they may bring actions in court, it would be odd to conclude
    that this provision circumscribes when the same actors can
    bring administrative actions that they could never have brought
    in the first place. Reinforcing this point, the RESPA provision
    is entitled “Jurisdiction of courts; limitations.”
    If the statute, read alone, was not clear enough, the Bureau
    would still be entitled to a presumption that statutes of
    limitations “are construed narrowly against the government”—
    a principle “rooted in the traditional rule . . . [that] time does
    not run against the King.” BP America Production Co. v.
    Burton, 
    549 U.S. 84
    , 95–96 (2006). “A corollary of this rule is
    that when the sovereign elects to subject itself to a statute of
    limitations, the sovereign is given the benefit of the doubt if the
    scope of the statute is ambiguous.” 
    Id. at 96
    . Given this, the
    court would have to presume that RESPA’s statute of
    limitations does not cover administrative actions. The Supreme
    Court addressed a remarkably similar issue in BP America, 
    549 U.S. 84
    , in which the Court unanimously held that a general
    statute of limitations for Government contract actions applied
    only to court actions, not to administrative proceedings
    initiated by the Government.
    5
    The Bureau thus reasonably interpreted PHH’s actions as
    running afoul of RESPA and correctly concluded that it could
    impose liability on conduct falling within the five-year
    limitations period. Based on this liability, the Bureau sought
    two forms of relief: disgorgement for PHH’s past harms and an
    injunction to prevent future ones. For substantially the reasons
    given by the panel, I agree that the Bureau ran afoul of the due
    process clause by failing to give PHH adequate notice in
    advance of imposing penalties for past conduct. Importantly for
    our purposes, however, the imposition of prospective relief is
    unaffected by that fair notice issue. See, e.g., Landgraf v. USI
    Film Products, 
    511 U.S. 244
    , 273 (1994) (“When the
    intervening statute authorizes or affects the propriety of
    prospective relief, application of the new provision is not
    retroactive.”); Bowen v. Georgetown University Hospital, 
    488 U.S. 204
    , 221 (1988) (Scalia, J., concurring) (“Retroactivity [in
    agency adjudications] is not only permissible but standard.”).
    Though I disagree with the panel’s now-reinstated
    statutory holdings, I completely agree with the en banc court
    that the Bureau’s structure does not violate the constitutional
    separation of powers. PHH is free to ask the Supreme Court to
    revisit Humphrey’s Executor and Morrison, but that argument
    has no truck in a circuit court of appeals. Attempts to
    distinguish those cases—by rereading Humphrey’s as hinging
    on the multi-member structure of the FTC, or by characterizing
    the Independent Counsel in Morrison as an insignificant
    inferior officer—are, at best, strained. Indeed, to uphold the
    constitutionality of the Bureau’s structure we need scarcely go
    further than Morrison itself, which approved a powerful
    independent entity headed by a single official and along the
    way expressly compared that office’s “prosecutorial powers”
    to the “civil enforcement powers” long wielded by the FTC and
    other independent agencies. Morrison v. Olson, 
    487 U.S. 654
    ,
    692 n.31 (1988).
    6
    Although it may (or may not) be wise, as a policy matter,
    to structure an independent agency as a multimember body,
    nothing in the Constitution’s separation of powers compels that
    result. The Constitution no more “enacts” social science about
    the benefits of group decision-making than it does “Mr. Herbert
    Spencer’s Social Statics.” Lochner v. New York, 
    198 U.S. 45
    ,
    75 (1905) (Holmes, J. dissenting).
    WILKINS, Circuit Judge, with whom ROGERS, Circuit
    Judge, joins, concurring: I concur with the Court’s decision
    in full. This petition involves a challenge to a final decision
    in an adjudication by the Consumer Financial Protection
    Bureau (“CFPB”). Petitioners are quite clear that they seek
    review of the “Decision of the Director” and the “Final
    Order” issued by the CFPB’s Director that, together,
    constitute the Bureau’s final agency action in an adjudication.
    Petition 1-3. The petitioners (and our dissenting colleagues)
    seek to downplay this basic fact, even though it is the bedrock
    for the exercise of our jurisdiction. They do so because
    acknowledging that the Director has significant adjudicatory
    responsibilities – indeed, the Director’s adjudicatory functions
    are the only powers at issue in this case – seriously
    undermines the separation-of-powers challenge before us. All
    in all, those significant quasi-judicial duties, as well as the
    Director’s quasi-legislative duties and obligations to
    coordinate and consult with other expert agencies, provide
    additional grounds for denial of the separation-of-powers
    claim before us.
    I.
    Congress authorized the CFPB “to conduct hearings and
    adjudication proceedings” to “ensure or enforce compliance
    with” the provisions of the Dodd-Frank Act establishing the
    authority of the CFPB and any rules issued thereunder, and
    “any other Federal law that the Bureau is authorized to
    enforce . . . .” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5563
    (a)(1)-(2). The Bureau must
    do so in the “manner prescribed” under the Administrative
    Procedure Act (“APA”), 
    5 U.S.C. §§ 551
     et seq. 
    12 U.S.C. § 5563
    (a). The CFPB can bring enforcement actions in either
    a court or an administrative proceeding. “The court (or the
    Bureau, as the case may be) in an action or adjudication
    proceeding brought under Federal consumer financial law,
    shall have jurisdiction to grant any appropriate legal or
    equitable relief . . . .” 
    Id.
     § 5565.
    2
    In 2012, the CFPB issued a final rule pursuant to 
    12 U.S.C. § 5563
    (e) to establish rules of practice for adjudication
    proceedings. 
    12 C.F.R. § 1081
    .
    The Director does not initiate investigations. Rather,
    “[t]he Assistant Director of the Office of Enforcement and the
    Deputy Assistant Directors of the Office of Enforcement have
    the nondelegable authority to initiate investigations,” 
    id.
    § 1080.4, just as they have the authority to close CFPB
    investigations, id. § 1080.11(c). If the investigation merits
    enforcement within the agency, Bureau lawyers commence
    the proceeding with the filing of a Notice of Charges, id.
    § 1081.200, as was done here, J.A. 41, and the matter
    proceeds to a hearing.
    The “hearing officer,” defined as “an administrative law
    judge or any other person duly authorized to preside at a
    hearing,” id. § 1081.103, is vested with wide adjudicatory
    authority, including the power to issue subpoenas, order
    depositions, hold settlement conferences, and “rule upon, as
    justice may require, all procedural and other motions
    appropriate    in    adjudication        proceedings.”     Id.
    § 1081.104(b)(2), (3), (7), (10). Most importantly, at the
    close of the administrative proceedings, “[t]he recommended
    decision shall be made and filed by the hearing officer who
    presided over the hearings . . . .” Id. § 1081.400(d).
    The Director of the Bureau acts as the chief adjudicatory
    official. Whether or not the parties choose to appeal the
    recommended decision, it goes to the CFPB Director, who
    “shall . . . either issue a final decision and order adopting the
    recommended decision, or order further briefing regarding
    any portion of the recommended decision.”                      Id.
    § 1081.402(b). If the Director determines that it would
    3
    “significantly aid[]” the decisional process, the Director may
    order oral argument. Id. § 1081.404(a). As the Director
    considers the recommended decision, the Director “will, to
    the extent necessary or desirable, exercise all powers which
    he or she could have exercised if he or she had made the
    recommended decision.” Id. § 1081.405(a). The Director’s
    final decision must be served on the parties and published in
    an order. Id. § 1081.405(e).
    The Director rendered a final decision and order as the
    chief adjudicatory official of the Bureau in this case. J.A. 1-
    40. That adjudication is the basis of the petition for review,
    Petition 1-3, and that adjudication provides the basis for our
    subject matter jurisdiction. Pet’r’s Br. 4.
    II.
    The adjudicatory nature of the order under review is
    material to the questions raised by the instant petition. We
    have an extensive line of authority, from the time of the
    Framers to the present, establishing that removal restrictions
    of officers performing adjudicatory functions intrude far less
    on the separation of powers than removal restrictions of
    officers who perform purely executive functions.
    From the time of the Constitution’s enactment, the
    Framers recognized that adjudication poses a special
    circumstance. Even James Madison, one of strongest and
    most articulate proponents “for construing [Article II] to give
    the President the sole power of removal in his responsibility
    for the conduct of the executive branch,” Myers v. United
    States, 
    272 U.S. 52
    , 117 (1926) (citation omitted),
    acknowledged the “strong reasons why” an executive officer
    who adjudicates disputes “between the United States and
    particular citizens . . . should not hold his office at the
    4
    pleasure of the Executive branch of the Government.” 1
    ANNALS OF CONG. 611-12 (1789) (Joseph Gales ed., 1834)
    (statement of James Madison). Consistent with Madison’s
    view, the Supreme Court has held that the evaluation of
    removal restrictions for an officer “will depend upon the
    character of the office.” Humphrey’s Executor v. United
    States, 
    295 U.S. 602
    , 631 (1935). As a result, the scrutiny of
    a removal restriction for an officer “with no duty at all related
    to either the legislative or judicial power,” differs from that of
    an officer who “perform[s] other specified duties as a
    legislative or as a judicial aid,” as the latter “must be free
    from executive control,” 
    id. at 627-28
    . The Court continued:
    We think it plain under the Constitution that
    illimitable power of removal is not possessed
    by the President in respect of officers of the
    character of those just named. The authority of
    Congress, in creating quasi legislative or quasi
    judicial agencies, to require them to act in
    discharge of their duties independently of
    executive control cannot well be doubted; and
    that authority includes, as an appropriate
    incident, power to fix the period during which
    they shall continue, and to forbid their removal
    except for cause in the meantime. For it is
    quite evident that one who holds his office
    only during the pleasure of another cannot be
    depended upon to maintain an attitude of
    independence against the latter’s will.
    
    Id. at 629
    .
    Relying upon the “philosophy of Humphrey’s Executor,”
    the Court later held that the power to remove “a member of an
    adjudicatory body” at will and without cause is not “given to
    5
    the President directly by the Constitution.” Wiener v. United
    States, 
    357 U.S. 349
    , 356 (1958).
    To be sure, the adjudicatory nature of an officer’s duties
    is not dispositive. The analysis is much more nuanced. The
    modern view is “that the determination of whether the
    Constitution allows Congress to impose a ‘good cause’-type
    restriction on the President’s power to remove an official
    cannot be made to turn on whether or not that official is
    classified as ‘purely executive.’” Morrison v. Olson, 
    487 U.S. 654
    , 689 (1988).         Thus, rather than “defin[ing] rigid
    categories of those officials who may or may not be removed
    at will by the President,” courts focus squarely on the
    separation-of-powers principle at stake: “ensur[ing] that
    Congress does not interfere with the President’s exercise of
    the ‘executive power’ and his constitutionally appointed duty
    to ‘take care that the laws be faithfully executed’ under
    Article II.” 
    Id. at 689-90
     (footnote omitted).
    Despite its rejection in Morrison of the simple
    categorization of officers, the Supreme Court was clear that it
    “d[id] not mean to suggest that an analysis of the functions
    served by the officials at issue is irrelevant.” 
    Id. at 691
    . As
    Madison recognized, the faithful execution of the laws may
    require that an officer has some independence from the
    President. To provide for due process and to avoid the
    appearance of impropriety, agency adjudications are
    structured to be “insulated from political influence” and to
    “contain many of the same safeguards as are available in the
    judicial process.” Butz v. Economou, 
    438 U.S. 478
    , 513
    (1978) (holding, among other things, that safeguards from
    political influence entitled the Secretary of Agriculture’s
    designee, who rendered final decisions in agency
    adjudications, to absolute immunity). The Article II inquiry is
    informed by the consistent recognition of the imperative to
    6
    safeguard the adjudicatory officer from undue political
    pressure. Thus, even if not dispositive, the quasi-judicial
    functions of the CFPB Director are still relevant to our
    inquiry, and those functions seriously undermine petitioners’
    separation-of-powers objection. See Free Enterprise Fund v.
    Pub. Co. Accounting Oversight Bd., 
    561 U.S. 477
    , 507 n.10
    (2010) (noting that its holding, which struck down two layers
    of good-cause removal restrictions for members of the Public
    Company Accounting Oversight Board, did not necessarily
    apply to administrative law judges who, “unlike members of
    the Board, . . . perform adjudicative rather than enforcement
    or policymaking functions”). 1
    1
    The substantive differences between the removal restrictions of
    Board members and ALJs provided another important distinction in
    Free Enterprise Fund. The tenure protection struck down in Free
    Enterprise Fund was “unusually high.” 
    561 U.S. at 503
    . The only
    violations of law that could lead to removal were violations of
    “provision[s] of [the Sarbanes-Oxley] Act, the rules of the
    [PCAOB], or the securities laws,” 
    15 U.S.C. § 7217
    (d)(3)(A), and
    Board members could only be removed if those violations or abuses
    were committed “willfully,” 
    id.
     § 7217(d)(3)(A)-(B). The Court
    noted that a Board member could not be removed even if, for
    example, he cheated on his taxes, even though such an action could
    greatly diminish the confidence that the member would faithfully
    carry out his or her duties. Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 503
    .
    By contrast, the removal standard for ALJs is quite modest.
    ALJs can be removed for “good cause,” 
    5 U.S.C. § 7521
    , which has
    been interpreted to require that an ALJ “act at all times in a manner
    that promotes public confidence in [] independence, integrity, and
    impartiality . . . and . . . avoid[s] impropriety and the appearance of
    impropriety,” a standard borrowed from the American Bar
    Association’s Model Code of Judicial Conduct. Long v. Soc. Sec.
    Admin., 
    635 F.3d 526
    , 533 (Fed. Cir. 2011). Accordingly, ALJs
    have been disciplined or removed for a wide variety of job-related
    7
    In sum, the Supreme Court has consistently rendered its
    “judgment that it was not essential to the President’s proper
    execution of his Article II powers that [quasi-judicial and
    quasi-legislative] agencies be headed up by individuals who
    were removable at will.” Morrison, 487 U.S at 691. Indeed,
    in his dissent in Morrison, Justice Scalia even acknowledged
    that “removal restrictions have been generally regarded as
    lawful” for independent agencies “which engage substantially
    in what has been called the ‘quasi-legislative activity’ of
    rulemaking” and “the ‘quasi-judicial’ function of
    adjudication.” Id. at 724-25 (citations omitted, emphasis
    added). Here, is there any doubt that the CFPB Director
    substantially engages in both of these activities? Of course
    not. In addition to the final adjudication authority described
    above, Congress granted the Director rulemaking authority for
    the Bureau. 
    12 U.S.C. § 5512
    (b). Thus, the Director (and the
    Bureau) fit squarely within the zone “generally regarded as
    lawful” by every Justice in Morrison and in the unbroken line
    of authority from the Supreme Court described above and in
    our Majority Opinion.
    misconduct, such as improperly using the imprimatur of the agency
    for personal business, Steverson v. Soc. Sec. Admin., 383 F. App’x
    939 (Fed. Cir. 2010); lack of productivity in comparison to
    colleagues, Shapiro v. Soc. Sec. Admin., 
    800 F.3d 1332
    , 1334-36
    (Fed. Cir. 2015); failure to follow mandatory office procedures,
    Brennan v. Dep’t of Health & Human Servs., 
    787 F.2d 1559
    , 1561
    (Fed. Cir. 1986), as well as for misbehavior not directly connected
    to official duties, such as domestic violence, Long, 
    635 F.3d 526
    .
    And in contrast to the Court’s concern in Free Enterprise Fund
    about the inability to remove a tax-cheating Board member, an ALJ
    has been fired for “financial irresponsibility” in failing to repay
    debts. See McEachern v. Macy, 
    341 F.2d 895
     (4th Cir. 1965).
    8
    III.
    Disagreeing with the weight of authority, the dissenters
    take two major tacks, neither of which is sufficient to
    overcome the Court’s precedent.
    First, the dissenters attempt to recast this case as more
    about the Director’s pure executive power of enforcement
    rather than about the quasi-judicial power of adjudication.
    Henderson Dissenting Op. 33; Kavanaugh Dissenting Op. 15-
    17, 20-23 & n.2. But what we have before us is the Director’s
    order of adjudication. Pet’r’s Br. 4 (Jurisdictional Statement).
    This essential detail, along with the fact that the Director has
    substantial adjudicative responsibilities, is minimized.
    This recasting is significant, because Judge Henderson
    contends that the Court’s precedents should be read to deem
    removal protections for a principal officer in violation of the
    separation of powers unless the officer’s “primary function is
    adjudication,” Henderson Dissenting Op. 33 (emphasis in
    original), and Judge Kavanaugh emphasizes over and again
    that this case is “about executive power,” Kavanaugh
    Dissenting Op. 1, because the CFPB Director has “substantial
    executive authority.” Id. at 3; see also id. at 5, 7, 8, 18, 68, 73
    (characterizing the Director’s “substantial executive power”
    or “authority”).
    This line of attack collapses under its own weight. The
    vast majority of independent agencies have significant
    enforcement and adjudicative responsibilities, and these
    shared duties are expressly addressed by the APA. 5 U.S.C.
    9
    § 554(d). If the dissenters were correct, then it would violate
    the separation of powers for any such independent agency to
    be headed by a principal officer with tenure protection. This
    has never been the law. At the time of Humphrey’s Executor,
    the Court was well aware that the Federal Trade Commission
    (“FTC”) exercised both enforcement, 
    15 U.S.C. §§ 45
    (b), 46,
    and adjudicative functions, Fed. Trade Comm’n v. Winsted
    Hosiery Co., 
    258 U.S. 483
    , 490 (1922), but it nonetheless
    upheld the removal protections of FTC Commissioners. 
    295 U.S. at 629
    . Similarly, in Free Enterprise Fund, the Court
    was not troubled that Securities and Exchange Commission
    (“SEC”) Commissioners enjoyed strong removal protection,
    
    561 U.S. at 487
    , even though the Commission quite obviously
    both enforces and adjudicates. As explained by the Court in
    Morrison, the cramped view of the separation of powers
    favored by the dissenters must be rejected:
    The dissent says that the language of Article II
    vesting the executive power of the United
    States in the President requires that every
    officer of the United States exercising any part
    of that power must serve at the pleasure of the
    President and be removable by him at will. . . .
    This rigid demarcation—a demarcation
    incapable of being altered by law in the
    slightest degree, and applicable to tens of
    thousands of holders of offices neither known
    nor foreseen by the Framers—depends upon an
    extrapolation from general constitutional
    language which we think is more than the text
    will bear. It is also contrary to our holding in
    United States v. Perkins, [
    116 U.S. 483
    ,]
    decided more than a century ago.
    Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 690, n.29
     (emphasis added).
    10
    In sum, the dissenters have warped the current meaning of
    Myers.     There is no rule requiring direct presidential
    supervision of all officers, with the only potential exception
    for “purely” judicial officers or officers having no
    “substantial” executive power; rather, Humphrey’s Executor
    “narrowly confined the scope of the Myers decision to include
    only ‘all purely executive officers.’” Wiener, 
    357 U.S. at 352
    (quoting Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 628
    ). 2
    In their other major line of attack, the dissenters seek to
    overcome the precedent upholding tenure protection for
    officers with significant quasi-judicial and quasi-legislative
    responsibilities by distinguishing the CFPB, headed by a
    single director, from independent agencies headed by multi-
    member commissions. In this regard, a few other points bear
    mention.
    2
    The dissenters seek to cast aspersions on Humphrey’s
    Executor, painting it as an outlier in the Court’s separation-of-
    powers jurisprudence. See Kavanaugh Dissenting Op. 61
    n.18; Henderson Dissenting Op. 36-37. Perhaps all that need
    be said in response is that the case binds us, as an inferior
    court. U.S. Const. Art. III, § 1. Nonetheless, it is worth
    noting that Humphrey’s Executor was a unanimous opinion
    and that all four Justices from the Myers majority who
    remained on the Court nine years later joined the opinion;
    indeed, one of those members of the Myers majority, Justice
    Sutherland, wrote the opinion. It thus seems inconceivable
    that the Court in Humphrey’s Executor did not understand
    what part of Myers was its holding rather than dictum.
    11
    As noted in the Majority Opinion, Congress mostly
    reshuffled existing responsibilities from other entities to the
    CFPB. Maj. Op. 11-12. I do not read the dissenting opinions
    as suggesting that the Constitution prohibits Congress from
    reassigning responsibilities from existing independent
    agencies to a new independent agency. Instead, the dissenters
    contend that the Constitution requires the new independent
    agency to be headed by multiple members in order to receive
    tenure protection; Congress cannot depart from that model.
    However, just as “[o]ur constitutional principles of separated
    powers are not violated . . . by mere anomaly or innovation,”
    Mistretta v. United States, 
    488 U.S. 361
    , 385 (1989), I do not
    believe that the concept of “two heads are better than one” has
    been elevated to a constitutional requirement of agency
    leadership. Single individuals have been entrusted with
    important decision-making authority throughout our
    government from the Founding, see Maj. Op. 42-43, so I am
    not swayed by the dissenters’ suggestion that the possibility
    of poor decisionmaking creates a constitutional defect.
    For our separation-of-powers analysis, there are two
    critical questions: How much, if at all, does the single-
    director structure decrease the agency’s accountability to the
    President in comparison to a multi-member agency? And is
    the President’s control so diminished as to “interfere
    impermissibly with his constitutional obligation to ensure
    faithful execution of the laws”? Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 693
    .
    As the Majority Opinion points out, the assumption that the
    single-director structure gives the President less control over
    the agency is dubious at best. Maj. Op. 43-45. Furthermore,
    we have a “duty . . . to construe [the CFPB] statute in order to
    save it from constitutional infirmities” and to avoid
    “overstat[ing] the matter” when describing the power and
    independence of the Director. Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 682
    . I
    12
    fear the dissenters have overstated the power of the Director
    and understated the checks on that power.
    I grant that having a single person in charge of the CFPB
    is different than having a multi-member body, but we cannot
    downplay the fact that Congress also required extensive
    coordination, expert consultation, and oversight of the
    Director. If much was given to the Director, then much was
    also required:
    1. The CFPB is required to “coordinate” with the SEC,
    FTC, Commodity Futures Trading Commission
    (“CFTC”), and other federal and state regulators “to
    promote consistent regulatory treatment of consumer
    financial and investment products and services.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5495
    .         There are numerous other
    “coordination” requirements. See, e.g., 
    id.
     § 5515(b)(2)
    (requiring coordination with prudential regulators and
    state bank regulatory authorities), § 5516(d)(2)
    (requiring coordination with prudential regulators for
    enforcement actions against banks).
    2. The Director must establish a Consumer Advisory
    Board, full of experts, to “advise and consult with the
    Bureau” at least twice a year. 
    12 U.S.C. § 5494
    (a), (c).
    3. The CFPB is required to “consult” with other federal
    agencies prior to proposing new rules to ensure
    “consistency with prudential, market, or systemic
    objectives administered by such agencies.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5512
    (b)(2)(B).
    4. The CFPB is not only required to continue the
    consultation during the comment process regarding the
    category of proposed rules described above, but if any
    13
    agency objects to the proposed rule, the CFPB must
    also “include in the adopting release a description of
    the objection and the basis for the Bureau decision, if
    any, regarding such objection.”           
    12 U.S.C. § 5512
    (b)(2)(C).
    5. The CFPB must also consult with other federal
    agencies prior to promulgating a rule prohibiting
    unfair, abusive, or deceptive practices, again to ensure
    “consistency.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5531
    (e).
    6. The CFPB is required to “conduct an assessment of
    each significant rule or order” addressing “the
    effectiveness of the rule or order in meeting the
    purposes and objectives” of the statute and the goals of
    the agency, using the “available evidence and any data
    that the [CFPB] reasonably may collect.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5512
    (d)(1).
    7. Along with creating the CFPB, Congress created the
    Financial Stability Oversight Council (“FSOC”), 
    12 U.S.C. § 5321
    , and gave it authority to stay or veto any
    final CFPB rule by a two-thirds vote of its members if
    the Council finds that the regulation “would put the
    safety and soundness of the United States banking
    system or the stability of the financial system of the
    United States at risk.” 
    Id.
     § 5513.
    In sum, Congress guided (and limited) the discretion of the
    Director of the CFPB in a very robust manner. Of course, the
    CFPB is not the only independent agency with consultation
    requirements, and the Dodd-Frank Act imposed new
    consultation requirements upon a number of agencies. See
    Jody Freeman & Jim Rossi, Agency Coordination in Shared
    Regulatory Space, 125 HARV. L. REV. 1131, 1168 (2012);
    14
    Susan Block-Lieb, Accountability and the Bureau of
    Consumer Financial Protection, 7 BROOK. J. CORP. FIN. &
    COM. L. 25, 55-56 (2012). But “[t]he Dodd-Frank Act does
    not subject any of the other federal financial regulators to
    similar overarching coordination requirements . . . .” U.S.
    GOV’T ACCOUNTABILITY OFFICE, GAO-12-151, DODD FRANK
    ACT REGULATIONS: IMPLEMENTATION COULD BENEFIT FROM
    ADDITIONAL ANALYSES AND COORDINATION 22 (2011). With
    the amount of “coordination” and “consultation” required of
    the CFPB by statute, there can be no doubt that the Director
    operates with as much expert advice as any other independent
    agency. Congress went even further, repeatedly requiring the
    Director to seek “consistency” with other agencies, and in
    some circumstances, requiring the Director to explain why he
    or she failed to heed an objection of another agency.
    Congress even required the Director to give a yearly after-
    action report assessing the merits of every significant rule or
    order.
    But here’s the kicker: Congress created a new entity, the
    above-described Financial Stability Oversight Council, with
    veto power over any rule promulgated by the Director that the
    Council believes will “put the safety and soundness of the
    United States banking system or the stability of the financial
    system of the United States at risk.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5513
    . Any
    member of the Council can file a petition to stay or revoke a
    rule, which can be granted with a two-thirds majority vote.
    See 
    id.
     Thus, if the Director’s decisionmaking goes awry on a
    critical rulemaking, a multi-member body of experts can step
    in. Significantly, a supermajority of persons on the Council
    are designated by the President. 3
    3
    The Secretary of the Treasury, who serves at the pleasure of the
    President, chairs the Council. 
    12 U.S.C. § 5321
    (b)(1)(A). In
    15
    The veto is powerful enough, but the filing of a petition
    alone will trigger congressional oversight, since it “shall be
    published in the Federal Register and transmitted
    contemporaneously with filing to the Committee on Banking,
    Housing, and Urban Affairs of the Senate and the Committee
    on Financial Services of the House of Representatives.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5513
    (b)(2). The choice Congress made to impose
    additional statutory requirements on CFPB action makes the
    CFPB Director more accountable to the President, not less. 4
    addition, the chairpersons of five independent agencies serve on the
    Council, each of whom the President has the opportunity to appoint
    either at the outset or near the beginning of the administration. See
    15 U.S.C. § 78d (SEC Chair); 
    12 U.S.C. § 1812
    (b)(1) (Chair of the
    Federal Deposit Insurance Corporation); 
    7 U.S.C. § 2
    (a)(2)(B)
    (Chair of the Commodity Futures Trading Commission); 12 U.S.C.
    § 1752a(b)(1) (Chair of the National Credit Union Association); 
    12 U.S.C. §§ 241
    , 242, 244 (Chair of the Federal Reserve Board of
    Governors, whose four-year term expires just after the first year of
    a new presidential administration taking office in a presidential
    election year). Only four members of the FSOC have terms longer
    than four years and are thus potentially not appointed by a one-term
    President:     the CFPB Director (five-year term), 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (c)(1); the Director of the Federal Housing Finance
    Association (five-year term), 
    12 U.S.C. § 4512
    (b)(2); the
    Comptroller of the Currency (five-year term), 
    12 U.S.C. § 2
    ; and
    the “independent member” of the FSOC (six-year term), 
    12 U.S.C. §§ 5321
    (b)(1)(J), (c)(1).
    4
    Judge Kavanaugh makes much of the fact that the CFPB
    Director’s five-year term could result in a one-term President being
    unable to remake the agency by naming a CFPB Director during his
    or her tenure. Kavanaugh Dissenting Op. 53-54. However, the
    same can be said of the Federal Reserve, where, absent the
    circumstance of a Board Member’s early retirement, a President can
    never appoint a majority of the Board. See 
    12 U.S.C. §§ 241
    , 242
    16
    These myriad coordination and consultation requirements
    have further significance for the separation-of-powers
    analysis: They give the President more potential ammunition
    to remove the CFPB Director than for the average officer.
    For-cause removal protections are meaningful as a bulwark
    against undue political influence in agencies relied on for
    their expertise and independent judgment. But the standard of
    removal for “inefficiency, neglect of duty, or malfeasance in
    office” does not afford officers who head independent
    agencies with unlimited discretion or untrammeled power.
    Here, the Director’s failure to abide by the stringent statutory
    requirements of consultation or coordination would almost
    certainly constitute “neglect of duty.” And the promulgation
    of a rule contrary to consensus expert advice without
    sufficient grounds or explanation would subject the Director
    to risk of removal for inefficiency.
    Although the Supreme Court has largely avoided the task
    of spelling out precisely what conduct constitutes “cause” to
    remove officers under Humphrey’s Executor, “inefficiency,
    neglect of duty, or malfeasance in office” provides a workable
    standard, and lower courts have long adjudicated the meaning
    of those terms in similar contexts. Congress first used
    “inefficiency, neglect of duty, or malfeasance in office” as a
    removal standard for officers of the Interstate Commerce
    Commission and the General Board of Appraisers in 1887 and
    1890, respectively. See An Act to Regulate Commerce, ch.
    104, § 11, 
    24 Stat. 379
    , 383 (1887); An Act to Simplify the
    Laws in Relation to the Collection of the Revenues, ch. 407,
    (establishing a seven-member Board with staggered, fourteen-year
    terms, removable only for cause).
    17
    § 12, 
    26 Stat. 131
    , 136 (1890). 5 The use of “efficiency” as a
    standard for removal of federal employees arose historically
    in the context of civil-service statutes around the same time
    period – the late-nineteenth and early-twentieth centuries. See
    Myers, 
    272 U.S. at
    74-75 & nn. 30-32 (Brandeis, J.,
    dissenting) (collecting statutes). The Lloyd-LaFollette Act of
    1912, 
    5 U.S.C. § 7513
     – like its predecessor, the Pendleton
    Act of 1883 – sought to establish a civil service based on
    merit and unshackled from patronage. The Lloyd-LaFollette
    Act included language providing that employees in
    competitive service could be removed “only for such cause as
    will promote the efficiency of the service.” 
    Id.
     § 7513(a).
    As interpreted by courts and agencies for nearly a
    century, “inefficiency” provides a broad standard allowing for
    the removal of employees whose performance is found
    lacking.      What constitutes “inefficiency” has varied
    depending on the context of the officer or employee’s
    responsibilities and functions, but it is best described as
    incompetence or deficient performance. See, e.g., Burnap v.
    United States, 
    53 Ct. Cl. 605
    , 609 (Ct. Cl. 1918) (upholding
    the removal of a landscape architect for inefficiency due to his
    5
    Because Congress did not specify a term of years for appraisers,
    the Supreme Court concluded that inefficiency, neglect of duty and
    malfeasance were not exclusive grounds for removal, because
    otherwise, the office of appraiser would be a lifetime appointment.
    Shurtleff v. United States, 
    189 U.S. 311
    , 316 (1903). The Court
    “recognized and applied the strong presumption against the creation
    of a life tenure in a public office under the federal government.”
    De Castro v. Bd. of Comm’rs of San Juan, 
    322 U.S. 451
    , 462
    (1944) (explaining Shurtleff); see also Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 622-23
     (finding the removal grounds exclusive for FTC
    Commissioners, because the statute provided for a fixed term of
    office, distinguishing Shurtleff).
    18
    failure to heed his supervisor’s instructions to cease working
    for private clients), aff’d, 
    252 U.S. 512
    , 519-20 (1920)
    (rejecting procedural and constitutional challenges, and
    upholding the removal); Thomas v. Ward, 
    225 F.2d 953
    , 954
    (D.C. Cir. 1955) (upholding a Navy personnel officer’s
    removal for inefficiency when the officer was charged with
    “lack of professional knowledge and supervisory ability; poor
    personnel management and public relations and acts of
    misconduct involving failure to carry out orders; disloyalty to
    his superiors and untruthfulness in official relations with other
    employees”); Seebach v. Cullen, 
    338 F.2d 663
    , 665 (9th Cir.
    1964) (upholding the dismissal of an IRS Auditor for
    “[i]nefficiency in handling tax cases as evidenced by technical
    and procedural errors, substandard report writing, and lack of
    proper audit techniques”); King v. Hampton, 
    412 F. Supp. 827
    (E.D. Va. 1976) (upholding the removal of a Navy electronics
    engineer for inefficiency); Alpert v. United States, 
    161 Ct. Cl. 810
     (Ct. Cl. 1963) (inefficiency removal sustained when an
    employee of a VA Hospital was charged with
    “Insubordination, Tardiness, Improper Conduct, and
    Unsatisfactory Interpersonal Relationships”); DeBusk v.
    United States, 
    132 Ct. Cl. 790
     (Ct. Cl. 1955) (upholding
    removal of VA loan examiner for failure to “promote the
    efficiency of the service” based on charges of his disrespect of
    supervisors and failure to follow instructions); Fleming v.
    U.S. Postal Serv., 
    30 M.S.P.R. 302
    , 308 (M.S.P.B. 1986)
    (upholding removal for “inefficiency” based on numerous
    unscheduled absences from work); see also Arnett v.
    Kennedy, 
    416 U.S. 134
    , 158-64 (1974) (upholding
    “efficiency” standard against vagueness challenge); see
    generally, 1 PETER BROIDA, A GUIDE TO MERIT SYSTEMS
    PROTECTION BOARD LAW & PRACTICE 1669, 1713 (Dewey
    Publ’ns Inc. 2012) (discussing cases upholding removal of
    federal employees for inefficiency); 1 ISIDORE SILVER,
    PUBLIC EMPLOYEE DISCHARGE & DISCIPLINE § 3.23 (John
    19
    Wiley & Sons Inc. 2d ed. 1995) (discussing the role of MSPB
    in adjudicating disputes over removals for inefficiency);
    OFFICE OF PERSONNEL MANAGEMENT, FEDERAL PERSONNEL
    MANUAL 752-15 (1989) (on file in the D.C. Circuit Library)
    (collecting cases upholding removal of federal employees for
    inefficiency); ROBERT VAUGHN, PRINCIPLES OF CIVIL SERVICE
    LAW §§ 1, 5 (Matthew Bender & Co. 1976) (discussing the
    origins of civil service law and the “efficiency” standard).
    In sum, this body of authority from the past century
    demonstrates that the CFPB Director would be subject to
    supervision and discipline for “inefficiency” if he or she
    failed to comply with the various statutory mandates of
    coordination and consultation.        It also shows that
    “inefficiency” is relatively broad and provides a judicially
    manageable standard. I agree with the overall sentiment of
    Judge Griffith that the broad removal authority gives the
    President adequate ability to supervise the CFPB Director, 6
    Griffith Concurring Op. 25, but I do not agree that
    “inefficiency” is properly construed to allow removal for
    mere policy disagreements. Such a capacious construction
    would essentially remove the concept of “independence” from
    “independent agencies.” After all, Congress established the
    CFPB as “an independent bureau,” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (a), and
    an agency subject to the President’s blanket control over its
    policy choices is hardly “independent.” See, e.g., NEW
    OXFORD AMERICAN DICTIONARY 857 (2d ed. 2005) (“free
    from outside control; not depending on another’s authority”);
    6
    Of course, the above presumes that the President is forced to take
    formal action against a poorly performing Director. Defending
    against a personnel action brought by the President has grave
    personal and professional consequences. Thus, a Director under
    pressure may decide to step down to “spend more time with the
    family,” preferring a soft landing to an ignominious expulsion.
    20
    BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY 838 (9th ed. 2009) (“Not subject
    to the control or influence of another”); WEBSTER’S THIRD
    NEW INTERNATIONAL DICTIONARY 1148 (1993) (“not subject
    to control by others: not subordinate”); THE AMERICAN
    HERITAGE DICTIONARY 654 (2d College ed. 1985) (“1.
    Politically autonomous; self-governing. 2. Free from the
    influence, guidance, or control of another . . . .”); see also 5
    THE CENTURY DICTIONARY AND CYCLOPEDIA 3055 (1911)
    (“Not dependent; not requiring the support or not subject to
    the control or controlling influence of others; not relying on
    others for direction or guidance”); HENRY CAMPBELL BLACK,
    A LAW DICTIONARY 616 (2d ed. 1910) (“Not dependent; not
    subject to control, restriction, modification, or limitation from
    a given outside source”); NOAH WEBSTER, A COMPENDIOUS
    DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE 156 (1806) (“not
    subject to control, free . . . .”). Black’s Law Dictionary has
    traced the term “independent agency” back to 1902 and
    defines it as “a federal agency, commission, or board that is
    not under the direction of the executive . . . .” BLACK’S LAW
    DICTIONARY 71-72 (9th ed. 2009) (emphasis added).
    Thus, even if the meaning of “inefficiency” could be
    construed, in isolation, as broadly as Judge Griffith contends,
    “[i]n expounding a statute, we must not be guided by a single
    sentence or member of a sentence, but look to the provisions
    of the whole law, and to its object and policy.” U.S. Nat. Bank
    of Oregon v. Indep. Ins. Agents of Am., Inc., 
    508 U.S. 439
    ,
    455 (1993) (quoting United States v. Heirs of Boisdore, 49
    U.S. (8 How.) 113, 122 (1849)). The removal standard must
    be interpreted in light of the fact that Congress designated the
    CFPB as “an independent bureau,” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (a), and
    even if agency independence exists on a spectrum, Griffith
    Concurring Op. 23-24, the spectrum has a limit. The essence
    of an independent agency is that it “be independent of
    executive authority, except in its selection, and free to
    21
    exercise its judgment without the leave or hindrance of [the
    President],” Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 625
    . Judge
    Griffith’s broad reading of the removal power is inconsistent
    with the common understanding of “independent” and “would
    render part of the statute entirely superfluous, something we
    are loath to do.” Cooper Indus., Inc. v. Aviall Servs., Inc., 
    543 U.S. 157
    , 166 (2004). See also Maj. Op. 30-34 (discussing
    the historical independence of financial regulators). This is
    why the interpretation of “inefficiency” for lower-level
    federal workers is instructive, but not dispositive, because no
    one imagines that federal employees are entitled to be
    “independent” of their bosses in the way Congress clearly
    intended the Director of the CFPB to remain “independent”
    from the President.
    Although the dissenters take great pains to distinguish the
    single-director structure of the CFPB from the multi-member
    structure of other agencies, they fail to show that this
    structural difference so impairs presidential control that it
    poses a constitutional problem. Or even that it provides the
    President less control over the CFPB than over other
    independent agencies. The upshot of the dissenters’ cramped
    reading of the Supreme Court’s separation-of-powers
    jurisprudence is that the President cannot exercise meaningful
    control over the Executive branch without the ability to
    remove all principal officers for any reason (or no reason at
    all). That is not the import of the Supreme Court’s
    separation-of-powers cases from Myers to Free Enterprise
    Fund. Those cases establish constitutional boundaries which
    the CFPB falls well within.
    ****
    While the Constitution requires that the President be
    permitted to hold principal and inferior officers to account, it
    22
    also accommodates – and may, at times, even require – a
    degree of independence for those officers who perform quasi-
    judicial and quasi-legislative functions. So here. And just as
    the commissioners on a multi-member board must consult
    with each other before acting, the CFPB Director is required
    to consult with a plethora of colleagues and experts.
    Furthermore, the unique combination of oversight provisions
    in the Dodd-Frank Act gives the President greatly enhanced
    control over the CFPB compared to other independent
    agencies.
    A proper balancing of these considerations against the
    factors that arguably diminish the President’s control requires
    that we uphold the present “good cause” tenure protections
    applicable to the CFPB Director. In sum, “[I] do not think
    that this limitation as it presently stands sufficiently deprives
    the President of control over the [CFPB Director] to interfere
    impermissibly with his constitutional obligation to ensure the
    faithful execution of the laws,” Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 693
    . I
    therefore concur in the denial of the constitutional claim in the
    petition.
    GRIFFITH, Circuit Judge, concurring in the judgment:1
    I agree that the challenged features of the CFPB do not violate
    the Constitution, but for different reasons than the majority. My
    colleagues debate whether the agency’s single-Director
    structure impermissibly interferes with the President’s ability
    to supervise the Executive Branch. But to make sense of that
    inquiry, we must first answer a more fundamental question:
    How difficult is it for the President to remove the Director? The
    President may remove the CFPB Director for “inefficiency,
    neglect of duty, or malfeasance in office.” After reviewing
    these removal grounds, I conclude they provide only a minimal
    restriction on the President’s removal power, even permitting
    him to remove the Director for ineffective policy choices.
    Therefore, I agree that the CFPB’s structure does not
    impermissibly interfere with the President’s ability to perform
    his constitutional duties.
    I
    Although most principal officers of Executive Branch
    agencies serve at the pleasure of the President as at-will
    employees, in Humphrey’s Executor v. United States, 
    295 U.S. 602
     (1935), the Supreme Court held that Congress may protect
    some principal officers by specifying the grounds upon which
    the President may remove them from office. The Court
    permitted Congress to establish these for-cause removal
    protections for officers who carry out “quasi judicial” and
    “quasi legislative” tasks, but not those who perform “purely
    executive” functions. 
    Id. at 629-32
    .
    Some fifty years later in Morrison v. Olson, 
    487 U.S. 654
    (1988), the Supreme Court recast the inquiry established in
    Humphrey’s Executor. The Court’s evaluation of the
    1
    Although I concur in the majority’s reinstatement of the
    panel’s statutory holding, I concur only in the judgment regarding
    the constitutional question.
    2
    “functions” performed by an officer did not “define rigid
    categories” but only sought to “ensure that Congress does not
    interfere with the President’s exercise of the ‘executive power’
    and his constitutionally appointed duty to ‘take care that the
    laws be faithfully executed’ under Article II.” 
    Id. at 689-90
    (quoting U.S. Const. art. II, §§ 1, 3). According to the Morrison
    Court, “the real question is whether the removal restrictions are
    of such a nature that they impede the President’s ability to
    perform his constitutional duty, and the functions of the
    officials in question must be analyzed in that light.” Id. at 691;
    see also id. at 692 (asking whether a restriction “impermissibly
    burdens” or “interfere[s] impermissibly” with the President’s
    constitutional obligations). More recently, in Free Enterprise
    Fund v. Public Company Accounting Oversight Board, 
    561 U.S. 477
     (2010), the Supreme Court applied Morrison’s test to
    strike down a particularly restrictive removal scheme, holding
    that “multilevel protection from removal . . . . contravenes the
    President’s ‘constitutional obligation to ensure the faithful
    execution of the laws.’” 
    Id. at 484
     (quoting Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 693
    ).2
    In this case, my colleagues conduct the Morrison inquiry
    by debating how the CFPB’s novel institutional design affects
    the President’s supervision of the agency. They focus on the
    agency’s single-Director structure and consider whether a
    single agency head is more or less responsive to the President
    than a multimember commission. And they debate whether,
    2
    I agree with Judge Kavanaugh’s statements in footnotes 7 and
    18 of his dissent: Humphrey’s Executor and Morrison appear at odds
    with the text and original understanding of Article II. The Framers
    understood that the President’s constitutional obligations entitle him
    to remove executive officers; the Supreme Court said as much in
    Free Enterprise Fund. But until the Court addresses this tension, we
    are bound to faithfully apply Humphrey’s Executor and Morrison to
    the question before us.
    3
    because of the single Director’s five-year term, a one-term
    President has sufficient supervisory power over the CFPB.
    Although these difficult questions may matter in a future case,
    we cannot understand their constitutional significance in this
    case until we know the strength of the Director’s removal
    protection.
    For-cause removal protections are generally considered
    the defining feature of independent agencies. See Free
    Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 483
    .3 But not all removal
    protections are created equal. See 
    id. at 502-03
     (emphasizing
    that the “unusually high” removal standard that protected the
    Board members in that case “present[ed] an even more serious
    threat to executive control”). Here, the President may remove
    the CFPB Director for “inefficiency, neglect of duty, or
    malfeasance in office.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (c)(3). Until we know
    what these causes for removal mean and how difficult they are
    to satisfy, we cannot determine whether the CFPB’s novel
    3
    Legal commentators have traditionally agreed that for-cause
    removal protection is an essential characteristic of independent
    agencies. In recent years some scholars have argued that other
    factors—various indicia of independence, political considerations,
    and agency conventions—must also be considered when assessing
    agency independence. See generally Rachel E. Barkow, Insulating
    Agencies: Avoiding Capture Through Institutional Design, 
    89 Tex. L. Rev. 15
     (2010); Lisa Schultz Bressman & Robert B. Thompson,
    The Future of Agency Independence, 
    63 Vand. L. Rev. 599
     (2010);
    Kirti Datla & Richard L. Revesz, Deconstructing Independent
    Agencies (and Executive Agencies), 
    98 Cornell L. Rev. 769
     (2013);
    Aziz Z. Huq, Removal as a Political Question, 
    65 Stan. L. Rev. 1
    (2013); Adrian Vermeule, Conventions of Agency Independence, 
    113 Colum. L. Rev. 1163
     (2013). Yet even these scholars generally
    acknowledge that removal protections play an important role for
    independent agencies. Although the presence of removal protections
    may not be the last question when assessing agency independence, it
    is generally the first.
    4
    structural features unconstitutionally impede the President in
    his faithful execution of the laws. Indeed, the only reason we
    are debating the constitutionality of the CFPB in the first place
    is because the Director enjoys removal protection. That’s why
    the three-judge panel’s initial remedy simply eliminated the
    Director’s removal protection, thereby ameliorating the panel’s
    constitutional concerns with the CFPB’s structure. But if it is
    the Director’s removal protection that prompts our examination
    of the CFPB’s constitutionality, we must necessarily ask: How
    much does this removal protection actually constrain the
    President? If the Director is only marginally more difficult to
    remove than an at-will officer, then it is hard to imagine how
    the single-Director structure of the CFPB could impermissibly
    interfere with the President’s supervision of the Executive
    Branch.4
    4
    For decades legal scholars have suggested that the
    Humphrey’s Executor standard of “inefficiency, neglect of duty, or
    malfeasance in office” provides a low barrier to presidential removal.
    See, e.g., Lawrence Lessig & Cass R. Sunstein, The President and
    the Administration, 
    94 Colum. L. Rev. 1
    , 110-12 (1994) (“Purely as
    a textual matter . . . ‘inefficiency, neglect of duty, or malfeasance in
    office’ seem best read to grant the President at least something in the
    way of supervisory and removal power—allowing him, for example,
    to discharge, as inefficient or neglectful of duty, those
    commissioners who show lack of diligence, ignorance,
    incompetence, or lack of commitment to their legal duties. The
    statutory words might even allow discharge of commissioners who
    have frequently or on important occasions acted in ways inconsistent
    with the President’s wishes with respect to what is required by sound
    policy.”); Geoffrey P. Miller, Independent Agencies, 
    1986 Sup. Ct. Rev. 41
    , 86-87 (arguing that for-cause provisions like the standard
    from Humphrey’s Executor can and should be interpreted broadly to
    permit extensive presidential removal); Richard H. Pildes & Cass R.
    Sunstein, Reinventing the Regulatory State, 
    62 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1
    , 30
    (1995) (noting that the removal standard from Humphrey’s Executor
    may permit the President to remove officers for “inefficiency” if “he
    5
    Moreover, when addressing the constitutionality of
    independent agencies, the Supreme Court has directed us to
    focus on the President’s removal power instead of squinting at
    “bureaucratic minutiae” such as the structural intricacies
    debated by the parties here. Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 499-500
    . In Free Enterprise Fund, the Court chided the dissent
    for “dismiss[ing] the importance of removal as a tool of
    supervision” and instead focusing on political and institutional
    design features. 
    Id.
     Rather than relying on those features, the
    Court decided the case on the basis of the removal power,
    noting that the power to appoint and remove is “perhaps the
    key means” for the President to protect the constitutional
    prerogatives of the Executive Branch. 
    Id. at 501
    ; see also
    Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 695-96
     (noting that the Ethics in
    Government Act gave the President “several means of
    supervising or controlling” the independent counsel—“[m]ost
    importantly . . . the power to remove the counsel for good
    cause” (emphasis added) (internal quotation marks omitted));
    cf. Bowsher v. Synar, 
    478 U.S. 714
    , 727 (1986) (observing that
    the broad statutory removal provision allowing Congress to
    remove the Comptroller General was the “critical factor” in
    determining that Congress controlled the official).
    finds [them] incompetent because of their consistently foolish policy
    choices”); Lindsay Rogers, The Independent Regulatory
    Commissions, 52 Pol. Sci. Q. 1, 7-8 (1937) (claiming that “[n]o
    ‘institutional consequences’ are to be expected from the Humphrey
    case” because presidents will be able to remove officers with ease
    under the Humphrey’s Executor standard); Paul R. Verkuil, The
    Status of Independent Agencies After Bowsher v. Synar, 
    1986 Duke L.J. 779
    , 797 n.100 (noting that the Humphrey’s Executor standard
    “could be construed so as to encompass a general charge of
    maladministration, in which event even if the terms of removal are
    deemed to be exclusive they could still be satisfied by a removal by
    the President on the ground of policy incompatibility”).
    6
    A faithful application of Morrison requires us to determine
    the extent to which the CFPB’s removal standard actually
    prevents the President from removing the Director. In addition,
    this approach allows us to forgo, at least for now, the more
    vexing constitutional questions about institutional design. Cf.
    Vt. Agency of Nat. Res. v. U.S. ex rel. Stevens, 
    529 U.S. 765
    ,
    787 (2000) (explaining that “statutes should be construed so as
    to avoid difficult constitutional questions” (emphasis added));
    John F. Manning, The Independent Counsel Statute: Reading
    “Good Cause” in Light of Article II, 
    83 Minn. L. Rev. 1285
    ,
    1288 (1999) (arguing that, to avoid a “serious constitutional
    question,” the “good cause” removal provision in the Ethics in
    Government Act should be interpreted to allow removal for
    insubordination).
    II
    The Dodd-Frank Wall Street Reform and Consumer
    Protection Act provides that the President may remove the
    CFPB Director for “inefficiency, neglect of duty, or
    malfeasance in office.” Pub. L. No. 111-203, § 1011, 
    124 Stat. 1376
    , 1964 (2010) (codified at 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (c)(3)). For
    purposes of simplicity, I refer to this as the “INM standard.”
    Congress first used the INM standard in the late nineteenth
    century, see An Act To Regulate Commerce, ch. 104, § 11, 
    24 Stat. 379
    , 383 (1887), and it has since become a common for-
    cause removal provision for independent agencies, see e.g., An
    Act To Complete the Codification of Title 46, Pub. L. No. 109-
    304, § 301(b)(3), 
    120 Stat. 1485
    , 1488 (2006); ICC
    Termination Act of 1995, Pub. L. No. 104-88, § 701(a)(3), 
    109 Stat. 803
    , 933; Federal Mine Safety and Health Act of 1977,
    Pub. L. No. 95-164, § 113, 
    91 Stat. 1290
    , 1313; Federal
    Aviation Act of 1958, Pub. L. No. 85-726, § 201(a)(2), 
    72 Stat. 731
    , 741; Bituminous Coal Act of 1937, ch. 127, § 2(a), 
    50 Stat.
                              7
    72, 73; An Act To Create the Federal Trade Commission, ch.
    311, § 1, 
    38 Stat. 717
    , 718 (1914); see also Marshall J. Breger
    & Gary J. Edles, Established by Practice: The Theory and
    Operation of Independent Federal Agencies, 
    52 Admin. L. Rev. 1111
    , 1144-45 (2000) (describing the INM standard as the
    prototypical removal provision).
    In spite of the repeated use of the INM standard throughout
    the U.S. Code and its prominent role in Humphrey’s Executor,
    the meaning of the standard’s three grounds for removal remain
    largely unexamined. Congress has nowhere defined these
    grounds and the Supreme Court has provided little guidance
    about the conditions under which they permit removal. See
    Lessig & Sunstein, supra note 4, at 110-12.
    Some suggest that the Court in Humphrey’s Executor
    established that the INM standard prohibits the President from
    removing an agency officer for disagreements over policy. See,
    e.g., Concurring Op. at 19-21 (Wilkins, J.) (arguing that “mere
    policy disagreements” cannot satisfy the INM standard).5 After
    all, the Court noted in Humphrey’s Executor that President
    Roosevelt had mentioned to Humphrey their disagreement over
    the “policies” and “administering of the Federal Trade
    Commission.” 
    295 U.S. at 619
     (internal quotation marks
    omitted). However, Humphrey’s Executor established only that
    the President’s removal power is not “illimitable” and that the
    INM standard in the Federal Trade Commission Act is a
    permissible limitation. 
    Id. at 629
    . The Court nowhere
    addressed the extent to which the INM standard insulated
    Humphrey. When the Court determined that President
    5
    See also Abner S. Greene, Checks and Balances in an Era of
    Presidential Lawmaking, 
    61 U. Chi. L. Rev. 123
    , 171 n.187 (1994)
    (“It is fairly clear that the Humphrey’s Executor Court construed the
    removal language to prevent removal for policy disagreement.”).
    8
    Roosevelt failed to comply with the INM standard, it was not
    because he removed Humphrey for any specific policy the
    Commissioner had pursued. Instead, the President failed to
    comply with the INM standard because he expressly chose to
    remove Humphrey for no cause at all. See 
    id. at 612
    ; Bowsher,
    
    478 U.S. at
    729 n.8 (noting that in Humphrey’s Executor “the
    President did not assert that he had removed the Federal Trade
    Commissioner in compliance with one of the enumerated
    statutory causes for removal”).
    Humphrey’s Executor came to the Supreme Court as a
    certified question from the Court of Claims. The certificate
    stipulated as an undisputed fact that the President never
    removed Humphrey pursuant to the INM standard.6 And if this
    admission were not enough, one need look no further than
    President Roosevelt’s own words to see that he never purported
    to remove Humphrey under the INM standard. In his first letter
    to Humphrey, Roosevelt expressly disavowed any attempt to
    remove the Commissioner for cause: “Without any reflection
    at all upon you personally, or upon the service you have
    rendered in your present capacity, I find it necessary to ask for
    your resignation as a member of the Federal Trade
    Commission.” Certificate from Court of Claims at 4,
    Humphrey’s Executor v. United States, 
    295 U.S. 602
     (1935)
    (No. 667). After several more exchanges, the President wrote
    Humphrey saying: “I still hope that you will be willing to let
    me have your resignation. . . . I feel that, for your sake and for
    mine, it would be much better if you could see this point of
    view and let me have your resignation on any ground you may
    6
    Certificate from Court of Claims at 12, Humphrey’s Executor
    v. United States, 
    295 U.S. 602
     (1935) (No. 667) (“The decedent
    [Humphrey] was not removed from his office as aforesaid on account
    of any inefficiency, neglect of duty, or malfeasance in office.”). And
    by filing its demurrer, the United States “admit[ted] the facts stated
    in the petition to be true.” Id. at 15.
    9
    care to place it.” Id. at 6 (emphasis added). After Humphrey
    continued to resist, Roosevelt had had enough and simply
    asserted: “Effective as of this date you are hereby removed
    from the office of Commissioner of the Federal Trade
    Commission.” Id. at 8.7
    Moreover, even if Humphrey’s Executor could be read to
    address the extent to which the INM standard insulates an
    officer, it would offer little guidance. We would first need to
    assume that President Roosevelt’s general reference to the
    “policies” and “administering” of the FTC functioned as a
    ground for removal under one or more of the INM terms
    (though it is unclear which). And even then, the Court’s ruling
    tells us only that Roosevelt’s removal of Humphrey based on
    their ideological differences does not satisfy any of the three
    INM grounds. Abstract policy differences are not enough.8 But
    7
    See also 78 Cong. Rec. 1679 (1934) (statement of Sen. Simeon
    Fess) (reviewing President Roosevelt’s letters to Humphrey and
    noting that the President made no attempt to remove the
    Commissioner under the INM standard); William E. Leuchtenburg,
    The Supreme Court Reborn: The Constitutional Revolution in the
    Age of Roosevelt 60-63 (1996) (recounting a Cabinet meeting in
    which the President acknowledged that he erred by trying to pressure
    Humphrey gently instead of removing him for cause under the INM
    standard).
    8
    See Peter L. Strauss, The Place of Agencies in Government:
    Separation of Powers and the Fourth Branch, 
    84 Colum. L. Rev. 573
    , 615 (1984) (observing that President Roosevelt “had given
    Commissioner Humphrey no particular directive; he had asked no
    advice that Humphrey then refused to give; he did not, perceiving
    insubordination, direct [Humphrey] to leave” and therefore the Court
    did not address “whether the President could give the FTC
    Commissioners binding directives . . . or what might be the
    consequences of any failure of theirs to honor them”). The Supreme
    Court in Free Enterprise Fund likewise suggested in dicta that
    Humphrey’s Executor precludes removal based on “simple
    10
    that does not mean an officer’s policy choices can never satisfy
    the INM standard. Nor would such a categorical rule make
    much sense. Certainly some policy disagreements may justify
    removal under the INM standard. Judge Wilkins even
    acknowledges as much. See Concurring Op. at 16 (Wilkins, J.)
    (“[T]he promulgation of a rule contrary to consensus expert
    advice without sufficient grounds or explanation would subject
    the Director to risk of removal for inefficiency.”). All told,
    nothing in the facts, constitutional holding, or logic of
    Humphrey’s Executor protects an officer from removal if he
    pursues a particular policy that the President determines to be
    inefficient, neglectful, or malfeasant.
    The Supreme Court’s most substantive discussion of the
    INM terms came in Bowsher v. Synar. There, the Court
    declared unconstitutional Congress’s delegation of executive
    power to the Comptroller General, who was an official in the
    Legislative Branch. 
    478 U.S. at 728-34
    . By joint resolution,
    Congress could remove the Comptroller General for several
    statutorily specified causes including the three INM grounds.
    
    Id. at 728
    . In assessing Congress’s control over the Comptroller
    General, the Court emphasized that the INM terms are “very
    broad and, as interpreted by Congress, could sustain removal
    of a Comptroller General for any number of actual or perceived
    transgressions of the legislative will.” 
    Id. at 729
     (emphasis
    added). In other words, the Court determined that the INM
    removal grounds were so broad that Congress retained
    significant power to supervise and direct the Comptroller
    General. However, the Court did not proceed to explore the
    disagreement” with a principal officer’s “policies and priorities.” 
    561 U.S. at 502
    . In light of the facts of Humphrey’s Executor, the Court’s
    reference to “simple disagreement” over policy refers precisely to the
    abstract, generalized policy differences Roosevelt arguably invoked
    when removing Humphrey. See Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 618-19
    .
    11
    meaning of the individual grounds for removal because that
    was unnecessary to resolve the case. See 
    id. at 730
    .
    In sum, although Congress has provided little guidance on
    the meaning of the INM standard, the Supreme Court in
    Bowsher nevertheless recognized the general breadth of the
    INM terms. Picking up where Bowsher left off, we must now
    determine the meaning of the INM standard as we would any
    other statutory text and interpret it according to the traditional
    tools of construction.
    III
    I begin with the text of the INM standard: “The President
    may remove the Director for inefficiency, neglect of duty, or
    malfeasance in office.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (c)(3). Because
    Congress has not defined these terms, we give them their
    ordinary meaning. See Taniguchi v. Kan Pac. Saipan, Ltd., 
    566 U.S. 560
    , 566 (2012). To discern a term’s ordinary meaning,
    the Court generally begins with dictionaries. See, e.g., Sandifer
    v. U.S. Steel Corp., 
    134 S. Ct. 870
    , 876-77 (2014); Schindler
    Elevator Corp. v. U.S. ex rel. Kirk, 
    563 U.S. 401
    , 407-08
    (2011); MCI Telecomm’ns Corp. v. Am. Tel. & Tel. Co., 
    512 U.S. 218
    , 225-28 (1994). Based on the following analysis, I
    conclude that the ordinary meaning of the INM terms—
    particularly given the breadth of the “inefficiency” ground—
    allow the President enough supervisory authority to satisfy
    Morrison.
    A
    Generally, the ordinary meaning of a statutory term is
    fixed at the time the statute was adopted. See, e.g., Perrin v.
    United States, 
    444 U.S. 37
    , 42 (1979) (“[W]ords will be
    interpreted as taking their ordinary, contemporary, common
    12
    meaning.”); Antonin Scalia & Bryan A. Garner, Reading Law:
    The Interpretation of Legal Texts 78 (2012). Were we to strictly
    follow that approach here, we would seek to determine the
    ordinary meaning of each INM term in 2010 when the Dodd-
    Frank Act established the CFPB.
    But there is good reason to think that 2010 is not the
    correct time period to fix the ordinary meaning of the INM
    terms. The INM standard was first used by Congress in the
    Interstate Commerce Act in 1887 and has since been readopted
    in dozens of statutes spanning over a century. See supra Part II.
    “[W]hen Congress uses the same language in two statutes
    having similar purposes . . . it is appropriate to presume that
    Congress intended that text to have the same meaning in both
    statutes.” Smith v. City of Jackson, 
    544 U.S. 228
    , 233 (2005).9
    Since the INM standard was introduced in the Interstate
    Commerce Act, and approved by the Supreme Court in
    Humphrey’s Executor, Congress has deliberately and
    repeatedly borrowed its precise language. See Steven G.
    9
    See also Lawson v. FMR LLC, 
    134 S. Ct. 1158
    , 1176 (2014)
    (“[P]arallel text and purposes counsel in favor of interpreting . . .
    provisions consistently.”); Northcross v. Bd. of Educ. of Memphis
    City Sch., 
    412 U.S. 427
    , 428 (1973) (per curiam) (stating that when
    two provisions of different statutes share similar language, that is a
    “strong indication” they are to be interpreted consistently);
    Morissette v. United States, 
    342 U.S. 246
    , 263 (1952) (explaining
    that “where Congress borrows terms of art” it also borrows their
    meaning); see also William N. Eskridge Jr., Interpreting Law: A
    Primer on How To Read Statutes and the Constitution 123 (2016)
    (explaining that when “similar or identical terminology is not a
    coincidence, because the legislature has borrowed it from a previous
    law,” interpreters should consider maintaining “[c]onsistency across
    the U.S. Code”); Scalia & Garner, supra, at 323 (“[W]hen a statute
    uses the very same terminology as an earlier statute . . . it is
    reasonable to believe that the terminology bears a consistent
    meaning.”).
    13
    Calabresi & Christopher S. Yoo, The Unitary Executive:
    Presidential Power from Washington to Bush 287 (2008)
    (noting “Congress’s interest in imposing removal restrictions
    revived after Humphrey’s Executor”). Because Congress has
    regularly adopted the same INM text for the same general
    purpose—securing for agency officers at least a modicum of
    independence from the President—it is appropriate to attribute
    a uniform meaning to the INM standard that is consistent with
    the meaning it bore when it was first adopted. For these
    reasons, I rely on sources from the late-nineteenth and early
    twentieth centuries to determine the meaning of the standard.
    B
    The INM standard provides three separate grounds for
    removal. Although the standard may seem to be a unitary,
    general “for cause” provision, the Supreme Court has clarified
    that these three grounds carry discrete meanings. In
    Humphrey’s Executor the Court explained that the INM
    standard prevented the President from removing any officer
    except for “one or more of the causes named in the applicable
    statute.” 
    295 U.S. at 632
    . Moreover, Congress has enacted
    other statutes that include only two of the three INM removal
    grounds, indicating that each term bears a distinct meaning. For
    instance, weeks after the Court decided Humphrey’s Executor,
    Congress added a removal provision to the National Labor
    Relations Act, but it narrowed the INM standard by eliminating
    “inefficiency.” See ch. 372, § 3, 
    49 Stat. 449
    , 451
    (1935) (codified at 
    29 U.S.C. § 153
    ).
    Turning then to each basis for removal, “malfeasance” was
    defined as “the doing of that which ought not to be done;
    wrongful conduct, especially official misconduct; violation of
    a public trust or obligation; specifically, the doing of an act
    which is positively unlawful or wrongful, in contradistinction
    14
    to misfeasance.” 6 The Century Dictionary and Cyclopedia
    3593 (Benjamin E. Smith ed., 1911).10 “Neglect of duty” meant
    “failure to do something that one is bound to do,” a definition
    broadly echoed by courts and dictionaries alike. See A Law
    Dictionary 404-05, 810 (Henry Campbell Black ed., 2d ed.
    1910).11
    However, I concentrate on “inefficiency” because it is the
    broadest of the three INM removal grounds and best illustrates
    the minimal extent to which the INM standard restricts the
    President’s ability to supervise the Executive Branch.
    10
    Contemporary definitions of malfeasance are generally
    comparable. See, e.g., Malfeasance, Black’s Law Dictionary (10th
    ed. 2014) (“A wrongful, unlawful, or dishonest act; esp., wrongdoing
    or misconduct by a public official.”); see also Daugherty v. Ellis, 
    97 S.E.2d 33
    , 42-43 (W. Va. 1956) (collecting definitions of
    “malfeasance”). Courts have likewise interpreted malfeasance to
    mean corrupt conduct that is wholly wrongful, if not positively
    unlawful. See, e.g., State ex rel. Neal v. State Civil Serv. Comm’n, 
    72 N.E.2d 69
    , 71 (Ohio 1947) (“Nonfeasance is the omission of an act
    which a person ought to do; misfeasance is the improper doing of an
    act which a person might lawfully do; and malfeasance is the doing
    of an act which a person ought not to do at all.”) (quoting Bell v.
    Josselyn, 
    69 Mass. (3 Gray) 309
    , 311 (1855))). Courts have often
    interpreted “malfeasance in office” to require a wrongful act that was
    done in an official capacity. See, e.g., Arellano v. Lopez, 
    467 P.2d 715
    , 717-18 (N.M. 1970).
    11
    See also Cavender v. Cavender, 
    114 U.S. 464
    , 472-74 (1885)
    (finding “neglect of duty” when a trustee failed to perform his duty
    to invest the trust funds he had received); Holmes v. Osborn, 
    115 P.2d 775
    , 783 (Ariz. 1941) (defining “neglect of duty” as equivalent
    to “nonfeasance,” which means the “substantial failure to perform
    duty” (quoting State v. Barnett, 
    69 P.2d 77
    , 87 (Okla. Crim. App.
    1936))).
    15
    Dictionaries consistently defined the word “inefficiency”
    to mean ineffective or failing to produce some desired result.
    For example, one prominent turn-of-the-century dictionary
    defined “efficient” as “[a]cting or able to act with due effect;
    adequate in performance; bringing to bear the requisite
    knowledge, skill, and industry; capable; competent.” 3 The
    Century Dictionary and Cyclopedia, supra, at 1849. The same
    dictionary also defined “inefficient” to mean “[n]ot efficient;
    not producing or not capable of producing the desired effect;
    incapable; incompetent; inadequate.” 5 id. at 3072. Other
    dictionaries from the time period reiterated these definitions.
    See, e.g., 3 A New English Dictionary on Historical Principles
    52 (Henry Bradley ed., 1897) (defining “efficient” as
    “productive of effects; effective; adequately operative. Of
    persons: Adequately skilled”); 5 id. at 240 (James A.H. Murray
    ed., 1901) (defining “inefficient” as “[n]ot efficient; failing to
    produce, or incapable of producing, the desired effect;
    ineffective. Of a person: Not effecting or accomplishing
    something; deficient in the ability or industry required for what
    one has to do; not fully capable”).12 These dictionaries indicate
    12
    See also 2 Universal Dictionary of the English Language
    1817 (Robert Hunter & Charles Morris eds., 1897) (“Efficient”
    defined as “[c]ausing or producing effects or results; acting as the
    cause of effects; effective,” and as “[h]aving acquired a competent
    knowledge of or acquaintance with any art, practice, or duty;
    competent; capable”); id. at 2660 (“Inefficient” defined as “wanting
    the power to produce the desired or proper effect; inefficacious;
    powerless,” and as “[i]ncapable; wanting in ability or capacity;
    incompetent,” and as “[i]ncapable of or indisposed to effective
    action”); A Dictionary of the English Language 306 (James
    Stormonth ed., 1885) (“Efficient” defined as “producing effects;
    able; competent” and “effectual; effective; capable, efficacious”); id.
    at 491 (“Inefficient” defined as “not possessing the power or qualities
    desired; not efficacious; not active” and as “want of power or
    qualities to produce the effects desired; inactivity”); Webster’s
    16
    that an individual acts inefficiently when he fails to produce
    some desired effect or is otherwise ineffective in performing or
    accomplishing some task.
    This broad understanding of “inefficiency” is supported by
    other contemporaneous sources, such as the debates in
    Congress both before and after Humphrey’s Executor.
    Legislative history is a permissible tool of statutory
    interpretation when used “for the purpose of establishing
    linguistic usage” or “showing that a particular word or phrase
    is capable of bearing a particular meaning.” Scalia & Garner,
    supra, at 388. The debates in Congress during the early
    twentieth century display how the “inefficiency” ground for
    removal was understood by “intelligent and informed people of
    the time.” Antonin Scalia, Common-Law Courts in a Civil-Law
    System: The Role of United States Federal Courts in
    Interpreting the Constitution and Laws, in A Matter of
    Interpretation 3, 38 (Amy Gutmann ed., 1997).
    When discussing congressional control of the Comptroller
    General, who was protected by the INM terms, Members of
    International Dictionary of the English Language 472 (Noah Porter
    ed., 1898) (“Efficient” defined as “[c]ausing effects; producing
    results; that makes the effect to be what it is; actively operative; not
    inactive, slack, or incapable; characterized by energetic and useful
    activity”); id. at 756 (“Inefficient” defined as “not producing the
    effect intended or desired; inefficacious” and as “[i]ncapable of, or
    indisposed to, effective action; habitually slack or remiss; effecting
    little or nothing; as, inefficient workmen; an inefficient
    administrator”); Dictionary of the English Language 465 (Joseph E.
    Worcester ed., 1878) (“Efficient” defined as “[a]ctually producing or
    helping to produce effects; that produces directly a certain effect;
    causing effects; effective; efficacious; effectual; competent; able;
    active; operative”); id. at 747 (“Inefficient” defined as “[n]ot
    efficient; having little energy; inactive; ineffectual; inefficacious”).
    17
    Congress assumed the Comptroller could be removed for
    “inefficiency” if he failed to produce Congress’s desired
    effects. One Congressman maintained that if the Comptroller
    “was inefficient and was not carrying on the duties of his office
    as he should and as the Congress expected, [then Congress]
    could remove him” under the INM standard. 61 Cong. Rec.
    1081 (1921) (statement of Rep. Joseph Byrns) (emphases
    added); see also Bowsher, 
    478 U.S. at 728
     (inferring from this
    quotation that “inefficiency” constitutes a broad ground for
    removal). And another Member reiterated that when the
    Comptroller General “fails to do that work [of Congress] in a
    strong and efficient way, in a way the Congress would have the
    law executed, Congress has its remedy, and it can reach out and
    say that if the man is not doing his duty, if he is inefficient . . .
    he can be removed.” 61 Cong. Rec. at 1080 (statement of Rep.
    James Good) (emphases added). Thus, even though the
    Comptroller General was protected by the INM terms, the
    breadth of the “inefficiency” ground permitted Congress to
    remove him for failing to perform his duties in the manner
    Congress wanted.
    Three years after Humphrey’s Executor, Congress again
    considered the meaning of “inefficiency” when debating
    whether to include INM protections for officials of the Civil
    Aeronautics Authority. One Senator participating in the debate,
    fearing that the “inefficiency” cause did not provide sufficient
    independence for agency officials, even lamented: “If we
    provide that the President may remove a man for inefficiency,
    to my mind we give him unlimited power of removal. Under
    such authority he could have removed Mr. Humphrey, had he
    assigned that as a reason. . . . I do not see anything to be gained
    by discussing the legal question if we are to leave the word
    ‘inefficiency’ in the provision.” 83 Cong. Rec. 6865 (1938)
    (statement of Sen. William Borah). While this sentiment
    somewhat overstates the breadth of the “inefficiency” ground,
    18
    it reflects a broader truth exemplified in the Congressional
    Record: well-informed people in the early twentieth century
    understood the word “inefficiency” in a manner consistent with
    its dictionary definition.
    And for those who find it relevant, turning to the
    contemporary meaning of “inefficiency” would not change
    much in this analysis. The word has maintained a fairly stable
    meaning throughout the life of the INM standard. If anything,
    the contemporary definition of “inefficiency” has gradually
    become more expansive than it was at the time of Humphrey’s
    Executor. While older definitions of inefficiency largely
    discuss ineffectiveness, modern definitions have increasingly
    adopted an additional definition of “wasteful.” See, e.g.,
    Efficiency, Oxford English Dictionary (2d ed. 1989) (outlining
    the etymological evolution of “efficiency”). And this broad
    understanding of “inefficiency” is further supported by
    contemporary usage. See, e.g., Budget Hearing—Consumer
    Financial Protection Bureau Before the Subcomm. on
    Oversight & Investigations of the H. Comm. on Fin. Servs.,
    112th Cong. 8 (2012) (statement of Rep. Barney Frank,
    Ranking Member, H. Comm. on Fin. Servs.) (discussing the
    INM standard and stating that “this notion that the Director
    cannot be removed is fanciful. . . . No one doubts that if a
    change in Administration comes, and the new President
    disagrees with the existing Director, he or she can be removed.
    And proving that you were not inefficient, the burden of proof
    being on you, would be overwhelming” (emphases added)).13
    13
    One commentator has suggested that the contemporary
    understanding of official “inefficiency” is limited to instances of
    “pecuniary or temporal waste.” Kent H. Barnett, Avoiding
    Independent Agency Armageddon, 
    87 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1349
    ,
    1386 (2012) (citing The New Oxford American Dictionary 867
    (2001)). This assertion is unconvincing for at least two reasons. First,
    the very dictionary on which the commentator relies also defines
    19
    While ordinary usage reveals that an officer is
    “inefficient” when he fails to produce or accomplish some end,
    one might wonder who or what sets the end that the officer must
    efficiently pursue. In context, it is clear that the end cannot be
    set by the officer himself. After all, it is a removal ground that
    we are interpreting. Congress establishes the broad purposes of
    an independent agency, see, e.g., 
    12 U.S.C. § 5511
     (outlining
    the purpose, objectives, and functions of the CFPB), and the
    President assesses whether the officer has produced the
    “desired effect.” Put differently, an officer is inefficient when
    he fails to produce or accomplish the agency’s ends, as
    understood or dictated by the President operating within the
    parameters set by Congress.
    All told, the President retains significant authority under
    the INM standard to remove the CFPB Director. The breadth
    of the standard—particularly the inefficiency ground—
    “inefficient” to include the failure to “achiev[e] maximum
    productivity” and the failure “to make the best use of time or
    resources.” The New Oxford American Dictionary, supra, at 867
    (emphases added). These definitions would seemingly allow a
    finding of “inefficiency” any time the President determined an
    officer used resources imperfectly, for instance by pursuing an
    unwise policy. Second, a host of other contemporary dictionaries
    provide definitions of “inefficiency” that are entirely consistent with
    the turn-of-the-century usage presented here. See, e.g., Merriam-
    Webster’s Collegiate Dictionary (11th ed. 2014) (defining
    “inefficient” as: “not producing the effect intended or desired . . .
    wasteful of time or energy . . . incapable, incompetent”); Bryan A.
    Garner, Garner’s Modern American Usage 293, 462 (2009)
    (similar); Inefficient, The American Heritage Dictionary of the
    English Language (2017) (similar).
    20
    preserves in the President sufficient supervisory power to
    perform his constitutional duties.14
    14
    Judge Wilkins argues that my interpretation of “inefficiency”
    is overly broad because it permits removal for some policy
    disagreements. However, he does not address the dictionaries and
    other contemporaneous sources that support my analysis, nor the
    Supreme Court’s construal of the INM terms in Bowsher. Instead,
    Judge Wilkins relies on a line of cases pertaining to the termination
    of federal employees under the civil-service statutes, which permit
    termination of government employees “for such cause as will
    promote the efficiency of the service.” See Concurring Op. at 16-19
    (Wilkins, J.) (citing 
    5 U.S.C. § 7513
    ). I am skeptical that this line of
    cases can explain the meaning of “inefficiency” in the INM standard.
    Establishing that a removal will “promote the efficiency of the
    service” calls for different considerations than establishing that an
    officer himself has acted inefficiently. Moreover, every single case
    Judge Wilkins cites upholds the removal of an employee, so none
    demonstrate what official conduct—including policy choices—
    would fail to meet the inefficiency standard. And more
    fundamentally, if these civil-service cases controlled our
    interpretation of the INM standard, they would actually increase the
    President’s control of independent agencies. This court has held that
    the “efficiency of the service” standard permits removal for
    insubordination and for abstract policy differences. If this standard
    were applied to INM-protected officers, it’s unclear how agencies
    could retain any independence from presidential control. See, e.g.,
    Meehan v. Macy, 
    392 F.2d 822
    , 836 (D.C. Cir. 1968) (“There can be
    no doubt that an employee may be discharged for failure to obey
    valid instructions, or that a discharge for insubordination will
    promote the efficiency of the service.”), reh’g on other grounds, 
    425 F.2d 469
     (D.C. Cir. 1968), aff’d en banc, 
    425 F.2d 472
     (D.C. Cir.
    1969); Leonard v. Douglas, 
    321 F.2d 749
    , 750-53 (D.C. Cir. 1963)
    (upholding the removal of a Justice Department attorney whose
    “professional competence [wa]s not questioned” but whose superior
    found him to be generally “unsuitab[le]” for a “policy-determining
    position”).
    21
    C
    The INM standard provides a broad basis for removing the
    CFPB Director, but what steps must the President take to effect
    such a removal? It appears well-settled that an officer with
    removal protection is entitled to notice and some form of a
    hearing before removal. See Shurtleff v. United States, 
    189 U.S. 311
    , 313-14 (1903) (concluding that where removal is sought
    pursuant to statute for “inefficiency, neglect of duty, or
    malfeasance in office . . . the officer is entitled to notice and a
    hearing”); Reagan v. United States, 
    182 U.S. 419
    , 425 (1901)
    (stating that where causes of removal are specified by the
    Constitution or statute, “notice and hearing are essential”).15
    Although the Supreme Court has not defined the precise
    contours of this process, there is little reason to think it would
    impose an onerous burden on the President. See Breger &
    Edles, supra, at 1147-50. Afterwards, removal would be
    permissible if the President determined that the CFPB Director
    had been ineffective or incapable of “producing the desired
    15
    The Supreme Court’s due-process cases from the 1970s and
    1980s also suggest that an officer covered by the INM standard
    would be constitutionally entitled to some procedural protections
    before removal. See, e.g., Cleveland Bd. of Educ. v. Loudermill, 
    470 U.S. 532
    , 538-39 (1985) (ruling that persons classified as civil
    servants under state law who could be terminated only for cause
    possessed a property right in their job security); Bd. of Regents of
    State Colls. v. Roth, 
    408 U.S. 564
    , 576-77 (1972); see also Robert E.
    Cushman, The Independent Regulatory Commissions 466 (1972).
    Most agency statutes do not prescribe specific procedures for
    removal hearings. Breger & Edles, supra, at 1147-51. But if removal
    protections secure a type of property interest for officers, see, e.g.,
    Roth, 
    408 U.S. at 576-77
    , then the removal procedures would need
    to satisfy an officer’s procedural due-process rights, see Mathews v.
    Eldridge, 
    424 U.S. 319
    , 332-35 (1976). This would generally require
    something less than a formal hearing under the Administrative
    Procedure Act. See Breger & Edles, supra, at 1147-50.
    22
    effect.” Because removing an officer for “inefficiency” is a
    removal for cause, the President should identify what the
    Director did that was inefficient. In other words, the President
    should identify the action taken by the Director that constitutes
    the cause for which he is being removed. Then the President
    must simply offer a reasoned, non-pretextual explanation of
    how those actions were inefficient.16
    In practical effect, my approach yields a result somewhat
    similar to Judge Kavanaugh’s proposed remedy. He would
    sever the for-cause provision from the CFPB’s authorizing
    statute, making the Director removable at will. See Dissenting
    Op. at 7, 68-73 (Kavanaugh, J.). My interpretation of the INM
    standard would not disturb Congress’s design of the CFPB, but
    it would allow the President to remove the Director based on
    policy decisions that amounted to inefficiency. In addition, my
    analysis of the INM standard would likely have broader
    implications. For example, the definition of “inefficiency”
    presented here would presumably apply to other independent
    agencies protected by the INM standard. See supra Part III.A.
    And while I conclude here that the INM standard is a
    permissible restriction on the President’s ability to remove the
    CFPB Director, other removal standards—particularly those
    lacking the “inefficiency” ground—may not be defensible
    under Humphrey’s Executor and Morrison.
    16
    A future case challenging a President’s decision to actually
    remove an officer may require courts to articulate the appropriate
    standard for judicial review, though that question is beyond the scope
    of this case. See generally Dalton v. Specter, 
    511 U.S. 462
    , 474-77
    (1994); Mountain States Legal Found. v. Bush, 
    306 F.3d 1132
    , 1135-
    36 (D.C. Cir. 2002); Breger & Edles, supra, at 1151; cf. John F.
    Dillon, Commentaries on the Law of Municipal Corporations § 484,
    at 815 (1911) (“[T]he power of the courts to review the acts of the
    removing power is necessarily limited.” (emphasis omitted)).
    23
    IV
    Judge Wilkins argues this interpretation of the INM
    standard defeats the purpose of the provision. See Concurring
    Op. at 19-21 (Wilkins, J.). After all, the Court in Humphrey’s
    Executor examined the legislative history of the Federal Trade
    Commission Act and concluded that the “congressional intent”
    underlying the Act was to create an “independent” body of
    experts. 
    295 U.S. at 625
    . How can agency directors be
    independent if the President can remove them so easily for
    “inefficiency”?
    As a preliminary matter, the Court’s discussion of FTC
    “independence” in Humphrey’s Executor was part of its
    statutory holding, not its constitutional analysis. See Maj. Op.
    at 45-46. In its statutory analysis, the Court merely attempted
    to discern if the INM standard was intended to limit the
    President’s removal power. The Court determined that it did,
    staking its conclusion on the text of the statute: “The words of
    the act are definite and unambiguous.” 
    295 U.S. at 623
    . The
    Court then proceeded to address the legislative history, but it
    expressly disavowed any reliance on that discussion, see 
    id. at 623-25
    , and concluded that the INM standard was designed to
    reduce the President’s otherwise “illimitable” removal power.
    But as described above, the Court never addressed just how
    much the INM standard limits that power. See supra Part II.
    More fundamentally, a straightforward textual analysis of
    “inefficiency” does not remove the “concept of ‘independence’
    from ‘independent agencies,’” Concurring Op. at 19 (Wilkins,
    J.), because agency independence is not a binary but rather a
    matter of degree. This principle is at the heart of Morrison,
    which does not forbid all interference with the President’s
    executive power but only forbids too much interference. See
    
    487 U.S. at 692
    . Insisting that each INM term be interpreted to
    24
    maximize director independence thwarts Congress’s specific
    choice of means to protect the Director. “[N]o legislation
    pursues its purposes at all costs. . . . [I]t frustrates rather than
    effectuates legislative intent simplistically to assume that
    whatever furthers the statute’s primary objective must be the
    law.” Rodriguez v. United States, 
    480 U.S. 522
    , 525-26 (1987)
    (per curiam). With the INM standard, Congress chose to
    provide three discrete grounds for removal, at least one of
    which is very broad. In other words, Congress specified the
    amount of removal protection the CFPB Director would
    receive, and that amount is minimal. Elsewhere Congress has
    elected to provide greater protection. For example, only weeks
    after Humphrey’s Executor Congress chose not to include
    “inefficiency” as a ground for removal in the National Labor
    Relations Act. See ch. 372, § 3, 
    49 Stat. 449
    , 451
    (1935) (codified at 
    29 U.S.C. § 153
    ) (permitting removal
    “upon notice and hearing, for neglect of duty or malfeasance in
    office, but for no other cause”).
    Since Humphrey’s Executor, Congress has created a wide
    range of removal protections, some stronger than others. See
    Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 549-56
     (Breyer, J.,
    dissenting) (listing numerous agency removal protections,
    many of which provide different statutory grounds for
    removal). “[L]aw is like a vector. It has length as well as
    direction. We must find both, or we know nothing of value. To
    find length we must take account of objectives, of means
    chosen, and of stopping places identified.” Frank H.
    Easterbrook, The Role of Original Intent in Statutory
    Construction, 11 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 59, 63 (1988). Here,
    Congress specified that the INM standard would move certain
    agencies in the direction of greater independence from the
    President, compared to those officers subject to at-will
    removal. But Congress also specified just how far that principle
    of independence would reach, and it is not for us to second-
    25
    guess that choice. “The removal restrictions set forth in the
    statute mean what they say.” Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 502
    .
    *   *    *
    The challenged features of the CFPB do not violate Article
    II because they do not prevent the President from performing
    his constitutional duty to supervise the Executive Branch. That
    is so because the INM standard creates only a minimal barrier
    to the President removing the CFPB Director. Of course, if
    Congress desires, it may pass a more restrictive removal
    provision, as it has with other agencies. At that point, my
    colleagues’ thorough evaluation of the CFPB’s bureaucratic
    structure may be necessary. But as it stands today, such an
    evaluation is neither required nor consistent with the mandate
    from Morrison.
    KAREN LECRAFT HENDERSON, Circuit Judge, dissenting:
    Effective 1789, we Americans “set up government by consent
    of the governed.” W. Va. State Bd. of Educ. v. Barnette, 
    319 U.S. 624
    , 641 (1943). Under the United States Constitution,
    all of the federal government’s power derives from the people.
    U.S. CONST. pmbl.; see McCulloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. (4
    Wheat.) 316, 405 (1819) (“In form, and in substance, it
    emanates from them.”). Much of that power has been further
    delegated to a warren of administrative agencies, making
    accountability more elusive and more important than ever.
    Nowadays we the people tolerate bureaucrats “poking into
    every nook and cranny of daily life,” City of Arlington v. FCC,
    
    133 S. Ct. 1863
    , 1879 (2013) (Roberts, C.J., dissenting), on the
    theory that if they exercise their delegated power unjustly,
    inexpertly or otherwise at odds with the popular will, we can
    elect legislators and a President who will take corrective action,
    Chevron, U.S.A., Inc. v. NRDC, 
    467 U.S. 837
    , 865 (1984)
    (underscoring that “[w]hile agencies are not directly
    accountable to the people,” they report to political actors who
    are).
    But consent of the governed is a sham if an administrative
    agency, by design, does not meaningfully answer for its
    policies to either of the elected branches. Such is the case with
    the Consumer Financial Protection Bureau (CFPB). The
    CFPB, created by the Dodd-Frank Wall Street Reform and
    Consumer Protection Act of 2010 (Dodd-Frank), Pub. L. No.
    111-203, Title X, 
    124 Stat. 1376
    , 1955-2113 (July 21, 2010),
    perma.cc/6K2U-CD9W, 1 is an agency like no other. Its
    Director has immense power to define elastic concepts of
    unfairness, deception and abuse in an array of consumer
    1
    The perma.cc links throughout this opinion archive materials
    that are available online. See Encino Motorcars, LLC v. Navarro,
    
    136 S. Ct. 2117
    , 2123 (2016) (using perma.cc); Bandimere v. SEC,
    
    844 F.3d 1168
    , 1170 n.1 (10th Cir. 2016) (same).
    2
    contexts; to enforce his rules in administrative proceedings
    overseen by employees he appoints; to adjudicate such actions
    himself if he chooses; and to decide what penalties fit the
    violation. The Director does all that and more without any
    significant check by the President or the Congress. Dodd-
    Frank gives the Director a five-year tenure—thereby outlasting
    a Presidential term—and prohibits the President from
    removing him except for cause. At the same time, the statute
    guarantees the CFPB ample annual funding from the Federal
    Reserve System, outside the ordinary appropriations process.
    It thus frees the agency from a powerful means of Presidential
    oversight and the Congress’s most effective means short of
    restructuring the agency. Finally, the Director is unique
    among the principal officers of independent agencies in that he
    exercises vast executive power unilaterally: as a board of one,
    he need not deliberate with anyone before acting.
    In my view, Dodd-Frank Title X, otherwise known as the
    Consumer Financial Protection Act, violates Article II: its
    “language providing for good-cause removal is . . . one of a
    number of statutory provisions that, working together, produce
    a constitutional violation.” Free Enter. Fund v. PCAOB, 
    561 U.S. 477
    , 509 (2010). Under Article II, “[t]he executive
    Power shall be vested in a President” who “shall take Care that
    the Laws be faithfully executed.” U.S. CONST. art. II, §§ 1, 3.
    In Myers v. United States, 
    272 U.S. 52
     (1926), the United States
    Supreme Court explained that the President must ordinarily
    have “unrestricted power” to remove executive officers if he is
    to faithfully execute the laws. 
    Id. at 176
    . More recently, the
    Court in Free Enterprise Fund emphasized “the importance of
    removal”—based on “simple disagreement with [an agency’s]
    policies or priorities”—as a means of ensuring that the modern
    administrative state does not “slip from the Executive’s
    control, and thus from that of the people.” 
    561 U.S. at 499, 502
    . Here, when taken together with the rest of Title X, the
    3
    for-cause removal provision in effect puts the CFPB beyond
    the people’s reach.
    I recognize that Humphrey’s Executor v. United States,
    
    295 U.S. 602
     (1935), made an exception to the President’s
    “exclusive power of removal,” Myers, 
    272 U.S. at 122
    , in
    holding that the Congress “can, under certain circumstances,
    create independent agencies run by principal officers appointed
    by the President, whom the President may not remove at will
    but only for good cause,” Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 483
    (emphasis added) (citing Humphrey’s Ex’r, 
    295 U.S. 602
    ).
    But Humphrey’s Executor remains the exception, not the rule,
    and it does not apply here.
    Humphrey’s Executor upheld a for-cause limit on the
    President’s authority to remove commissioners of the Federal
    Trade Commission (FTC), a “legislative agency” headed by a
    “non-partisan” “body of experts” whose staggered terms
    ensure that the commission does not “complete[ly] change at
    any one time” but instead gains collective expertise even as
    individual members come and go. 
    295 U.S. at 624, 628
    . By
    contrast, the CFPB is not a legislative agency, if that means an
    agency that reports to the Congress. 2 Nor is it a nonpartisan
    body of experts. Unlike the five FTC commissioners, only
    three of whom can be members of the same political party, the
    CFPB’s sole Director does not have to bother with the give and
    take required of a bipartisan multimember body. Also, the
    CFPB’s membership is subject to complete change all at once,
    at five-year intervals that do not coincide with the four-year
    2
    The Congress’s abdication of financial responsibility for the
    CFPB may give rise to Article I objections beyond the scope of this
    opinion. For my purpose, the deficiency in congressional oversight
    is important because it is one of several factors distinguishing this
    case from Humphrey’s Executor.
    4
    term of the President. The imperfect overlap means that for
    much of the President’s term—sometimes all of it—the sole
    “regulator of first resort . . . for a vital sector of our economy,”
    Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 508
    , might well be faithful to the
    policies of the last President, not the views of the current one.
    First principles, not Humphrey’s Executor, control here.
    This unaccountable agency violates them. I disagree with the
    majority’s conclusion to the contrary. Further, although I
    agree with portions of Judge Kavanaugh’s dissent, I cannot join
    it, primarily because it would strike and sever Title X’s for-
    cause removal provision. Even assuming that remedy would
    bring the CFPB fully in line with the Constitution, I do not
    think we can dictate it to the Congress.
    Severability turns on whether the statute, minus any
    invalid provision, “will function in a manner consistent with
    the intent of Congress” and “is legislation that Congress would
    . . . have enacted.” Alaska Airlines, Inc. v. Brock, 
    480 U.S. 678
    , 685 (1987) (emphasis in original). Statutory text,
    structure and history manifest the 111th Congress’s belief that
    the CFPB’s independence from both of the elected branches is
    indispensable. Excising only the for-cause removal provision
    would leave behind a one-legged agency that, by all
    indications, the Congress would not have created. True, the
    introduction to the 849-page Dodd-Frank legislation includes a
    standard-form severability clause. But such a clause raises
    only a “presumption” that “the objectionable provision can be
    excised.” Alaska Airlines, 480 U.S. at 686. The presumption
    is rebutted here. As I see it, Dodd-Frank’s severability clause
    speaks to severing Title X from other titles of the legislation
    but does not support severing the for-cause removal provision
    from the rest of Title X.
    5
    Accordingly, I would invalidate Title X in its entirety and
    let the Congress decide whether to resuscitate—and, if so, how
    to restructure—the CFPB. I would set aside the Director’s
    decision as ultra vires and forbid the agency from resuming
    proceedings. Because the en banc Court’s decision permits
    this case to continue before the agency, I respectfully dissent. 3
    I. THE CFPB’S STRUCTURE VIOLATES ARTICLE II
    The administrative agencies sprawled across Washington,
    D.C.—especially the “independent” ones—do not fit
    3
    I found it unnecessary to decide the CFPB’s constitutionality
    at the panel stage because PHH sought the same relief (“vacatur”)
    whether we endorsed its constitutional claim or its statutory claims,
    the latter of which the panel unanimously found meritorious. PHH
    Corp. v. CFPB, 
    839 F.3d 1
    , 56-60 (D.C. Cir. 2016) (Henderson, J.,
    concurring in part and dissenting in part), vacated upon grant of
    reh’g en banc (Feb. 16, 2017); see PHH Panel Br. 23-24, 61-62; PHH
    Panel Reply Br. 31. But unlike its panel briefs, PHH’s en banc
    briefs expressly ask that the Director’s decision “be vacated without
    remand” and that the Court “forbid the CFPB from resuming
    proceedings.” PHH Br. 58; PHH Reply Br. 29. Because that relief
    is warranted only if the CFPB is unconstitutionally structured, I
    believe the constitutional question can no longer be avoided. See
    Citizens United v. FEC, 
    558 U.S. 310
    , 375 (2010) (Roberts, C.J.,
    concurring) (“When constitutional questions are ‘indispensably
    necessary’ to resolving the case at hand, ‘the court must meet and
    decide them.’” (quoting Ex parte Randolph, 
    20 F. Cas. 242
    , 254 (No.
    11,558) (CC Va. 1833) (Marshall, C.J.))); see also infra note 17. In
    any event, because the majority decides the constitutional question
    and gets it wrong, I see no reason to withhold my views. Cf. Freytag
    v. Comm’r, 
    501 U.S. 868
    , 892-922 (1991) (Scalia, J., concurring in
    part and concurring in the judgment) (expressing views on merits
    after disagreeing with Court’s decision to reach Appointments
    Clause issue).
    6
    comfortably within the text and structure of the Constitution.4
    FTC v. Ruberoid Co., 
    343 U.S. 470
    , 487 (1952) (Jackson, J.,
    dissenting) (“[A]dministrative bodies . . . have become a
    veritable fourth branch of the Government, which has deranged
    our three-branch legal theories . . . .”); see PHILIP HAMBURGER,
    IS ADMINISTRATIVE LAW UNLAWFUL? 1-2 (2014)
    (“Constitution generally establishes three avenues of power”
    but administrative state “prefers to drive off-road”).
    Cognizant of modern-day complexities, and bowing to
    perceived necessity, the judiciary has made accommodations
    such as Humphrey’s Executor. But the accommodations have
    limits and the CFPB exceeds them.
    A. THE PRESIDENT’S REMOVAL POWER
    Three Article II cases—Myers, Humphrey’s Executor and
    Free Enterprise Fund—set forth the legal framework for
    deciding the CFPB’s constitutionality. I discuss each in turn.
    1. Myers
    One would not know it from the CFPB’s one-sentence
    treatment, CFPB Br. 32, but Myers is a “landmark,” Free
    Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 492
    . In 1917, President Wilson, by
    and with the advice and consent of the Senate, appointed Frank
    Myers to a four-year term as first-class postmaster. Myers,
    
    272 U.S. at 56, 106
    . He did so pursuant to an 1876 statute
    providing in relevant part that “[p]ostmasters of the first,
    second and third classes shall be appointed and may be
    removed by the President by and with the advice and consent
    of the Senate.” 
    Id. at 107
     (quoting Act of July 12, 1876, ch.
    4
    In this opinion, I use the term “independent agency” to mean
    an agency whose principal officers enjoy protection from removal at
    the President’s will. See Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 483
    .
    7
    179, § 6, 
    19 Stat. 80
    , 81). In 1920, for reasons undisclosed in
    the Myers opinion, 5 President Wilson removed Myers from
    office without the Senate’s advice and consent. 
    Id. at 106-07
    .
    Invoking the 1876 statute, Myers sued for “salary from the date
    of his removal.” 
    Id. at 106
    . He lost. In an opinion authored
    by Chief Justice Taft—Wilson’s predecessor as President—the
    Supreme Court held that requiring the President to obtain
    advice and consent in order to remove an executive officer
    violates Article II. 
    Id. at 108, 176
    .
    Because the Constitution contains “no express provision
    respecting removals” and “[t]he subject was not discussed in
    the Constitutional Convention,” 272 U.S. at 109-10, the Court
    focused on the First Congress, id. at 111-36. In 1789, the First
    Congress enacted a law that effectively recognized “the power
    of the President under the Constitution to remove the Secretary
    of Foreign Affairs”—now the Secretary of State—“without the
    advice and consent of the Senate.” Id. at 114; see id. at 111-
    15. The Court gave “great[] weight” to the debates on the bill
    because the First Congress “numbered among its leaders those
    who had been members of the Convention.” Id. at 136, 174-
    75. The Court pointed especially to James Madison’s
    “masterly” arguments about the removal power because they
    “carried the House.” Id. at 115. Collecting the views of
    Madison and his colleagues, and “supplementing them” with
    “additional considerations” of its own, the Court declared that
    generally the President’s “executive power” “includ[es] . . . the
    5
    Many years later, the Supreme Court noted that Myers had
    been suspected of fraud. Raines v. Byrd, 
    521 U.S. 811
    , 827 (1997).
    Historical records indicate that he also alienated colleagues and
    ensnared himself in one political dustup after another. See Jonathan
    L. Entin, The Curious Case of the Pompous Postmaster: Myers v.
    United States, 65 CASE W. RES. L. REV. 1059, 1062-64 (2015)
    (citing contemporaneous news accounts and personal letters).
    8
    exclusive power of removal.” Id. at 115, 122. The Court
    supported that general proposition with four reasons rooted in
    constitutional text, structure and function. Id. at 115-35.
    First, Article II gives the President not only the power to
    execute the laws but the obligation “to take care that they be
    faithfully executed.” 272 U.S. at 117. He cannot do so
    “unaided”; he needs “the assistance of subordinates.” Id.
    Because “his selection of administrative officers is essential to”
    his faithful execution of the laws, “so must be his power of
    removing those for whom he can not continue to be
    responsible.” Id. (citing 1 ANNALS OF CONG. 474 (1789)
    (Joseph Gales ed., 1834) (available in photo. reprint, William
    S. Hein & Co. 2003) (statement of Fisher Ames)). And
    because the crown—the British executive—had the power to
    appoint and remove executive officers, “it was natural” for the
    Framers “to regard the words ‘executive power’ as including
    both.” Id. at 118.
    Second, the Constitution divides legislative and executive
    powers, giving them to two separate but coequal political
    branches as a check against oppression by either. 272 U.S. at
    120-21.      Some Framers had thought it an “unchaste”
    “mingling” of the legislative and executive powers even to give
    the Senate the job of advising on and consenting to the
    President’s appointments. Id. at 120 (quoting 1 ANNALS OF
    CONG. 557 (statement of Abraham Baldwin)). In the First
    Congress, Madison and others cautioned against “‘extend[ing]
    this connexion’” to “the removal of an officer who has served
    under the President.” Id. at 121 (quoting 1 ANNALS OF CONG.
    380 (statement of James Madison)). Whereas a veto on the
    appointment power merely “enables the Senate to prevent the
    filling of offices with bad or incompetent men,” a veto on the
    President’s “exclusive power of removal” entangles the
    Congress in an executive function: deciding whether an
    9
    incumbent officer has the requisite “loyalty” to the President’s
    agenda. Id. at 121-22, 131, 134.
    Third, the President’s removal power is especially strong
    with respect to principal executive officers. 272 U.S. at 126-
    29. The first half of the Appointments Clause requires the
    President personally to appoint, with the Senate’s advice and
    consent, “Ambassadors, other public Ministers and Consuls,
    Judges of the supreme Court, and all other Officers of the
    United States, whose Appointments are not herein otherwise
    provided for, and which shall be established by Law.” U.S.
    CONST. art. II, § 2, cl. 2. By way of an “exception,” 272 U.S.
    at 127, the second half of the Appointments Clause provides:
    “[B]ut the Congress may by Law vest the Appointment of such
    inferior Officers, as they think proper, in the President alone,
    in the Courts of Law, or in the Heads of Departments.” U.S.
    CONST. art. II, § 2, cl. 2. The Congress accordingly has
    “legislative power in the matter of appointments and removals
    in the case of inferior executive officers.” 272 U.S. at 127
    (citing United States v. Perkins, 
    116 U.S. 483
    , 485 (1886)).
    “By the plainest implication,” however, the Appointments
    Clause “excludes Congressional dealing with appointments or
    removals of executive officers not falling within the [inferior-
    officer] exception, and leaves unaffected the executive power
    of the President to appoint and remove” principal officers. 
    Id.
    Fourth, the Framers did not “intend[], without express
    provision, to give to Congress . . . the means of thwarting the
    Executive . . . by fastening upon him, as subordinate executive
    officers, men who by their inefficient service,” “lack of
    loyalty” or “different views of policy” would make it “difficult
    or impossible” for him to “faithfully execute[]” the laws. 272
    U.S. at 131. The removal power was vested in the President
    to help him “secure th[e] unitary and uniform execution of the
    laws,” id. at 135, and to preserve a discernible “chain” of
    10
    “responsibility” from appointed officers to the President and
    from the President to the people, id. at 131-32 (quoting 1
    ANNALS OF CONG. 499, 523 (statements of James Madison and
    Theodore Sedgwick)).
    For those four reasons, the Court concluded that the
    President must ordinarily have “unrestricted power” to
    “remov[e] executive officers who ha[ve] been appointed by
    him by and with the advice and consent of the Senate.” 272
    U.S. at 176. Because the 1876 statute restricting removal of
    postmasters violated that general rule, the Court invalidated the
    statute. Id.
    2. Humphrey’s Executor
    Less than a decade after Myers, the Supreme Court in
    Humphrey’s Executor again addressed the scope of the
    President’s removal power, this time in the context of the FTC.
    Under section 1 of the Federal Trade Commission Act (FTC
    Act), an FTC commissioner “may be removed by the President
    for inefficiency, neglect of duty, or malfeasance in office.” 
    15 U.S.C. § 41
    . In 1933, President Roosevelt requested the
    resignation of William Humphrey, a business-friendly FTC
    commissioner appointed by President Coolidge and
    reappointed by President Hoover. 
    295 U.S. at 618
    ; see
    RICHARD A. HARRIS & SIDNEY M. MILKIS, THE POLITICS OF
    REGULATORY CHANGE: A TALE OF TWO AGENCIES 153 (2d ed.
    1996) (noting that Humphrey’s appointment was perceived as
    “transform[ing] the FTC into an agency that served not as an
    overseer but a partner of business” (internal quotation
    omitted)). In his correspondence with Humphrey, President
    Roosevelt cited “polic[y]” differences and “disclaim[ed] any
    reflection upon the commissioner personally or upon his
    services.” 
    295 U.S. at 618-19
     (internal quotation omitted).
    Humphrey refused to resign and the President removed him.
    11
    
    Id. at 619
    . Humphrey died shortly thereafter but his executor
    sued to recover Humphrey’s salary from the date of removal.
    
    Id. at 618-19
    .
    The Court in Humphrey’s Executor confronted two
    questions. First, does section 1 of the FTC Act prohibit the
    President from removing an FTC commissioner for any reason
    other than inefficiency, neglect or malfeasance? 
    295 U.S. at 619
    . Second, if so, “is such a restriction or limitation valid
    under the Constitution”? 
    Id.
     The Court answered yes to both
    questions. 
    Id. at 632
    . In considering the first question, the
    Court described at length “the character of the commission,”
    
    id. at 624
    , as manifested in the FTC Act’s text and legislative
    history, 
    id. at 619-26
    . And in considering the second question,
    the Court indicated that “the character of the office” would
    determine the Congress’s ability to restrict the President’s
    removal power. 
    Id. at 631
    .
    In other words, the constitutionality of the FTC Act, like
    any other law, depended on its content. The CFPB resists this
    truism, suggesting the “Court’s discussion of the FTC’s
    structure” is irrelevant because it “comes in the statutory
    interpretation part of the decision.” CFPB Br. 31. But
    Humphrey’s Executor makes plain that, if we are to understand
    what it says about Article II, we must understand the structure
    of the agency it sustained. 
    295 U.S. at 632
     (holding that
    President’s “unrestrictable power” of removal “does not extend
    to an office such as that here involved” (emphasis added)); see
    Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 516
     (Breyer, J., dissenting)
    (recognizing that applicability of Humphrey’s Executor turns
    in part on “the nature of the office,” “its function” and “its
    subject matter”); see also Maj. Op. 22, 36 (“Supreme Court
    looks to the character of the office” and “the sort of agency
    involved” when “analyzing where Congress may deploy . . .
    for-cause protection” (internal quotation omitted)).
    12
    As summarized in Humphrey’s Executor, the FTC’s
    structure is as follows:
    •   It is composed of five commissioners. 
    295 U.S. at 619-20
    . Together they “are called upon to exercise the
    trained judgment of a body of experts . . . informed by
    experience.” 
    Id. at 624
     (internal quotation omitted).
    •   The FTC has certain “powers of investigation,” 
    id. at 621
    , but they are legislative rather than executive
    because they are for the purpose of making reports and
    recommendations to the Congress, 
    id. at 621, 628
    .
    •   With the advice and consent of the Senate, the President
    appoints each commissioner to a seven-year term
    staggered with those of his fellow commissioners. 
    Id. at 620, 624
    . The duration and “arrange[ment]” of the
    terms foster collective expertise. 
    Id. at 624
     (seven
    years is “‘long enough’” to “‘acquire . . . expertness’”
    if “membership [is not] subject to complete change at
    any one time” (quoting S. REP. NO. 63-597, at 11
    (1914))).
    •   The FTC is a “non-partisan” “agency of the legislative
    and judicial departments.” 
    Id. at 624, 630
    . “Its duties
    are neither political nor executive, but predominantly
    quasi-judicial and quasi-legislative.” 
    Id. at 624
    ; see 
    id. at 628-29
    . To ensure the FTC’s “entire impartiality”
    in carrying out its duties—and to insulate it from
    “suspicion of partisan direction”—no more than three
    of its commissioners can be members of the same
    political party. 
    Id. at 620, 624-25
    .
    Having made these observations, the Court concluded that
    an FTC commissioner “is so essentially unlike” a first-class
    13
    postmaster that Myers “cannot be accepted as controlling our
    decision here.” 
    295 U.S. at 627
    . Unlike a postmaster, the
    Court reasoned, an FTC commissioner “exercises no part of the
    executive power . . . in the constitutional sense.” 
    Id. at 628
    .
    Rather, “[t]o the extent that [the FTC] exercises any executive
    function, . . . it does so in the discharge and effectuation of its
    quasi-legislative and quasi-judicial powers” as an expert
    agency “charged with the enforcement of no policy except the
    policy of the law.” 
    Id. at 624, 628
    . In the Court’s view, just
    as the Congress has limited power to interfere with the
    President’s removal of executive officers, the President has
    “[]limitable power” to remove FTC commissioners because
    they are legislative or judicial officers. 
    Id. at 629
    ; see 
    id. at 630
     (“The sound application of a principle that makes one
    master in his own house precludes him from imposing his
    control in the house of another who is master there.”).
    3. Free Enterprise Fund
    In Free Enterprise Fund, the Supreme Court’s most recent
    decision on the scope of the removal power, the Court was
    asked to extend Humphrey’s Executor to “a new situation” it
    had “not yet encountered.” 
    561 U.S. at 483
    . It declined the
    invitation. At issue were provisions that precluded the
    Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC) from removing
    members of the Public Company Accounting Oversight Board
    (Board) except for cause. 
    Id.
     at 486 (citing 
    15 U.S.C. §§ 7211
    (e)(6), 7217(d)(3)). Based on the “understanding”
    that SEC commissioners “cannot themselves be removed by
    the President except” for cause, 
    id. at 487
    , the Court held that
    two layers of “good-cause protection” violate Article II
    because together they prevent the President from “oversee[ing]
    the faithfulness” of officers who “determine[] the policy and
    enforce[] the laws of the United States,” 
    id. at 484
    .
    14
    The Court acknowledged that the Congress has “power to
    create a vast and varied federal bureaucracy” to ensure
    “apolitical expertise.” 
    561 U.S. at 498-99
     (internal quotation
    omitted). But faced with a “novel structure” not squarely
    authorized by Humphrey’s Executor or any other precedent, 
    id. at 496
    ; see 
    id. at 483, 492-96, 514
    , the Court returned to the
    most fundamental of first principles: “Our Constitution was
    adopted to enable the people to govern themselves, through
    their elected leaders.” 
    Id. at 499
    . In view of that principle,
    the Court held that the Congress could not “encase[]” the Board
    “within a Matryoshka doll of tenure protections” and thereby
    “immun[ize] from Presidential oversight” the “regulator of first
    resort . . . for a vital sector of our economy.” 
    Id. at 497, 508
    ;
    see 
    id. at 485
     (detailing Board’s “expansive powers to govern
    an entire industry” through rulemaking, audits, inspections,
    investigations, monetary penalties and other forms of
    discipline). Concluding otherwise, the Court reasoned, would
    sever the chain of responsibility linking the Board to the people
    via the President. 
    Id. at 495
     (“The result is a Board that is not
    accountable to the President, and a President who is not
    responsible for the Board.”).
    B. THE CFPB’S STRUCTURAL DEFECTS
    Under the foregoing framework and considering Title X as
    a whole, I believe the CFPB’s structure violates Article II.
    1. Novelty
    For me the initial question is whether the Supreme Court
    has “encountered” an agency like the CFPB or if, instead, its
    structure is “novel.” Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 483, 496
    .
    Although structural “innovation” is not itself unconstitutional,
    Mistretta v. United States, 
    488 U.S. 361
    , 385 (1989); see Maj.
    Op. 53-54, a novel agency fights uphill: “the lack of historical
    precedent for [an] entity” is “[p]erhaps the most telling
    15
    indication of [a] severe constitutional problem.” Free Enter.
    Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 505
     (internal quotation omitted). The CFPB
    argues that it is sufficiently like the FTC to fall within the ambit
    of Humphrey’s Executor. CFPB Br. 13-14, 18-21, 23, 30-31.
    It also relies on Morrison v. Olson, 
    487 U.S. 654
     (1988), which
    involved the independent counsel. CFPB Br. 18-21, 24-25,
    31-32.      Finally, along with Humphrey’s Executor and
    Morrison, my colleagues invoke Wiener v. United States, 
    357 U.S. 349
     (1958), which involved a claims adjudicator. Maj.
    Op. 7-9, 20-30, 36, 38, 42, 58, 66-67; Wilkins Concurring Op.
    4-5, 10. None of this is precedent for the CFPB or its Director.
    Before explaining why, I recap essential elements of the
    CFPB’s design.
    a. Title X
    Equating financial products with household appliances,
    Professor Elizabeth Warren in 2007 advocated for the creation
    of a federal agency to protect consumers from “[u]nsafe”
    mortgages, student loans and credit cards in the same way the
    Consumer Product Safety Commission protects consumers
    from exploding toasters. Elizabeth Warren, Unsafe at Any
    Rate, DEMOCRACY (Summer 2007), perma.cc/52X3-892V.
    She proposed that the Congress consolidate in the new agency
    the power to administer most federal consumer-protection
    laws, the result being “the review of financial products in a
    single location.” 
    Id.
     The proposed agency was to be
    “independent” of “national politic[s],” the “financial . . .
    industry lobby” and “legislative micromanaging.” 
    Id.
     Freed
    of such burdens, the agency could take “quick action” to solve
    the problems regularly generated by a financial services
    industry bent on “increas[ing] profits.” 
    Id.
     The agency, in
    short, was to “side” with consumers against the industry. 
    Id.
    16
    Consistent with Professor Warren’s proposal, Title X
    established the CFPB as “an independent bureau” to “regulate
    the offering and provision of consumer financial products or
    services under the Federal consumer financial laws.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (a). It transferred to the CFPB the authority to
    enforce eighteen existing laws previously administered by
    seven different federal agencies. 
    Id.
     §§ 5481(12), 5581(a)(2),
    (b). Those eighteen laws cover most consumer credit
    products, including mortgages, student loans and credit cards.
    The CFPB now has all but exclusive power “to prescribe rules
    or issue orders or guidelines pursuant to” all eighteen laws. Id.
    § 5581(a)(1)(A); see id. §§ 5481(12), 5512(b)(4). The agency
    also has expansive new powers under Title X to investigate,
    charge, adjudicate and penalize—through (inter alia)
    subpoena, rescission, restitution, disgorgement and monetary
    penalties—a consumer-connected “act or practice” the agency
    defines as “unfair, deceptive, or abusive.” Id. § 5531(a), (b);
    see id. §§ 5562-5565.
    The CFPB’s expansive powers are vested in and derive
    from its sole Director. 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (b)(1) (Director is
    “head” of CFPB); 
    id.
     § 5491(b)(5)(A) (Director appoints
    Deputy Director); id. § 5492(b) (Director “may delegate to any
    duly authorized employee, representative, or agent any power
    vested in the Bureau by law”); id. § 5493(a)(1)(A) (Director
    “fix[es] the number of” CFPB employees and “appoint[s]” and
    “direct[s]” all of them); id. § 5512(b)(1) (Director “may
    prescribe rules and issue orders and guidance, as may be
    necessary or appropriate to enable the Bureau to administer and
    carry out the purposes and objectives of the Federal consumer
    financial laws, and to prevent evasions thereof”).
    The President appoints the Director “by and with the
    advice and consent of the Senate.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (b)(2).
    The Director is thereafter insulated from both political
    17
    branches. He has a five-year term, 
    id.
     § 5491(c)(1), and the
    President may remove him only “for cause,” i.e., “inefficiency,
    neglect of duty, or malfeasance in office,” id. § 5491(c)(3). 6
    At the same time, the Director obtains funding from the Federal
    Reserve System, outside the Congress’s appropriations
    process. Id. § 5497(a)(1). On a quarterly basis, the Director
    determines how much money the CFPB “reasonably” needs,
    id., up to 12 per cent of the Federal Reserve budget, id.
    § 5497(a)(2)(A)(iii).    The Federal Reserve “shall” then
    transfer that amount to the CFPB. 7 Id. § 5497(a)(1). The
    money “shall not be subject to review by the Committees on
    Appropriations of the House of Representatives and the
    Senate.” Id. § 5497(a)(2)(C). Nor does the Director need
    “any” form of “consent or approval” from the executive
    branch’s Office of Management and Budget (OMB), which
    lacks “any jurisdiction or oversight over the affairs or
    operations of the Bureau.” Id. § 5497(a)(4)(E).
    6
    Title X permits the Director to continue serving “after the
    expiration of the term for which [he is] appointed, until a successor
    has been appointed and qualified.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (c)(2). Citing
    a CFPB concession, Oral Arg. Tr. 48-49, the Court suggests the
    President may remove the Director at will during any holdover
    period, Maj. Op. 12 n.1. I agree. Nothing in the statute authorizes
    the Senate to keep a holdover Director in office against the
    President’s will by failing to act on a nominee even after expiration
    of the Director’s term has triggered the President’s appointment
    power under 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (b)(2). Cf. Swan v. Clinton, 
    100 F.3d 973
    , 981-88 (D.C. Cir. 1996) (no good-cause protection for holdover
    board member of National Credit Union Administration).
    7
    Through three quarters of fiscal year 2017, the Director
    claimed $517.4 million, putting him on pace for the maximum of
    $646.2 million for the year. CFPB, Semiannual Report 122 (Spring
    2017), perma.cc/M7XD-4QMT.
    18
    b. CFPB distinguished from FTC
    The agency just described is not even a distant cousin of
    the FTC blessed by Humphrey’s Executor. I see at least three
    critical distinctions.
    First, like nearly all other administrative agencies, the
    FTC is and always has been subject to the appropriations
    process. 
    15 U.S.C. § 42
    ; see HARRIS & MILKIS, supra, at 146,
    204-05 (discussing FTC appropriations); see also Note,
    Independence, Congressional Weakness, and the Importance
    of Appointment: The Impact of Combining Budgetary
    Autonomy with Removal Protection, 125 HARV. L. REV. 1822,
    1823 (2012) (Budgetary Autonomy) (“A complete exemption
    from appropriations is rare . . . .”). Accordingly, the FTC must
    go to the Congress every year with a detailed budget request
    explaining its expenditure of public money. See, e.g., FTC,
    Fiscal Year 2018 Congressional Budget Justification (May 22,
    2017) (185-page request), perma.cc/4V7G-83JL.               The
    procedure provides a measure of public accountability and
    helps explain the Supreme Court’s description of the FTC as a
    “quasi-legislative” agency that “report[s] to Congress.”
    Humphrey’s Ex’r, 
    295 U.S. at 621, 624, 628-29
    .
    The CFPB is different. As the agency itself declares, it is
    “fund[ed] outside of the congressional appropriations process
    to ensure full independence.” CFPB, Strategic Plan: FY2013-
    FY2017, at 36 (Apr. 2013), perma.cc/XQW5-5S5S. The
    agency has made the most of its autonomy: when legislators
    have sought explanation for its spending or policies, it has
    stonewalled. See, e.g., Letter from Rep. Randy Neugebauer et
    al. to Richard Cordray (May 2, 2012) (noting CFPB’s “wholly
    unresponsive” posture to “requests for additional budget
    information”), perma.cc/NTH6-KR98; Letter from Sen. Rob
    Portman et al. to Richard Cordray (Oct. 30, 2013) (seeking
    19
    “greater transparency for the Bureau’s activity”),
    perma.cc/5N3Z-GGCQ. Perhaps the best illustration is a
    2015 hearing in which a legislator asked the Director who
    authorized a CFPB project that cost more than $215 million.
    House Financial Services Committee, Hearings and Meetings
    (Mar. 17, 2015), www.congress.gov/committees/video/house-
    financial-services/hsba00/5IxSfJ638cs. The Director replied:
    “Why does that matter to you?” 
    Id.
    The appropriations process has long been considered “the
    most potent form of Congressional oversight.” 2 SENATE
    COMMITTEE ON GOVERNMENT OPERATIONS, STUDY ON
    FEDERAL REGULATION: CONGRESSIONAL OVERSIGHT OF
    REGULATORY AGENCIES 42 (1977); see MICHAEL J. KLARMAN,
    THE FRAMERS’ COUP: THE MAKING OF THE UNITED STATES
    CONSTITUTION 16 (2016) (founding generation “generally
    embraced the maxim that the power which holds the purse-
    strings absolutely will rule” (internal quotation and brackets
    omitted)). Because of its freedom from appropriations, the
    CFPB cannot be called “an agency of the legislative . . .
    department[]” and the Congress cannot be called its “master.”
    Humphrey’s Ex’r, 
    295 U.S. at 630
    . The agency argues that,
    whatever its accountability to the Congress, its budgetary
    independence “does not interfere with the President’s power to
    take care that the laws be faithfully executed.” CFPB Br. 28
    & n.8 (emphasis added); see Maj. Op. 41 (“The CFPB’s
    budgetary independence . . . does not intensify any effect on
    the President of the removal constraint.”). The contention
    overlooks the President’s constitutional role in the budget
    process.
    Lest it be forgotten, the Presentment Clause gives the
    President the power to veto legislation, including spending
    bills. U.S. CONST. art. I, § 7, cl. 2. Armed with that authority
    and the prerogative to “recommend to [the Congress’s]
    20
    Consideration such Measures as he shall judge necessary and
    expedient,” U.S. CONST. art. II, § 3, the President has for the
    past century submitted an annual budget to the Congress, see
    LOUIS FISHER, CONGRESSIONAL ABDICATION ON WAR AND
    SPENDING 24 (2000) (tracing practice to Budget and
    Accounting Act of 1921). Indeed, the President has long been
    required to submit an annual budget. 
    31 U.S.C. § 1105
    (a).
    Acting through OMB, the President uses his annual budget
    to influence the policies of independent agencies, including the
    FTC. Eloise Pasachoff, The President’s Budget as a Source
    of Agency Policy Control, 125 YALE L.J. 2182, 2191, 2203-04
    (2016) (independent agencies “must participate in the annual
    budget cycle under [the] oversight” of OMB’s Resource
    Management Offices, which in turn “serve as a conduit for
    policy and political direction from the President” and his staff);
    see, e.g., HARRIS & MILKIS, supra, at 204-05 (noting policy-
    driven budget cuts at FTC under President Reagan). The
    President lacks that leverage over the CFPB, which stands
    outside the budget. 
    12 U.S.C. § 5497
    (a)(1).
    Similarly, the President requires the FTC and other
    independent agencies to (inter alia) “prepare an agenda of all
    regulations under development or review” and submit them to
    the Office of Information and Regulatory Affairs, an arm of
    OMB, to ensure “coordination of regulations” that “promote
    the President’s priorities.” Exec. Order No. 12866 § 4, 
    58 Fed. Reg. 51735
     (Sept. 30, 1993); see Exec. Order No. 13563
    § 1(b), 
    76 Fed. Reg. 3821
     (Jan. 18, 2011) (“reaffirm[ing]” 1993
    order). But the requirements apply only “to the extent
    permitted by law,” Exec. Order No. 12866 § 4, and Title X
    exempts the CFPB by shielding it from OMB’s “jurisdiction or
    oversight,” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5497
    (a)(4)(E).
    21
    Second, unlike the FTC, the CFPB is not a “non-partisan”
    commission pursuing “entire impartiality” in law and policy.
    Humphrey’s Ex’r, 
    295 U.S. at 624
    . In contrast to the FTC, see
    
    id. at 620
    , the CFPB does not have a partisan balance
    requirement. Its single Director is from a single party—in
    most cases, presumably, the party of the President who
    appoints him.
    The CFPB contends that its single-Director, single-party
    structure is no greater threat to the President’s faithful
    execution of the laws than is the FTC’s multimember bipartisan
    structure. CFPB Br. 23-32. In fact, the CFPB says, the
    President can more easily replace or persuade one Director than
    three of five commissioners. See, e.g., Oral Arg. Tr. 49; see
    also Maj. Op. 35, 43-44 (making similar points). But if the
    President’s dissatisfaction is rooted in policy, it is just as
    impossible for him to remove a single official with for-cause
    protection as it is to remove several such officials. 8 And
    8
    Some commentators have suggested that a provision
    permitting removal for “‘inefficiency, neglect of duty, or
    malfeasance in office’” allows the President “to discharge officials
    whom he finds incompetent because of their consistently foolish
    policy choices.” Richard H. Pildes & Cass R. Sunstein, Reinventing
    the Regulatory State, 62 U. CHI. L. REV. 1, 30 (1995). Humphrey’s
    Executor leaves little or no room for that argument: the Supreme
    Court rebuffed President Roosevelt’s attempt to remove Humphrey
    based on the policies Humphrey had pursued for years. 
    295 U.S. at 619
     (President told Humphrey, “I do not feel that your mind and my
    mind go along together on either the policies or the administering of
    the Federal Trade Commission” (internal quotation omitted)); see
    Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 502
     (reading Humphrey’s Executor to
    suggest that “simple disagreement with [an official’s] policies or
    priorities” does not “constitute ‘good cause’ for [his] removal”); see
    also Amicus Br. of Current and Former Members of Congress
    Supporting CFPB 2 (arguing that 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (c)(3) does not
    permit President to remove Director “for policy differences alone”);
    22
    whether directed at one officer or more, attempts at persuasion
    are no substitute for removal. Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 502
     (“Congress cannot reduce the Chief Magistrate to a
    cajoler-in-chief.”).
    Moreover, because of the mismatch between the
    President’s four-year term and the Director’s five-year term,
    the CFPB’s entire leadership may for much of the President’s
    tenure—and sometimes all of it—identify with a political party
    other than the President’s. This does not happen at the FTC.
    The difference matters for accountability: a minority party of a
    multimember agency is “a built-in monitoring system,”
    dissenting when appropriate and serving as a “fire alarm” for
    the President and the public. Rachel E. Barkow, Insulating
    Agencies: Avoiding Capture Through Institutional Design, 89
    TEX. L. REV. 15, 41 (2010).
    Further, whereas the FTC is structured to administer the
    laws apolitically and with “impartiality,” Humphrey’s Ex’r,
    
    295 U.S. at 624
    , the CFPB’s design encourages the opposite.
    Title X gives the Director latitude to define and punish “unfair,
    deceptive, or abusive acts or practices” broadly or narrowly,
    Press Conference, Financial Regulations Bill, C-SPAN (Mar. 24,
    2010) (Rep. Frank: “I am obviously committed to a very strong
    independent consumer agency that can’t be overruled on policy
    grounds . . . .”), www.c-span.org/video/?292698-2/financial-
    regulations-bill (3:52-3:58). In a testament to how difficult it may
    be to remove a principal officer for cause, the CFPB admits that it
    “cannot” provide “any example where an agency head has been
    actually successfully removed for cause.” Oral Arg. Tr. 72. In any
    event, if Article II authorizes the President to remove a particular
    officer at will, he should not have to concern himself with the
    potential political cost of asserting inefficiency, neglect or
    malfeasance as cover for a policy choice. Cf. Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 547
     (Breyer, J., dissenting).
    23
    depending on his policy preferences. 
    12 U.S.C. § 5531
    (a),
    (b); see 
    id.
     § 5531(c), (d) (malleable statutory definitions of
    “unfair” and “abusive”). The legislators who supported Title
    X expected the Director to use that power—together with his
    authority over eighteen other laws—to “stick[] up for the little
    guy” in the “battle” against “all the big sharks and lobbyists
    and lawyers who are ganged up against [him].” 156 CONG.
    REC. 6364, 6366, 7015 (2010) (statements of Sen.
    Whitehouse); see id. at 3187 (statement of Sen. Kaufman)
    (CFPB is to “look[] out totally for the interest of consumers and
    consumers alone”). 9 The agency’s first Director shared that
    one-sided vision, describing his “sole focus” as “protecting
    consumers.” CFPB, Written Testimony of CFPB Director
    Richard Cordray Before the House Committee on Financial
    Services (Mar. 3, 2015), perma.cc/GAG6-ENDN.
    I do not question the importance of protecting consumers.
    But an agency cannot be considered “impartial[]” under
    Humphrey’s Executor if in partisan fashion it uniformly
    crusades for one segment of the populace against others.
    Consistent with its design, that is what the CFPB has done.
    See Dep’t of Treasury, A Financial System That Creates
    Economic Opportunities: Banks and Credit Unions 82-87
    9
    See also, e.g., 156 CONG. REC. 2052 (statement of Rep.
    Tsongas) (CFPB was designed to “level [the] playing field”); id. at
    6240 (statement of Sen. Franken) (it is “an independent watchdog for
    consumers”); id. at 7486 (statement of Sen. Dodd) (it is “one single,
    empowered, focused cop on the consumer protection beat”); id. at
    11814 (statement of Rep. Lee) (it “puts consumers first”); id.
    (statement of Rep. Fudge) (it “hold[s] Wall Street and the big banks
    accountable”); id. at 12414 (statement of Rep. McGovern) (it
    “empower[s] consumers”); id. at 12434 (statement of Rep. Maloney)
    (it is “on their side”); id. at 13135 (statement of Sen. Cardin) (it
    “represent[s]” consumers “in the financial structure”).
    24
    (June 2017) (Economic Opportunities) (cataloging
    questionable practices CFPB has undertaken at expense of
    regulated parties), perma.cc/V3SC-VXBH; Amicus Br. of U.S.
    Chamber of Commerce 16-29 (same).
    By at least some accounts, for instance, the CFPB under
    its first Director hired all but exclusively from one political
    party, deliberately weeding out applicants from other parties
    and the banking industry. Todd Zywicki, The Consumer
    Financial Protection Bureau: Savior or Menace?, 81 GEO.
    WASH. L. REV. 856, 877, 895 (2013) (asserting that agency
    hired staffers and “true believers” from one political party);
    Ronald L. Rubin, The Tragic Downfall of the Consumer
    Financial Protection Bureau, NAT’L REV., Dec. 21, 2016
    (alleging, from insider’s perspective, that agency used
    “screening techniques”), perma.cc/VR9F-TWHQ; cf. Bill
    McMorris, 100% of CFPB Donations Went to Democrats,
    WASH. FREE BEACON, Nov. 23, 2016 (reporting that, during
    2016 Presidential election, CFPB employees made more than
    300 donations totaling about $50,000, all of which went to
    candidates of one party), perma.cc/6JVQ-RRRQ.
    Additionally, the CFPB provides an online forum for
    consumers to complain publicly about providers of mortgages,
    student loans, credit cards and other financial products.
    CFPB, Consumer Complaint Database, perma.cc/VT2D-
    E6K5. The agency acknowledges that some complaints may
    be misleading or flat wrong. Disclosure of Consumer
    Complaint Narrative Data, 
    79 Fed. Reg. 42765
    , 42767 (July 23,
    2014) (“[T]he narratives may contain factually incorrect
    information . . . .”). Without attempting to verify them, the
    agency publishes the complaints anyway, knowing it is
    providing a “megaphone” for debtors who needlessly damage
    business reputations. CFPB, Prepared Remarks of CFPB
    Director Richard Cordray at the Consumer Response Field
    25
    Hearing (July 16, 2014), perma.cc/4S3G-9ALK. Compare
    that blinkered outlook with the FTC’s approach. The FTC
    likewise provides a complaint database to help deter and detect
    unfair business practices. But its database can be accessed
    only by law enforcement agencies, yielding similar value
    without the reputational costs. FTC, Consumer Sentinel
    Network, perma.cc/M5TZ-5USM. One cannot help but think
    that the difference in the FTC’s policy owes at least in part to
    the difference in its design.
    Consider also PHH’s case. In rulings reinstated today,
    see Maj. Op. 16-17, the panel rejected: the Director’s new
    interpretation of the anti-kickback provision of the Real Estate
    Settlement Procedures Act (RESPA), PHH Corp. v. CFPB, 
    839 F.3d 1
    , 39-44 (D.C. Cir. 2016), vacated upon grant of reh’g en
    banc (Feb. 16, 2017); his attempt to apply that interpretation
    retroactively to PHH, 
    id. at 44-49
    ; his construction of RESPA’s
    limitations provision, 
    id. at 52-55
    ; and his theory that the CFPB
    is bound by no limitations period in any administrative
    enforcement action under any of the laws the agency
    administers, 
    id. at 50-52
    . The issues were “not a close call”:
    the CFPB flunked “Rule of Law 101” and was called out for
    “gamesmanship” and “absurd[]” reasoning. 
    Id. at 41, 48-49, 55
    . An agency that gets the law so badly wrong four times
    over in its first major case in this circuit has a steep climb in
    claiming “[i]t is charged with the enforcement of no policy
    except the policy of the law.” Humphrey’s Ex’r, 
    295 U.S. at 624
    .
    Third, and relatedly, the Director is not a “body of experts”
    “informed by experience,” Humphrey’s Ex’r, 
    295 U.S. at 624
    (internal quotation omitted), because he is not a body at all.
    When a Director leaves at the end of his term, he takes with
    him all of the expertise and experience that his board of one
    has collected in five years. The new Director—faced with a
    26
    one-sided mission and armed with unilateral power to
    administer a complex web of laws at the heart of the credit
    economy—starts with no expertise qua rector and has no
    coequal colleagues with whom to deliberate. Far from
    “promot[ing] stability and confidence,” Maj. Op. 13; see id. at
    7, 33, full turnover from one insulated Director to the next is a
    recipe for jarring policy changes and costly rookie mistakes,
    see, e.g., PHH Corp., 839 F.3d at 7 (multitude of errors
    “resulted in a $109 million order against” PHH).
    By contrast, each FTC commissioner is informed by
    fellow commissioners who have years of collective experience
    as commissioners. See Kirti Datla & Richard L. Revesz,
    Deconstructing Independent Agencies (and Executive
    Agencies), 98 CORNELL L. REV. 769, 794 (2013)
    (“[M]ultimember agencies allow for the development of
    institutional memory.”). From the FTC’s inception, its
    staggered multimember structure has been central to its
    functions. The Congress passed the FTC Act in part because
    of dissatisfaction with the Bureau of Corporations, “a single-
    headed organization” better suited to “investigation and
    publicity” than to “judgment and discretion.” 51 CONG. REC.
    11092 (1914) (statement of Sen. Newlands, sponsor of FTC
    Act). As the Senate Report explained:
    It is manifestly desirable that the terms of the
    commissioners shall be long enough to give
    them an opportunity to acquire the expertness in
    dealing with these special questions concerning
    industry that comes from experience. The
    terms of the commissioners should expire in
    different years, in order that such changes as
    may be made from time to time shall not leave
    the commission deprived of men of experience
    in such questions.
    27
    One of the chief advantages of the proposed
    commission over the Bureau of Corporations
    lies in the fact that it will have greater prestige
    and independence, and its decisions, coming
    from a board of several persons, will be more
    readily accepted as impartial and well
    considered.
    S. REP. NO. 63-597, at 10-11 (1914).
    The CFPB’s proponents view its single-Director structure
    as a strong selling point. In the 111th Congress, they
    advocated for a regulator who can “keep pace with the
    changing financial system” and “respond quickly and
    effectively to . . . new threats to consumers.” S. REP. NO. 111-
    176, at 18, 40 (2010); see id. at 11 (agency must be
    “streamlined” and “have enough flexibility to address future
    problems as they arise”); 156 CONG. REC. 6237 (2010)
    (statement of Sen. Whitehouse) (agency must “monitor the
    market and act quickly when there is a consumer hazard”); id.
    at 12436 (statement of Rep. Meeks) (agency must “act swiftly”
    to protect consumers “from unscrupulous behavior”); id. at
    15025 (statement of Sen. Durbin) (agency must “keep up with
    the[] lawyers and accountants” of “the big banks on Wall
    Street”); cf. Warren, Unsafe at Any Rate, supra (agency must
    be prepared to take “quick action” against financial services
    industry). Similarly, in this Court, the agency’s proponents
    tout its single-Director structure as essential to preventing “the
    delay and gridlock to which multimember commissions are
    susceptible.” Amicus Br. of Current and Former Members of
    Congress Supporting CFPB 2; see id. at 15-20.
    I do not begin to assert that the Constitution “enacts social
    science about the benefits of group decision-making.” Tatel
    Concurring Op. 6 (internal quotation omitted). Far be it from
    28
    a judge to question the Congress’s conclusion that a single
    Director beats a multimember commission as a fast-acting
    solution to real-time problems. See Buckley v. Valeo, 
    424 U.S. 1
    , 138-39 (1976) (per curiam) (subject to constitutional
    constraints, Congress has authority to create and structure
    government offices “as it chooses”). My point is more
    modest: if the Director is a speedy unitary actor, he cannot also
    be a “quasi-legislative and quasi-judicial” “body of experts”
    exercising “trained judgment” by considered consensus.
    Humphrey’s Ex’r, 
    295 U.S. at 624, 629
    ; compare THE
    FEDERALIST NO. 70, at 472 (Alexander Hamilton) (J. Cooke
    ed., 1961) (“power in a single hand” is exercised with
    “dispatch”), with John Locke, The Second Treatise of Civil
    Government, in 2 THE TRADITION OF FREEDOM 201, 252 § 160
    (M. Mayer ed., 1957) (legislative power is “too numerous and
    so too slow for the dispatch requisite to execution”).
    In sum, the FTC is a deliberative expert nonpartisan
    agency that reports to the Congress. The CFPB is a unitary
    inexpert partisan agency that reports to no one. Because the
    former is no precedent for the latter, Humphrey’s Executor
    does not control here.
    c. CFPB Director distinguished from independent counsel
    As for Morrison, that case and this one are not on the same
    jurisprudential planet. At issue in Morrison was (inter alia)
    whether the Ethics in Government Act “impermissibly
    interferes with the President’s exercise of his constitutionally
    appointed functions” by “restricting the Attorney General’s
    power to remove the independent counsel to only those
    instances in which he can show ‘good cause.’” 
    487 U.S. at 685
    . The Supreme Court found no violation. 
    Id. at 685-93, 695-96
    . Crucially, however, the Court recognized that “the
    independent counsel [was] an inferior officer under the
    29
    Appointments Clause, with limited jurisdiction and tenure and
    lacking policymaking or significant administrative authority.”
    
    Id. at 691
     (emphasis added).
    The CFPB Director has even less in common with the
    independent counsel than with an FTC commissioner. As no
    one disputes, the Director is a principal officer: he has no
    “superior” who “direct[s] and supervise[s]” his work.
    Edmond v. United States, 
    520 U.S. 651
    , 662-63 (1997). The
    distinction between principal and inferior makes a considerable
    difference. The Constitution gives the Congress much more
    power over the appointment and removal of an inferior officer
    than over the appointment and removal of a principal officer,
    see U.S. CONST. art. II, § 2, cl. 2; Myers, 
    272 U.S. at 126-29
    , at
    least where, as here, the principal officer is not a legislative
    agent under Humphrey’s Executor. 10
    10
    During oral argument before the en banc Court, there was
    much discussion about our being bound by Morrison whether we like
    it or not. Oral Arg. Tr. 12-17, 25-26, 30-31, 82-83. Today, three
    of my colleagues continue to push the point. Tatel Concurring Op.
    5 (joined by Millett and Pillard, JJ.). I do not contradict it. See
    Hutto v. Davis, 
    454 U.S. 370
    , 375 (1982) (per curiam) (“[U]nless we
    wish anarchy to prevail within the federal judicial system, a
    precedent of [the Supreme] Court must be followed by the lower
    federal courts no matter how misguided the judges of those courts
    may think it to be.”). All but lost in that discussion, however, has
    been the distinction between this case’s principal officer and
    Morrison’s inferior officer. Counsel at oral argument only
    fleetingly mentioned it. Oral Arg. Tr. 15, 30-31, 83. The majority
    relegates it to an ipse dixit footnote, Maj. Op. 42 n.2, ignoring vital
    discussion in Myers, 272 U.S. at 126-29; see supra p. 9. And my
    colleagues in concurrence denigrate the distinction as “strained”
    without explaining why. Tatel Concurring Op. 5. I submit they
    can’t. The Supreme Court has described Morrison, together with
    Perkins, 
    116 U.S. at 485
    , as cases in which “the Court sustained . . .
    30
    The distinction makes good sense “in the context of a
    Clause designed to preserve political accountability relative to
    important Government assignments.” Edmond, 
    520 U.S. at 663
    . The more important the officer’s assignments, the more
    directly his actions implicate the President’s responsibility to
    faithfully execute the laws.         Myers, 
    272 U.S. at 132
    (President’s oversight “varies with the character of [the
    officer’s] service”); see 
    id. at 132-33
     (each principal executive
    officer charged with “highest and most important duties” of his
    department “must be the President’s alter ego”). And the
    more powerful the officer, the more likely the people will hold
    the President personally responsible if the officer formulates
    bad policy. 1 ANNALS OF CONG. 499 (statement of James
    Madison) (describing “chain of dependence” from “lowest
    officers” to “middle grade” to “highest” to “President” to
    restrictions on the power of principal executive officers—themselves
    responsible to the President—to remove their own inferiors,” Free
    Enter. Fund., 
    561 U.S. at 483
     (emphasis added). Administrations
    across the political spectrum have recognized that Morrison does not
    apply to removal of a principal officer. See The Constitutional
    Separation of Powers Between the President and Congress, 
    20 Op. O.L.C. 124
    , 169 (1996) (“The Morrison Court . . . had no occasion
    to consider the validity of removal restrictions affecting principal
    officers, officers with broad statutory responsibilities, or officers
    involved in executive branch policy formulation.”), perma.cc/DF3R-
    FFER; Amicus Br. of United States 14 n.3 (Morrison “obviously
    does not apply to any principal officer who heads an executive
    agency”). And most importantly, Article II itself distinguishes
    between principal and inferior. U.S. CONST. art. II, § 2, cl. 2; see 1
    ANNALS OF CONG. 548 (statement of James Madison) (“If the
    gentleman admits that the Legislature may vest the power of
    removal, with respect to inferior officers, he must also admit that the
    Constitution vests the President with the power of removal in the
    case of superior officers; because both powers are implied in the
    same words.”).
    31
    “community”); see, e.g., Editorial, President Cordray Strikes
    Again, WALL ST. J., Oct. 5, 2017 (criticizing President for not
    removing     Director),    on.wsj.com/2xmzcii;       Editorial,
    Republicans for Richard Cordray, WALL ST. J., Aug. 11, 2017
    (same), on.wsj.com/2fjuMpe; Editorial, Richard Cordray’s
    Financial Damage, WALL ST. J., July 12, 2017 (same),
    on.wsj.com/2w7nuIr; Editorial, Trump to Cordray: You’re Not
    Fired, WALL ST. J., June 20, 2017 (same),
    on.wsj.com/2hjw2G5.
    The Director is more powerful than the independent
    counsel and poses a more permanent threat to the President’s
    faithful execution of the laws. The independent counsel had
    “limited jurisdiction” to investigate and prosecute crimes
    pursuant to Department of Justice policy. Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 691
    ; see 
    id. at 672
    . She lacked “any authority to formulate
    policy” of her own. 
    Id. at 671
    ; see 
    id. at 691
    . She performed
    no “administrative duties outside of those necessary to operate
    her office.” 
    Id. at 671-72
    . She had “limited . . . tenure” and
    “no ongoing responsibilities”: her “temporary” office
    “terminated” when she finished investigating or prosecuting
    the matters for which she was called to duty. 
    Id. at 672
    (internal quotation omitted); see 
    id. at 664, 691
    .
    The Director’s jurisdiction and tenure, by contrast, are
    anything but “limited” and “temporary.” He has all but
    exclusive power to make and enforce rules under eighteen
    preexisting consumer laws and a nineteenth in Title X itself.
    
    12 U.S.C. §§ 5481
    (12), 5512(b)(4), 5562-5565, 5581(a)(1)(A).
    Under the latter, his power to define and punish “unfair,
    deceptive, or abusive acts or practices” is cabined by little more
    than his imagination. 
    Id.
     § 5531(a), (b). Absent inefficiency,
    neglect or malfeasance, he is guaranteed five years in which to
    impose on the people his version of consumer protection. 12
    
    32 U.S.C. § 5491
    (c)(1), (3). And the cycle immediately begins
    again when he is through.
    d. CFPB Director distinguished from claims adjudicator
    Wiener has still less bearing on this case than Morrison
    does. The parties apparently recognize as much, as their briefs
    do not cite it.
    In 1948, the Congress established the War Claims
    Commission, a temporary body consisting of three
    Commissioners whose sole task was to “adjudicate according
    to law” claims seeking compensation for injuries suffered
    during World War II. Wiener, 
    357 U.S. at 349-50
     (quoting
    War Claims Act of 1948, Pub. L. No. 80-896, § 3, 
    62 Stat. 1240
    , 1241 (July 3, 1948)). In 1950, President Truman, by
    and with the advice and consent of the Senate, appointed
    Myron Wiener as a Commissioner. 
    Id.
     In 1953, President
    Eisenhower removed Wiener not for lack of “rectitude” but
    because the President wanted “‘personnel of my own
    selection.’” 
    Id. at 350, 356
    . The Commission was abolished
    in 1954. 
    Id. at 350
    . Wiener sued for salary from the date of
    his removal. 
    Id. at 350-51
    .
    Viewing Wiener’s case as a “variant” of Humphrey’s
    Executor, the Supreme Court held that the War Claims Act
    implicitly protected him from removal except for cause and
    that the statute so construed was consistent with Article II.
    Wiener, 
    357 U.S. at 351
    ; see 
    id. at 352-56
    . The Court noted
    that Humphrey’s Executor “explicitly ‘disapproved’ the
    expressions in Myers supporting the President’s inherent
    constitutional power to remove members of quasi-judicial
    bodies.” 
    Id. at 352
     (quoting Humphrey’s Ex’r, 
    295 U.S. at 626-27
    ). Emphasizing “the intrinsic judicial character of the
    task with which the Commission was charged”—i.e.,
    adjudicating individual claims based on “evidence and
    33
    governing legal considerations”—the Court concluded that
    “[t]he philosophy of Humphrey’s Executor” controlled. Id. at
    355-56.
    As I read it, Wiener stands for the narrow proposition that
    the Congress can constitutionally bestow for-cause protection
    on an officer whose primary function is adjudication, given his
    need for independence.         
    357 U.S. at 355
    ; see The
    Constitutional Separation of Powers Between the President and
    Congress, 
    20 Op. O.L.C. 124
    , 170 & n.120 (1996) (suggesting
    Wiener is limited to officers “whose only functions are
    adjudicatory” or at most to officers “whose primary duties
    involve the adjudication of disputes involving private
    persons”), perma.cc/DF3R-FFER.
    The CFPB is not a quasi-judicial body. Nor does its
    Director have an “intrinsic judicial character.” Wiener, 
    357 U.S. at 355
    . Nor does the Director have as his primary
    function the adjudication of disputes. Adjudicative power is
    only a fraction of his entire authority. He is no less than the
    czar of consumer finance. In that realm, he is legislator,
    enforcer and judge. See supra pp. 16-17, 31-32. James
    Madison wrote that “[t]he accumulation of all powers
    legislative, executive, and judiciary in the same hands . . . may
    justly be pronounced the very definition of tyranny.” THE
    FEDERALIST NO. 47, at 324. The Director’s adjudicative
    power is part of the reason he meets Madison’s definition of a
    tyrant. And a tyrant with complete authority over “a vital
    sector of our economy,” Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 508
    ,
    cannot but threaten the President’s faithful execution of the
    laws in that realm. In my estimation, then, the Director’s
    34
    adjudicative power does not exempt him from at-will
    removal. 11
    My colleagues invoke Madison for the opposite
    conclusion. Maj. Op. 21, 31; Wilkins Concurring Op. 3-5.
    They point to his statement in the First Congress that “there
    may be strong reasons why” the Comptroller of the Treasury
    “should not hold his office at the pleasure of the Executive
    branch.” 1 ANNALS OF CONG. 612. He underscored that the
    Comptroller—whose “principal duty seems to be deciding
    upon the lawfulness and justice of the claims and accounts
    subsisting between the United States and particular citizens”—
    “partakes strongly of the judicial character.” 
    Id. at 611-12
    .
    For reasons just explained, that observation is inapposite here.
    It does not describe the CFPB Director, whose “principal duty”
    consists of far more than adjudicating “claims and accounts”
    through rote application of existing law. 12 
    Id.
    11
    Two of my colleagues think it significant not just that the
    Director has adjudicative power but that this case involves
    adjudication rather than enforcement. Wilkins Concurring Op. 1, 3,
    8 (joined by Rogers, J.). At best that is an argument for reserving
    judgment until, in a future case, a regulated party challenges the
    CFPB’s structure in the context of a rulemaking. It is not a basis for
    giving the agency an all-encompassing stamp of Article II approval
    in an opinion that does not purport to limit itself to cases involving
    adjudication. See generally Maj. Op. 1-68 (joined by Rogers and
    Wilkins, JJ.). In any event, no one has cited any authority for the
    idea that the CFPB’s constitutionality may differ case by case,
    depending on whether and to what extent the Director is wearing his
    adjudicator’s hat.
    12
    My colleagues also neglect the context of Madison’s
    statement. He made it in proposing that the Comptroller have fixed
    tenure “unless sooner removed by the President,” presumably for
    cause only. 1 ANNALS OF CONG. 612. His colleagues, including
    35
    *****
    In short, the CFPB and its Director have no ancestor in
    Humphrey’s Executor, Morrison or Wiener. Undeterred, the
    CFPB takes a divide-and-conquer approach to the structural
    features that in combination differentiate it from any
    predecessor.      It contends that each feature has no
    constitutional import standing alone and that, collectively, they
    add up to no problem at all. Oral Arg. Tr. 66-67 (“[W]hen you
    add them all together you’re adding zero plus zero plus zero
    plus zero, and at the end of the day . . . you’re still there with
    zero.”). The apt analogy is not math but chemistry: even if
    innocuous in isolation, some elements are toxic in combination.
    See, e.g., THE CAMBRIDGE ENCYCLOPEDIA 328 (D. Crystal ed.,
    1990) (cyanide, merely carbon plus nitrogen, is deadly); see
    also Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 496
     (second layer of for-
    cause protection did not only “add to the Board’s
    independence, but transform[ed] it”); 
    id. at 509
     (“a number of
    statutory provisions,” “working together,” “produce[d] a
    constitutional violation”); Ass’n of Am. R.Rs. v. Dep’t of
    Transp., 
    721 F.3d 666
    , 673 (D.C. Cir. 2013) (“[J]ust because
    his allies, disagreed with the proposal. Theodore Sedgwick, for one,
    objected that the Comptroller’s duties were both sufficiently
    “important” and sufficiently “Executive” that “the man who has to
    perform them ought . . . to be dependent upon the President.” 
    Id. at 613
    . Likewise, Egbert Benson lamented that Madison’s proposal
    “set[] afloat” what the House had already resolved: namely, that
    “judges hold their[] [offices] during good behaviour, as established
    by the Constitution” and that “all others [serve] during pleasure.”
    
    Id. at 614
    . Madison—who was known to change his mind, see, e.g.,
    KLARMAN, supra, at 384, 392-93, 561-66, 574-75, 737 n.300, 799
    n.58; David A. O’Neil, The Political Safeguards of Executive
    Privilege, 60 VAND. L. REV. 1079, 1134 & nn.232-35 (2007)—
    withdrew his proposal the very next day. 1 ANNALS OF CONG. 615.
    36
    two structural features raise no constitutional concerns
    independently does not mean Congress may combine them in
    a single statute.”), vacated on other grounds, 
    135 S. Ct. 1225
    (2015).
    The CFPB is not the first agency exempt from
    appropriations. See Budgetary Autonomy, supra, at 1823
    (pointing out, however, that list of other exempt agencies is
    “short” and “composed of narrowly focused” regulators
    “operat[ing] in technical sectors”). It is not the first agency
    headed by a single official or lacking a partisan balance
    requirement. See Datla & Revesz, supra, at 793-94 & nn.125,
    127 (listing agencies headed by single official); id. at 797
    (listing agencies with no partisan balance requirement). It is
    not the first agency with sweeping rulemaking and enforcement
    powers over an entire sector of the economy—the SEC comes
    to mind. But the CFPB is the only agency that combines each
    and every one of these elements with for-cause removal
    protection and a mission to “side” with one segment of the
    population against others. Neither the Supreme Court nor our
    Court has upheld anything like it before.
    2. Diminution of the Presidency
    Because the CFPB falls between the existing removal
    cases, our job is to decide the agency’s validity under first principles.13
    13
    I concede that Myers and Free Enterprise Fund do not
    squarely dictate the outcome here. The CFPB Director does not
    resemble a first-class postmaster and Title X does not purport to
    require the Senate’s advice and consent to remove him. Nor is the
    Director ensconced in multiple layers of for-cause removal
    protection. Recognizing as much, however, does not negate the
    textual, structural and functional lessons of Myers and Free
    37
    Humphrey’s Ex’r, 
    295 U.S. at 632
     (acknowledging possible
    “field of doubt” between Myers and Humphrey’s Executor and
    “leav[ing] such cases as may fall within it for future
    consideration”). So I go back to the beginning. Because
    “[o]ur Constitution was adopted to enable the people to govern
    themselves, through their elected leaders,” the President “as a
    general matter” has power to remove the principal officers of
    an agency—based on “simple disagreement with the
    [agency’s] policies or priorities”—as a means of ensuring that
    the agency does not “slip from the Executive’s control, and
    thus from that of the people.” Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 499, 502, 513
    ; see 
    id. at 509
     (“Under the traditional default
    rule, removal is incident to the power of appointment.”); 
    id. at 513
     (“The Constitution that makes the President accountable to
    the people for executing the laws also gives him the power to
    do so.”). If it were otherwise, the President would be
    “fasten[ed]” to subordinates who “by their lack of loyalty” or
    “different views of policy” would make it “difficult or
    impossible” for him to “faithfully execute[]” the laws. Myers,
    
    272 U.S. at 131
    .
    To date, the Supreme Court has recognized only one
    exception to the default rule: Humphrey’s Executor. The
    CFPB violates the rule, see 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (c)(3), and does
    not fit within the exception, see supra pp. 15-28. The
    question, then, is whether we should stretch the exception to
    reach the CFPB. That is what my colleagues do today, even if
    they do not say so. But just as we cannot overrule Supreme
    Court decisions, Shea v. Kerry, 
    796 F.3d 42
    , 54 (D.C. Cir.
    2015); see Tatel Concurring Op. 5, we have no business
    fundamentally recalibrating them, Humphries v. Ozmint, 
    397 F.3d 206
    , 225 n.9 (4th Cir. 2005) (en banc) (“we, as judges of
    Enterprise Fund. They are the best guidance we have about the
    original and enduring meaning of Article II.
    38
    an inferior court, are without liberty to change” Supreme Court
    “framework”). Even if the FTC and the CFPB were not as
    dissimilar as I believe they are, I would be loath to cede any
    more of Article II than Humphrey’s Executor squarely
    demands. See FCC v. Fox Television Stations, Inc., 
    556 U.S. 502
    , 525-26 (2009) (opinion of Scalia, J.) (“There is no reason
    to magnify the separation-of-powers dilemma posed by the
    headless Fourth Branch . . . .”); see also Ziglar v. Abbasi, 
    137 S. Ct. 1843
    , 1864 (2017) (“[E]ven a modest extension is still
    an extension.”).
    Given the CFPB’s novelty, we must “[a]t the very least”
    “‘pause to consider the implications of’” sustaining it. Cf.
    Nat’l Fed’n of Indep. Bus. v. Sebelius, 
    567 U.S. 519
    , 550
    (2012) (opinion of Roberts, C.J.) (quoting United States v.
    Lopez, 
    514 U.S. 549
    , 564 (1995)). The CFPB assures us that
    “the President has an 80 percent chance . . . to be guaranteed
    an opportunity to replace the Bureau’s Director.” Oral Arg.
    Tr. 49. That is hardly comforting. It means there is a twenty
    per cent chance the President will have no at-will opportunity
    to replace the agency’s leader—and no real policy influence
    over the agency—for the entirety of the President’s four-year
    term. Furthermore, the odds grow ever larger that the
    President will have no such opportunity or influence during his
    first three years, first two years, first year and first hundred
    days. The President cannot be reduced to appointer-in-chief,
    cf. Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 502
    , especially if his
    appointment power turns on luck of the draw, see 
    id. at 500
    (separation of powers “cannot be permitted to turn on”
    “bureaucratic minutiae” (internal quotation omitted)).
    Even assuming the CFPB violates Article II only some of
    the time—a year here, a couple years there—that is not a strong
    point in its favor. Heedless of the implications for the
    Presidency, my colleagues plow ahead and sustain the agency
    39
    anyway. The case-specific result is disturbing enough: the
    people will suffer this agency’s unnecessary mistakes for years
    to come. Worse, however, is that the majority’s logic invites
    aggregation. Suppose the Congress over time decides to
    restructure, say, the FTC, the SEC, the Federal Election
    Commission (FEC) and the National Labor Relations Board
    (NLRB) so that each stands outside of the appropriations
    process and is headed by a single political-minded director
    removable only for cause and tenured for five years. 14 Or
    make it seven years. Cf. 
    15 U.S.C. § 41
     (tenure for FTC
    commissioner). Or fourteen years. Cf. 
    12 U.S.C. § 241
    (tenure for member of Federal Reserve Board of Governors).
    Now throw in fourteen years for the CFPB Director. I can
    discern no reason why the majority would not approve all of
    that and more if it happened one step at a time. But if the FTC,
    SEC, FEC, NLRB and CFPB were each headed by a fast-acting
    partisan director with fourteen years of tenure, the policy havoc
    they could collectively inflict from within the executive branch
    without having to answer to the executive would be too much
    for Article II to bear.
    14
    This is not a farfetched hypothetical. The principal officers
    of each agency already have for-cause removal protection. 
    15 U.S.C. § 41
     (expressly providing it for FTC commissioners); Free
    Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 487
     (assuming, even absent express
    provision, that SEC commissioners have it); FEC v. NRA Political
    Victory Fund, 
    6 F.3d 821
    , 826 (D.C. Cir. 1993) (same as to FEC
    commissioners); 
    29 U.S.C. § 153
    (a) (expressly providing it for
    NLRB members). Also, the principal officers of each agency
    already enjoy tenure of at least five years. 
    15 U.S.C. § 41
     (seven
    years for FTC commissioners); 15 U.S.C. § 78d(a) (five years for
    SEC commissioners); 
    52 U.S.C. § 30106
    (a)(2)(A) (six years for FEC
    commissioners); 
    29 U.S.C. § 153
    (a) (five years for NLRB members).
    40
    The erosion of Presidential responsibility, no less than the
    “accretion” of Presidential power, can be “dangerous” even
    when it “does not come in a day.” Youngstown Sheet & Tube
    Co. v. Sawyer, 
    343 U.S. 579
    , 594 (1952) (Frankfurter, J.,
    concurring); see Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 497
     (“[I]f
    allowed to stand, this dispersion of responsibility could be
    multiplied.”); 
    id. at 499
     (“[W]here, in all this, is the role for
    oversight by an elected President?”). I would draw the line
    right here and now.
    3. Lack of accountability
    If forced to expand the Humphrey’s Executor exception, I
    would limit it to an agency that answers in some meaningful
    way to the policy oversight of at least one political branch.
    See Myers, 
    272 U.S. at 131-32
     (emphasizing need for “chain”
    of “responsibility” from appointed officers to populace
    (quoting 1 ANNALS OF CONG. 499, 523 (statements of James
    Madison and Theodore Sedgwick))); see also Free Enter.
    Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 501
     (“The Framers created a structure in
    which ‘[a] dependence on the people’ would be the ‘primary
    controul on the government.’” (quoting THE FEDERALIST NO.
    51, at 349 (James Madison))); McCulloch, 17 U.S. (4 Wheat.)
    at 405 (ours is “a government of the people”). The CFPB fails
    even this minimal test of accountability. The agency and its
    proponents cite a grab bag of purported checks on the agency’s
    authority but none is an adequate substitute for removal at the
    President’s will. 15
    15
    In my view, there is no constitutionally appropriate stand-in
    for the President’s removal power. See Horne v. USDA, 
    135 S. Ct. 2419
    , 2428 (2015) (because Constitution “is concerned with means
    as well as ends,” court cannot permit “shorter cut than the
    constitutional way” (internal quotation omitted)). But because the
    majority downgrades at-will removal to a congressional benefaction,
    41
    First, the Congress’s ability to restructure the CFPB is not
    an adequate substitute check. Contra, e.g., CFPB Br. 28 n.8
    (emphasizing that Congress can pass legislation subjecting
    CFPB to appropriations process); Amicus Br. of Americans for
    Financial Reform et al. 15 (pointing out that Congress can
    amend “organic statute” if it wants to “revisit[]” agency’s
    design).
    In Free Enterprise Fund, the Supreme Court rejected the
    contention that the SEC’s functional control over the Public
    Company Accounting Oversight Board “blun[ted] the
    constitutional impact of for-cause removal.” 
    561 U.S. at 504
    (internal quotation omitted). The Court explained that
    “altering the budget or powers of an agency as a whole is a
    problematic way to control an inferior officer. The [SEC]
    cannot wield a free hand to supervise individual members if it
    must destroy the Board in order to fix it.” 
    Id.
    The Court’s reasoning applies with equal force to the
    Congress’s ability to restructure the CFPB. See Oral Arg. Tr.
    34, Free Enter. Fund v. PCAOB, S. Ct. No. 08-861 (Dec. 7,
    2009) (Justice Scalia: “I’m not sure that [the Congress’s]
    ability to take away responsibility . . . from an agency is the
    same as controlling what authority that agency does exercise.”
    (emphasis added)). Refashioning the agency as a whole is a
    ham-handed way to monitor the Director’s handling of a
    specific policy matter. Similarly, threatening to alter the
    agency does not give the Congress much leverage either. Any
    Director with the political instinct for the job knows that,
    nowadays especially, transformative legislation is akin to a bolt
    of lightning. See Perry v. MSPB, 
    137 S. Ct. 1975
    , 1990 (2017)
    (Gorsuch, J., dissenting) (“[T]he demands of bicameralism and
    we should at least require the Congress to devise a second-best way
    of ensuring the CFPB answers to the people.
    42
    presentment are real and the process can be protracted. [And]
    the difficulty of making new laws isn’t some bug in the
    constitutional design; it’s the point of the design . . . .”);
    Budgetary Autonomy, supra, at 1831-32 (describing hurdles
    such as “crowded agenda,” “filibuster” and need for “support
    of congressional leadership”). At all events, an otherwise
    invalid agency is no less invalid merely because the Congress
    can fix it at some undetermined point in the future.
    Second, judicial review under the Administrative
    Procedure Act is not a meaningful substitute check. Contra,
    e.g., Amicus Br. of Americans for Financial Reform et al. 15.
    Some of the CFPB’s excesses will “occur[] in the twilight of
    judicially unreviewable discretion.” PHH Corp., 839 F.3d at
    35; see Chevron, 
    467 U.S. at 844-45
    ; 
    12 U.S.C. §§ 5512
    (b)(4)(B), 5581(b)(5)(E)(ii); 15 U.S.C. § 1693b(e)(1).
    And even if the courts could review de novo everything the
    CFPB does, that would not suffice for today’s purpose. The
    chain of responsibility from the agency to the judiciary does
    not then link to the people. Federal judges “have no
    constituency,” Chevron, 
    467 U.S. at 866
    , and are therefore no
    proxy for the people’s representatives in deciding consumer-
    finance policy, TVA v. Hill, 
    437 U.S. 153
    , 195 (1978) (courts
    decide legal questions, leaving it to “political branches” to
    decide “what accords with common sense and the public weal”
    (internal quotation omitted)).
    Third, procedural requirements associated with CFPB
    rulemaking are not a meaningful substitute check. Contra,
    e.g., Amicus Br. of Financial Regulation Scholars 23.
    Granted, the agency must adhere to notice-and-comment
    procedures, 
    5 U.S.C. §§ 500
    (a)(1), 551, 553; must “consider”
    the costs and benefits of proposed rules, 
    12 U.S.C. § 5512
    (b)(2)(A); and must “consult” with other financial
    regulators about the rules, 
    id.
     § 5512(b)(2)(B).         But
    43
    rulemaking requirements cannot constrain the CFPB when it
    formulates policy through an enforcement action rather than
    rulemaking. The CFPB has done this a lot, perhaps because
    of the rulemaking requirements. See Dep’t of Treasury,
    Economic Opportunities, supra, at 82-83 (describing CFPB’s
    “[e]xcessive reliance on enforcement actions, rather than rules
    and guidance, to regulate conduct”). Notably, the CFPB has
    initiated no rulemaking to explain to the regulated public, ex
    ante, what the agency will deem “an unfair, deceptive, or
    abusive act or practice.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5531
    (a). Nor is there
    any indication in the briefs or the record before us that the
    agency has any plans to change its know-it-when-we-see-it
    approach. See CFPB, Prepared Remarks of CFPB Director
    Richard Cordray at the Consumer Bankers Association (Mar.
    9, 2016) (suggesting that CFPB’s critics “set[] the bar too high”
    in expecting agency to “think through and explicitly articulate
    rules for every eventuality” before initiating enforcement
    actions), perma.cc/79TC-BQMA.
    Fourth, and finally, the threat of supermajority veto by the
    Financial Stability Oversight Council is not a meaningful
    substitute check. Contra, e.g., Amicus Br. of Financial
    Regulation Scholars 23; Wilkins Concurring Op. 13-15. The
    Council (another unelected body) can “set aside a final
    regulation” of the CFPB only if the regulation “would put the
    safety and soundness of the United States banking system or
    the stability of the financial system of the United States at risk.”
    
    12 U.S.C. § 5513
    (a). As far as the Council is concerned, then,
    the CFPB can break the law or abuse its power as long as it
    does so (1) in an enforcement action or (2) in a regulation that
    does not threaten national financial ruin.
    A recent episode illustrates how toothless the Council’s
    veto is in controlling CFPB policy. In July 2017, the CFPB
    finalized one of its most controversial policies to date: a rule
    44
    prohibiting certain providers from entering arbitration
    agreements with consumers to stave off class actions. CFPB,
    Final Rule: Arbitration Agreements (July 10, 2017),
    perma.cc/N3JH-573A.         The acting Comptroller of the
    Currency, one of the Council’s ten voting members, 
    12 U.S.C. § 5321
    (b)(1)(C), sought data so that he could determine the
    rule’s “safety and soundness implications.” Letter from Keith
    Noreika to Richard Cordray (July 17, 2017), perma.cc/3X6D-
    YZS6. In response, the CFPB Director asserted that, because
    the rule’s projected impact is “less than $1 billion per year,” it
    is “plainly frivolous” to suggest the rule “poses a safety and
    soundness issue.” Letter from Richard Cordray to Keith
    Noreika (July 18, 2017), perma.cc/76MU-39PC.                 The
    Director also implied that the Comptroller was “distort[ing] the
    FSOC process” because of a mere “disagree[ment] with the
    policy judgments for the rule.” 
    Id.
    The rule was published in the Federal Register the next
    day. 16 Arbitration Agreements, 
    82 Fed. Reg. 33210
     (July 19,
    2017). The fact that anyone mentions the Council’s narrow
    16
    A few months later, the Congress passed and the President
    signed a joint resolution that disapproves the rule. Joint Resolution
    of Nov. 1, 2017, Pub. L. No. 115-74, 
    131 Stat. 1243
    ,
    perma.cc/U4GE-6W72. The Congress acted pursuant to the
    Congressional Review Act (CRA), 
    5 U.S.C. §§ 801
     et seq., which
    authorizes it to disapprove an agency rule by simple majority in both
    Houses within 60 legislative days after the agency submits the rule.
    See Daniel Cohen & Peter L. Strauss, Congressional Review of
    Agency Regulations, 49 ADMIN. L. REV. 95, 96-102 (1997) (detailing
    CRA’s provisions and procedures). Regarding the CFPB, the CRA
    is not an adequate substitute for at-will removal, especially in light
    of its inapplicability to enforcement actions.
    45
    veto as a check is instead a testament to the CFPB’s
    unaccountable policymaking power.
    II. THE FOR-CAUSE REMOVAL PROVISION CANNOT
    BE SEVERED FROM THE REST OF TITLE X
    Judge Kavanaugh and I agree that Title X’s for-cause
    removal provision, 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (c)(3), is unconstitutional.
    But he would excise section 5491(c)(3) and preserve the rest of
    Title X. Kavanaugh Dissenting Op. 68-73. I respectfully
    disagree with that approach. Above all else, the 111th
    Congress wanted the CFPB to be independent: free, that is,
    from industry influence and the changing political tides that
    come with accountability to the President. Severing section
    5491(c)(3) would yield an executive agency entirely at odds
    with the legislative design. In my view, the Congress would
    not have enacted Title X in its current form absent for-cause
    removal protection. I believe, therefore, that the appropriate
    remedy for the CFPB’s Article II problem is to invalidate Title
    X in its entirety. 17
    17
    I recognize that severability is to be considered “when
    confronting a constitutional flaw in a statute,” Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 508
     (internal quotation omitted), and that my colleagues in
    the majority find no such flaw in Title X. I nonetheless address
    severability because it bears on my threshold view that we must
    decide the Article II question in light of the relief PHH now seeks:
    vacatur without remand and cessation of any further proceedings.
    See supra note 3; cf. INS v. Chadha, 
    462 U.S. 919
    , 931-36 (1983)
    (addressing severability at threshold because it bore on standing).
    46
    A. THE LAW OF SEVERABILITY
    When remedying a constitutional defect, a court should not
    “nullify more of a legislature’s work than is necessary” because
    the “ruling of unconstitutionality” already “frustrates the intent
    of the elected representatives of the people.” Ayotte v.
    Planned Parenthood of N. New Eng., 
    546 U.S. 320
    , 329 (2006)
    (internal quotation omitted). Neither, however, should the
    court use the severability doctrine to “rewrit[e]” an
    unconstitutional statute because that also “circumvent[s] the
    intent of the legislature.” 
    Id. at 329-30
     (internal quotation
    omitted); see Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 510
     (doctrine does
    not give court “editorial freedom”); United States v. Reese, 
    92 U.S. 214
    , 221 (1875) (court cannot “introduce words” into
    statute).
    With those competing considerations in mind, the court
    must ask whether the statute minus any invalid provision “will
    function in a manner consistent with the intent of Congress”
    and “is legislation that Congress would . . . have enacted.”
    Alaska Airlines, 480 U.S. at 685 (emphasis in original). If the
    answer to either component of the question is no, the invalid
    provision cannot be severed. Id. In deciding the question,
    the court looks to the statute’s “language,” “structure” and
    “legislative history.” Id. at 687; see, e.g., id. at 687-97
    (weighing all three); Regan v. Time, Inc., 
    468 U.S. 641
    , 652-55
    (1984) (plurality opinion) (same); INS v. Chadha, 
    462 U.S. 919
    , 931-35 (1983) (same); see also 2 NORMAN J. SINGER &
    J.D. SHAMBIE SINGER, SUTHERLAND STATUTES & STATUTORY
    CONSTRUCTION § 44:3, at 591-92 (7th ed. 2009) (noting related
    factors such as “circumstances” of enactment and “object” of
    statute).
    A severability clause can be probative of legislative intent
    but it is by no means dispositive. Dorchy v. Kansas, 
    264 U.S. 47
    286, 290 (1924) (“[I]t is an aid merely; not an inexorable
    command.”); see United States v. Jackson, 
    390 U.S. 570
    , 585
    n.27 (1968) (“[T]he ultimate determination of severability will
    rarely turn on the presence or absence of such a clause.”); 2
    SINGER & SINGER, supra, § 44:8, at 627 (“Because of the
    frequency with which it is used, the separability clause is
    regarded as little more than a mere formality.”). In the federal
    courts, a severability clause creates only a rebuttable
    “presumption that Congress did not intend the validity of the
    statute in question to depend on the validity of the
    constitutionally offensive provision.” Alaska Airlines, 480
    U.S. at 686; see Dorchy, 
    264 U.S. at 290
     (treating severability
    clause as “a rule of construction”). Thus, the Supreme Court
    sometimes declines to sever an invalid provision despite a
    severability clause. See, e.g., City of Akron v. Akron Ctr. for
    Reprod. Health, Inc., 
    462 U.S. 416
    , 425 n.8, 445-46 n.37
    (1983), overruled on other grounds by Planned Parenthood of
    Se. Pa. v. Casey, 
    505 U.S. 833
     (1992); Planned Parenthood of
    Cent. Mo. v. Danforth, 
    428 U.S. 52
    , 83-84 (1976); Sloan v.
    Lemon, 
    413 U.S. 825
    , 833-35 (1973); Hill v. Wallace, 
    259 U.S. 44
    , 70-71 (1922).
    B. INDEPENDENCE AS SINE QUA NON OF TITLE X
    At the outset of Title X, the Congress “established” the
    CFPB as “an independent bureau.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (a). 18
    The Supreme Court has long used the term “independent
    18
    Section 5491(a) also says that the CFPB “shall be
    considered an Executive agency, as defined in section 105 of Title
    5.” All that really means, however, is that the agency is an arm of
    the federal government: for the purpose of 
    5 U.S.C. § 105
    , an
    “Executive agency” includes not only “an Executive department” but
    also “a Government corporation” and “an independent
    establishment.”
    48
    agenc[y]” to describe an agency run by principal officers
    sheltered from the “President’s power to remove.” Buckley,
    
    424 U.S. at 136
    ; see, e.g., Bowsher v. Synar, 
    478 U.S. 714
    , 725
    n.4 (1986). Significantly, the Court used the same definition
    in Free Enterprise Fund just a few weeks before the Congress
    enacted Title X. 
    561 U.S. at 483
     (“Congress can, under
    certain circumstances, create independent agencies run by
    principal officers appointed by the President, whom the
    President may not remove at will but only for good cause.”).
    Because we are to assume the Congress is familiar with
    Supreme Court precedents—especially the “unusually
    important” ones, Cannon v. Univ. of Chicago, 
    441 U.S. 677
    ,
    699 (1979)—“an independent bureau” is best understood to
    mean the kind of agency Free Enterprise Fund described: one
    whose principal officer enjoys for-cause removal protection.
    In other words, section 5491(a) ties the CFPB’s very
    existence to its freedom from the President. That is powerful
    evidence the Congress opposed the idea of a CFPB answerable
    to him. Other statutory features reinforce the conclusion.
    As discussed earlier, the Congress transferred to the CFPB
    the authority to enforce and issue rules under eighteen existing
    laws previously administered by seven different federal
    agencies. 
    12 U.S.C. §§ 5481
    (12), 5512(b)(4), 5581. A
    majority of those agencies are themselves more or less free
    from Presidential control. 
    Id.
     § 5581(a)(2)(A) (Federal
    Reserve Board of Governors, Federal Deposit Insurance
    Corporation, FTC and National Credit Union Administration).
    Reinventing the CFPB as an executive agency through excision
    of section 5491(c)(3) would by judicial decree transfer to the
    executive branch far-reaching new powers that, before Title X,
    resided with several non-executive agencies.
    49
    Even if that result might be worth cheering for the purpose
    of accountability, it is not what the Congress had in mind. The
    floor statements in support of Title X highlighted, more than
    any other consideration, the CFPB’s need for independence.
    See, e.g., 156 CONG. REC. 2052 (2010) (statement of Rep.
    Tsongas); id. at 3187 (statement of Sen. Kaufman); id. at 6237,
    6365, 7015 (statements of Sen. Whitehouse); id. at 6240
    (statement of Sen. Franken); id. at 6990 (statement of Sen.
    Reid); id. at 7481, 7485-86, 8931 (statements of Sen. Dodd);
    id. at 9447 (statement of Rep. Kilroy); id. at 9839 (statement of
    Rep. Holt); id. at 11814 (statement of Rep. Lee); id. at 12434
    (statement of Rep. Maloney); id. at 13135 (statement of Sen.
    Cardin).
    Likewise, in this Court, the CFPB’s strongest backers have
    repeatedly emphasized its independence as a sine qua non.
    See, e.g., Amicus Br. of Current and Former Members of
    Congress Supporting Rehearing En Banc 2 (“By . . . severing
    the provision that made [the] Director removable only for
    cause, the panel decision fundamentally altered the CFPB and
    hampered its ability to function as Congress intended.”);
    Amicus Br. of Americans for Financial Reform et al. 2-3 (“The
    Bureau’s independence has been critical to its ability to remain
    a steadfast enforcer of the consumer protection laws despite
    massive political opposition from the financial industry.”);
    Amicus Br. of Financial Regulation Scholars 17-18
    (“Regulated industries are likely to bring concentrated political
    pressure to bear on the White House to influence an agency
    whose head is subject to at-will removal to adjust policy in
    favor of the industry.”); cf. Maj. Op. 16, 68 (Congress sought
    to “insulat[e]” CFPB “from political winds and [P]residential
    will” but panel majority, by excising section 5491(c)(3),
    “effectively turned the CFPB into an instrumentality of the
    President”).
    50
    Indeed, the Congress so valued the CFPB’s independence
    that it forfeited its own oversight by exempting the agency from
    appropriations. The intent, as the CFPB’s architects made
    plain, was to give the agency watertight freedom from both of
    the elected branches, lest the agency’s mission be
    compromised by shifting popular will, the “financial . . .
    industry lobby” or “legislative micromanaging.” Warren,
    Unsafe at Any Rate, supra; see, e.g., S. REP. NO. 111-176, at
    163 (finding that “adequate funding, independent of the
    Congressional appropriations process, is absolutely essential”
    to CFPB’s “independent operations”); 156 CONG. REC. 8931
    (statement of Sen. Dodd) (“[T]he [CFPB’s] funding will be
    independent and reliable so that its mission cannot be
    compromised by political maneuvering.”). 19
    The upshot is that excising section 5491(c)(3) would yield
    a mutant CFPB responsive to the President—and hence to
    majoritarian politics and lobbying—but nowise accountable to
    the Congress. Where, as here, severing a statutory provision
    “alters the balance of powers between the Legislative and
    Executive Branches,” we must consider whether our effective
    “delegation[] of power to the Executive . . . may have been so
    controversial or so broad that Congress would have been
    19
    Title X’s proponents modeled the CFPB in part on the
    Consumer Product Safety Commission. See, e.g., Warren, Unsafe
    at Any Rate, supra; 156 CONG. REC. 6219 (statement of Sen. Dodd);
    id. at 6237 (statement of Sen. Whitehouse); id. at 6239 (statement of
    Sen. Merkley); id. at 6363 (statement of Sen. Durbin). But they also
    learned a lesson from the Commission: because it is subject to
    appropriations, it answers to “budgetary politics” and has long
    suffered policy-based cuts. HARRIS & MILKIS, supra, at 124; see,
    e.g., id. (describing cuts under President Reagan); Eric Lipton, Safety
    Agency Faces Scrutiny Amid Changes, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 2, 2007
    (describing cuts under President George W. Bush), nyti.ms/2jKal6h.
    51
    unwilling to make the delegation without a strong oversight
    mechanism.” Alaska Airlines, 
    480 U.S. at 685
     (considering
    severability of legislative veto). After all, “one branch’s
    handicap is another’s strength” and vice versa. Free Enter.
    Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 500
    .
    A CFPB responsive to the President would have been too
    “controversial” to pass the 111th Congress. Alaska Airlines,
    
    480 U.S. at 685
    . At the very least it would not have passed
    absent “strong oversight” via the appropriations process. 
    Id.
    But we judges cannot subject the agency to appropriations; to
    do so would be to “blue-pencil” still more of Title X, Free
    Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 509
    , and potentially introduce new
    provisions of our own. Nor can we convert the agency into a
    multimember commission. True, in contrast to a CFPB
    responsive to the President, a multimember CFPB “would
    deviate less radically from Congress’ intended system.”
    United States v. Booker, 
    543 U.S. 220
    , 247 (2005); see Amicus
    Br. of Current and Former Members of Congress Supporting
    CFPB 17-20 (Congress seriously considered multimember
    structure). Yet that alternative, too, would be a rewrite for the
    Congress and not the courts. See Free Enter. Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 509-10
    ; Ayotte, 
    546 U.S. at 329-30
    ; Reese, 92 U.S. at 221.
    The best argument for excising section 5491(c)(3) is
    Dodd-Frank’s severability clause, 
    12 U.S.C. § 5302
    , but it does
    not change my view. Appearing in the mega Dodd-Frank
    legislation 574 pages before section 5491(c)(3), see 124 Stat.
    at 1390, 1964, section 5302 provides in relevant part that “[i]f
    any provision of this Act . . . is held to be unconstitutional, the
    remainder of this Act . . . shall not be affected thereby.” The
    clause says nothing specific about Title X, let alone the CFPB’s
    independence, let alone for-cause removal, let alone the
    massive transfer of power inherent in deleting section
    5491(c)(3), let alone whether the Congress would have
    52
    endorsed that transfer of power even while subjecting the
    CFPB to the politics of Presidential control. Instead, as one of
    Dodd-Frank’s architects said decades earlier of a materially
    identical clause: “This is just boilerplate severability.” 134
    CONG. REC. 12280 (1988) (statement of Rep. Frank). Thus,
    beyond the standard presumption that section 5302 creates, see
    Alaska Airlines, 
    480 U.S. at 686
    , it tells us little about how the
    Congress would deal with invalidation of section 5491(c)(3) in
    particular, see Max Radin, A Short Way With Statutes, 56
    HARV. L. REV. 388, 419 (1942) (“Are we really to imagine that
    the legislature . . . weighed each paragraph literally and c[a]me
    to the conclusion that it would have enacted that paragraph if
    all the rest of the statute were invalid?”).
    For reasons already stated, the presumption of severability
    is rebutted here. A severability clause “does not give the court
    power to amend” a statute. Hill, 
    259 U.S. at 71
    . Nor is it a
    license to cut out the “heart” of a statute. Cf. Alaska Airlines,
    
    480 U.S. at 691
    . Because section 5491(c)(3) is at the heart of
    Title X, I would strike Title X in its entirety.
    *****
    As a guarantor of self-government, Article II has always
    been “one of the Constitution’s best provisions.” Saikrishna
    Prakash, The Essential Meaning of Executive Power, 2003 U.
    ILL. L. REV. 701, 725 (quoting 1788 North Carolina ratification
    debate) (brackets omitted). But it suffers a major defeat today
    and will suffer more if today’s decision stands. In my view,
    the CFPB violates Article II and should be invalidated top to
    bottom.
    Accordingly, I dissent.
    KAVANAUGH, Circuit Judge, with whom Senior Circuit
    Judge RANDOLPH joins, dissenting:
    INTRODUCTION AND SUMMARY
    This is a case about executive power and individual
    liberty.
    To prevent tyranny and protect individual liberty, the
    Framers of the Constitution separated the legislative,
    executive, and judicial powers of the new national government.
    To further safeguard liberty, the Framers insisted upon
    accountability for the exercise of executive power. The
    Framers lodged full responsibility for the executive power in a
    President of the United States, who is elected by and
    accountable to the people. The first 15 words of Article II
    speak with unmistakable clarity about who controls the
    executive power: “The executive Power shall be vested in a
    President of the United States of America.” U.S. CONST. art.
    II, § 1. And Article II assigns the President alone the authority
    and responsibility to “take Care that the Laws be faithfully
    executed.” Id. § 3. The purpose “of the separation and
    equilibration of powers in general, and of the unitary Executive
    in particular, was not merely to assure effective government but
    to preserve individual freedom.” Morrison v. Olson, 
    487 U.S. 654
    , 727 (1988) (Scalia, J., dissenting).
    Of course, the President executes the laws with the
    assistance of subordinate executive officers who are appointed
    by the President, often with the advice and consent of the
    Senate. To carry out the executive power and be accountable
    for the exercise of that power, the President must be able to
    supervise and direct those subordinate officers. In its
    landmark decision in Myers v. United States, 
    272 U.S. 52
    (1926), authored by Chief Justice and former President Taft,
    the Supreme Court recognized the President’s Article II
    2
    authority to supervise, direct, and remove at will subordinate
    officers in the Executive Branch.
    In 1935, however, the Supreme Court carved out an
    exception to Myers and Article II by permitting Congress to
    create independent agencies that exercise executive power.
    See Humphrey’s Executor v. United States, 
    295 U.S. 602
    (1935). An agency is “independent” when the agency’s
    commissioners or board members are removable by the
    President only for cause, not at will, and therefore are not
    supervised or directed by the President. Examples of
    independent agencies include well-known bodies such as the
    Federal Trade Commission, the Federal Communications
    Commission, the Securities and Exchange Commission, the
    National Labor Relations Board, and the Federal Energy
    Regulatory Commission.
    Those and other independent agencies exercise executive
    power by bringing enforcement actions against private citizens.
    Those agencies often promulgate legally binding regulations
    pursuant to statutes enacted by Congress, and they adjudicate
    disputes involving private parties. So those agencies exercise
    executive, quasi-legislative, and quasi-judicial power.
    The independent agencies collectively constitute, in effect,
    a headless fourth branch of the U.S. Government. They hold
    enormous power over the economic and social life of the
    United States. Because of their massive power and the
    absence of Presidential supervision and direction, independent
    agencies pose a significant threat to individual liberty and to
    the constitutional system of separation of powers and checks
    and balances.
    To mitigate the risk to individual liberty, the independent
    agencies historically have been headed by multiple
    3
    commissioners or board members. In the Supreme Court’s
    words, each independent agency has traditionally been
    established as a “body of experts appointed by law and
    informed by experience.” Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 624
    . Multi-member independent agencies do not concentrate
    all power in one unaccountable individual, but instead divide
    and disperse power across multiple commissioners or board
    members. The multi-member structure thereby reduces the
    risk of arbitrary decisionmaking and abuse of power, and helps
    protect individual liberty.
    In other words, the heads of executive agencies are
    accountable to and checked by the President; and the heads of
    independent agencies, although not accountable to or checked
    by the President, are at least accountable to and checked by
    their fellow commissioners or board members.              No
    independent agency exercising substantial executive authority
    has ever been headed by a single person.
    Until now.
    In the Dodd-Frank Act of 2010, Congress created a new
    independent agency, the Consumer Financial Protection
    Bureau. As originally proposed by then-Professor and now-
    Senator Elizabeth Warren, the CFPB was to be another
    traditional, multi-member independent agency. The initial
    Executive Branch proposal from President Obama’s
    Administration likewise envisioned a multi-member
    independent agency. The House-passed bill sponsored by
    Congressman Barney Frank and championed by Speaker
    Nancy Pelosi also contemplated a multi-member independent
    agency.
    But Congress ultimately departed from the Warren and
    Executive Branch proposals, and from the House bill
    4
    sponsored by Congressman Frank. Congress established the
    CFPB as an independent agency headed not by a multi-member
    commission but rather by a single Director.
    The Director of the CFPB wields enormous power over
    American businesses, American consumers, and the overall
    U.S. economy. The Director unilaterally implements and
    enforces 19 federal consumer protection statutes, covering
    everything from home finance to student loans to credit cards
    to banking practices.
    The Director alone may decide what rules to issue. The
    Director alone may decide how to enforce, when to enforce,
    and against whom to enforce the law. The Director alone may
    decide whether an individual or entity has violated the law.
    The Director alone may decide what sanctions and penalties to
    impose on violators of the law.
    Because the CFPB is an independent agency headed by a
    single Director and not by a multi-member commission, the
    Director of the CFPB possesses more unilateral authority – that
    is, authority to take action on one’s own, subject to no check –
    than any single commissioner or board member in any other
    independent agency in the U.S. Government. Indeed, other
    than the President, the Director enjoys more unilateral
    authority than any other official in any of the three branches of
    the U.S. Government.
    That combination – power that is massive in scope,
    concentrated in a single person, and unaccountable to the
    President – triggers the important constitutional question at
    issue in this case.
    The petitioner here, PHH, is a mortgage lender and was the
    subject of a CFPB enforcement action that resulted in a $109
    5
    million sanction. In seeking to vacate the CFPB’s order, PHH
    argues that the CFPB’s novel structure – an independent
    agency headed by a single Director – violates Article II of the
    Constitution. I agree with PHH.
    Three considerations inform my Article II analysis:
    history, liberty, and Presidential authority.
    First, history. In separation of powers cases, the Supreme
    Court has repeatedly emphasized the significance of historical
    practice. See, e.g., NLRB v. Noel Canning, 
    134 S. Ct. 2550
    (2014); Free Enterprise Fund v. Public Company Accounting
    Oversight Board, 
    561 U.S. 477
     (2010). The single-Director
    structure of the CFPB represents a gross departure from settled
    historical practice. Never before has an independent agency
    exercising substantial executive authority been headed by just
    one person. That history matters. In Free Enterprise Fund,
    in invalidating the novel structure of another newly created
    independent agency, the Public Company Accounting
    Oversight Board, the Supreme Court stated: “Perhaps the
    most telling indication of the severe constitutional problem
    with the PCAOB is the lack of historical precedent for this
    entity.” 
    Id. at 505
    . Here too: Perhaps the most telling
    indication of the severe constitutional problem with the CFPB
    is the lack of historical precedent for this entity.
    Second, liberty. The CFPB’s concentration of enormous
    power in a single unaccountable, unchecked Director poses a
    far greater risk of arbitrary decisionmaking and abuse of power,
    and a far greater threat to individual liberty, than a multi-
    member independent agency does.                The overarching
    constitutional concern with independent agencies is that the
    agencies exercise executive power but are unchecked by the
    President, the official who is accountable to the people and who
    is responsible under Article II for the exercise of executive
    6
    power. In lieu of Presidential control, the multi-member
    structure of independent agencies operates as a critical
    substitute check on the excesses of any individual independent
    agency head. This new agency, the CFPB, lacks that critical
    check, yet still wields vast power over American businesses
    and consumers. This “wolf comes as a wolf.” Morrison, 
    487 U.S. at 699
     (Scalia, J., dissenting).
    Third, Presidential authority. The single-Director CFPB
    diminishes the President’s Article II authority to control the
    Executive Branch more than traditional multi-member
    independent agencies do. In comparable multi-member
    independent agencies such as the Federal Trade Commission
    (to which the CFPB repeatedly compares itself), the President
    ordinarily retains power to designate the chairs of the agencies
    and to remove chairs at will from the chair position. As a
    result, Presidents can maintain at least some influence over the
    general direction of the agencies. Soon after a new President
    enters office, the new President typically designates new
    chairs. Those independent agencies therefore flip to control
    by chairs who are aligned with the new President. For
    example, shortly after he took office on January 20, 2017,
    President Trump designated new Chairs of the Federal Trade
    Commission, the Federal Communications Commission, the
    Securities and Exchange Commission, and the National Labor
    Relations Board, among others. President Obama did the
    same within a few weeks of taking office in 2009.
    A President possesses far less influence over the single-
    Director CFPB. The single CFPB Director serves a fixed five-
    year term and, absent good cause, may not be replaced by the
    President, even by a newly elected President. The upshot is
    that a President may be stuck for years with a CFPB Director
    who was appointed by the prior President and who vehemently
    opposes the current President’s agenda. To illustrate, upon
    7
    taking office in January 2017, the President could not appoint
    a new Director of the CFPB, at least absent good cause for
    terminating the existing Director. It will get worse in the
    future. Any new President who is elected in 2020, 2024, or
    2028 may spend a majority of his or her term with a CFPB
    Director who was appointed by a prior President. That does
    not happen with the chairs of the traditional multi-member
    independent agencies.        That dramatic and meaningful
    difference vividly illustrates that the CFPB’s novel single-
    Director structure diminishes Presidential power more than
    traditional multi-member independent agencies do.
    In sum, because of the consistent historical practice in
    which independent agencies have been headed by multiple
    commissioners or board members; because of the serious threat
    to individual liberty posed by a single-Director independent
    agency; and because of the diminution of Presidential authority
    caused by this single-Director independent agency, I conclude
    that the CFPB violates Article II of the Constitution. Under
    Article II, an independent agency that exercises substantial
    executive power may not be headed by a single Director. As
    to remedy, I agree with the United States as amicus curiae:
    The Supreme Court’s Free Enterprise Fund decision and the
    Court’s other severability precedents require that we sever the
    CFPB’s for-cause provision, so that the Director of the CFPB
    is supervised, directed, and removable at will by the President.
    8
    I. HISTORY
    I begin by describing the history of independent agencies
    in general and of the CFPB in particular. That history
    demonstrates that, in order to comply with Article II,
    independent agencies exercising substantial executive power
    must be structured as multi-member agencies.
    A
    As the Supreme Court has explained, our Constitution
    “was adopted to enable the people to govern themselves,
    through their elected leaders,” and the Constitution “requires
    that a President chosen by the entire Nation oversee the
    execution of the laws.” Free Enterprise Fund v. Public
    Company Accounting Oversight Board, 
    561 U.S. 477
    , 499
    (2010). Article II of the Constitution provides quite simply:
    “The executive Power shall be vested in a President of the
    United States of America.” U.S. CONST. art. II, § 1. And
    Article II assigns the President alone the authority and
    responsibility to “take Care that the Laws be faithfully
    executed.” Id. § 3. Article II makes “emphatically clear
    from start to finish” that the President is “personally
    responsible for his branch.” AKHIL REED AMAR, AMERICA’S
    CONSTITUTION: A BIOGRAPHY 197 (2005).
    To exercise the executive power, the President must be
    assisted by subordinates. The Framers anticipated and
    provided for executive departments, and for officers (principal
    and inferior) in those departments who would assist the
    President. See U.S. CONST. art. II, § 2. In 1789, soon after
    being sworn in, the First Congress established new executive
    Departments of Foreign Affairs, War, and Treasury, and
    created various offices in those new Departments.
    9
    In order to control the exercise of executive power and take
    care that the laws are faithfully executed, the President must be
    able to supervise and direct those subordinate executive
    officers. As James Madison stated during the First Congress,
    “if any power whatsoever is in its nature Executive, it is the
    power of appointing, overseeing, and controlling those who
    execute the laws.” 1 ANNALS OF CONGRESS 463 (Madison)
    (1789) (Joseph Gales ed., 1834); see also Neomi Rao,
    Removal: Necessary and Sufficient for Presidential Control, 
    65 Ala. L. Rev. 1205
    , 1215 (2014) (“The text and structure of
    Article II provide the President with the power to control
    subordinates within the executive branch.”).
    To supervise and direct executive officers, the President
    must be able to remove those officers at will. Otherwise, a
    subordinate could ignore the President’s supervision and
    direction without fear, and the President could do nothing about
    it. See Bowsher v. Synar, 
    478 U.S. 714
    , 726 (1986) (“Once an
    officer is appointed, it is only the authority that can remove
    him, and not the authority that appointed him, that he must fear
    and, in the performance of his functions, obey.”).
    The Article II chain of command therefore depends on the
    President’s removal power. As James Madison explained
    during the First Congress: “If the President should possess
    alone the power of removal from office, those who are
    employed in the execution of the law will be in their proper
    situation, and the chain of dependence be preserved; the lowest
    officers, the middle grade, and the highest, will depend, as they
    ought, on the President, and the President on the community.”
    1 ANNALS OF CONGRESS 499 (Madison).
    In 1789, the First Congress confirmed that Presidents may
    remove executive officers at will. As the Supreme Court has
    explained: “The removal of executive officers was discussed
    10
    extensively in Congress when the first executive departments
    were created. The view that ‘prevailed, as most consonant to
    the text of the Constitution’ and ‘to the requisite responsibility
    and harmony in the Executive Department,’ was that the
    executive power included a power to oversee executive officers
    through removal.” Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 492
    (quoting Letter from James Madison to Thomas Jefferson (June
    30, 1789), 16 DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE FIRST FEDERAL
    CONGRESS 893 (2004)). That Decision of 1789 “soon became
    the settled and well understood construction of the
    Constitution.” Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 492
    .
    To summarize:        “The Constitution that makes the
    President accountable to the people for executing the laws also
    gives him the power to do so. That power includes, as a
    general matter, the authority to remove those who assist him in
    carrying out his duties. Without such power, the President
    could not be held fully accountable for discharging his own
    responsibilities; the buck would stop somewhere else.” 
    Id. at 513-14
    .
    But that bedrock constitutional principle was challenged in
    the late 1800s and the early 1900s. As part of the Progressive
    Movement and an emerging belief in expert, apolitical, and
    scientific answers to certain public policy questions, Congress
    began creating new agencies that were independent of the
    President but that exercised combined powers: the executive
    power of enforcement, the legislative power of issuing binding
    legal rules, and the judicial power of deciding adjudications
    and appeals. The heads of those independent agencies were
    removable by the President only for cause, not at will, and were
    neither supervised nor directed by the President. Some early
    examples included the Interstate Commerce Commission
    (1887) and the Federal Trade Commission (1914).
    Importantly, the independent agencies were multi-member
    11
    bodies: They were designed as non-partisan expert agencies
    that could neutrally and impartially issue rules, initiate law
    enforcement actions, and conduct or review administrative
    adjudications.
    The constitutionality of those independent agencies was
    called into doubt by the Supreme Court in the 1926 Myers
    decision written by Chief Justice and former President Taft.
    In that case, the Supreme Court ruled that, under Article II, the
    President must be able to supervise, direct, and remove at will
    executive officers. The Court stated: When “the grant of the
    executive power is enforced by the express mandate to take
    care that the laws be faithfully executed, it emphasizes the
    necessity for including within the executive power as conferred
    the exclusive power of removal.” Myers v. United States, 
    272 U.S. 52
    , 122 (1926).
    The Myers Court’s articulation of the President’s broad
    removal power appeared to mean that Congress could no
    longer create independent agencies. Indeed, Congress itself
    read Myers that way. For several years after Myers, Congress
    therefore did not create any new agencies whose heads were
    protected by for-cause removal provisions.
    In the 1930s, based on his reading of Article II and buoyed
    by Myers, President Franklin Roosevelt vigorously challenged
    the notion of independent agencies. President Roosevelt did
    not necessarily object to the existence of the agencies; rather,
    he objected to the President’s lack of control over the agencies.
    The issue came to a head in President Roosevelt’s dispute
    with William E. Humphrey, a commissioner of the Federal
    Trade Commission.        Commissioner Humphrey was a
    Republican holdover from the Hoover Administration who, in
    President Roosevelt’s view, was too sympathetic to big
    12
    business and too hostile to the Roosevelt Administration’s
    regulatory agenda. Asserting his authority under Article II,
    President Roosevelt fired Commissioner Humphrey.
    Humphrey contested the removal (and after Humphrey’s death,
    his representative continued the litigation in order to obtain
    back pay). Humphrey’s representative argued that Humphrey
    was protected against firing by the statute’s for-cause removal
    provision, and further argued that Congress could create
    independent agencies without violating Article II. The case
    reached the Supreme Court in 1935.
    At its core, the Humphrey’s Executor case raised the
    question whether Article II permitted independent agencies.
    Representing President Roosevelt, the Solicitor General
    contended that Congress could not create independent
    agencies. The Solicitor General relied on the text and history
    of Article II, as well as the Supreme Court’s 1926 decision in
    Myers. But notwithstanding Article II and Myers, the
    Supreme Court upheld the constitutionality of independent
    agencies – an unexpected decision that incensed President
    Roosevelt and helped trigger his ill-fated court reorganization
    proposal in 1937. See Humphrey’s Executor v. United States,
    
    295 U.S. 602
    , 631-32 (1935).
    In allowing independent agencies, the Humphrey’s
    Executor Court emphasized that the Federal Trade
    Commission was intended “to be non-partisan” and “to
    exercise the trained judgment of a body of experts appointed
    by law and informed by experience.” 
    Id. at 624
    . Those
    characteristics, among others, led the Court to conclude that
    Congress could create an independent agency “wholly
    disconnected from the executive department,” except in its
    selection. 
    Id. at 630, 625
    . According to the Court, Congress
    could limit the President’s power to remove the commissioners
    of the Federal Trade Commission and, by extension, Congress
    13
    could limit the President’s power to remove the commissioners
    and board members of similar independent agencies. 
    Id. at 628-30
    .
    Ever since the 1935 Humphrey’s Executor decision,
    independent agencies have played a significant role in the U.S.
    Government.        The independent agencies possess
    extraordinary authority over vast swaths of American
    economic and social life – from securities to antitrust to
    telecommunications to labor to energy. The list goes on.
    Importantly, however, each of the independent agencies
    has traditionally operated – and each continues to operate – as
    a multi-member “body of experts appointed by law and
    informed by experience.” 
    Id. at 624
    . Independent agencies
    are not headed by single Directors. As Professor Amar has
    explained, “the Decision of 1789” has remained controlling, at
    least to the extent that the Decision “established that in all one-
    headed departments, the department head must be removable
    at will by the president.” AKHIL REED AMAR, AMERICA’S
    UNWRITTEN CONSTITUTION 323 (2012).
    The independent agency at issue here, the CFPB, arose out
    of an idea originally advanced by then-Professor and now-
    Senator Elizabeth Warren.         In 2007, concerned about
    balkanized and inconsistent federal law enforcement of
    consumer protection statutes, Professor Warren encouraged
    Congress to create a new independent agency, a Financial
    Product Safety Commission.          This new agency would
    centralize and unify federal law enforcement efforts to protect
    consumers. See Elizabeth Warren, Unsafe at Any Rate: If It’s
    Good Enough for Microwaves, It’s Good Enough for
    Mortgages. Why We Need a Financial Product Safety
    Commission, Democracy, Summer 2007, at 8, 16-18.
    14
    The agency proposed by Professor Warren was to operate
    as a traditional multi-member independent agency. The
    subsequent Executive Branch proposal by President Obama’s
    Administration likewise contemplated a multi-member
    independent agency. See DEPARTMENT OF THE TREASURY,
    FINANCIAL REGULATORY REFORM: A NEW FOUNDATION:
    REBUILDING FINANCIAL SUPERVISION AND REGULATION 58
    (2009). The originally passed House bill sponsored by
    Congressman Barney Frank and supported by Speaker Nancy
    Pelosi similarly would have created a multi-member
    independent agency. See H.R. 4173, 111th Cong. § 4103 (as
    passed by House, Dec. 11, 2009).
    But Congress ultimately departed from the Warren and
    Executive Branch proposals, from the House bill, and from
    historical practice by creating an independent agency with only
    a single Director. See Dodd-Frank Wall Street Reform and
    Consumer Protection Act, Pub. L. No. 111-203, Title X § 1011,
    
    124 Stat. 1376
    , 1964 (codified at 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    ). The
    single Director of the CFPB is removable only for cause – that
    is, for “inefficiency, neglect of duty, or malfeasance in office”
    – during the Director’s fixed five-year term. See 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (c)(3); cf. Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 620
    .
    Congress’s choice of a single-Director CFPB was not an
    especially considered legislative decision. No committee
    report or substantial legislative history delved into the benefits
    of single-Director independent agencies versus multi-member
    independent agencies. No congressional hearings studied the
    question. Congress apparently stumbled into this single-
    Director structure as a compromise or landing point between
    the original Warren multi-member independent agency
    proposal and a traditional executive agency headed by a single
    person.
    15
    Under the law as enacted, the President may not supervise,
    direct, or remove at will the CFPB Director. As a result, a
    Director appointed by a President may continue to serve in
    office even if the President later wants to remove the Director
    based on a policy disagreement, for example.               More
    importantly, a Director may continue to serve as Director under
    a new President (until the Director’s statutory five-year tenure
    has elapsed), even though the new President might strongly
    disagree with that Director about policy issues or the overall
    direction of the agency.
    Congress insulated the CFPB’s Director from Presidential
    influence, yet also granted the CFPB extraordinarily broad
    authority to implement and enforce U.S. consumer protection
    laws.     Under the Dodd-Frank Act, the CFPB may
    “implement[] the Federal consumer financial laws through
    rules, orders, guidance, interpretations, statements of policy,
    examinations, and enforcement actions.”          
    12 U.S.C. § 5492
    (10). The CFPB may “prescribe rules or issue orders or
    guidelines pursuant to” 19 distinct consumer protection laws.
    
    Id.
     § 5581(a)(1)(A); see also id. §§ 5481(14), 5512(b). That
    rulemaking power was previously exercised by seven different
    government agencies. See id. § 5581(b) (transferring to the
    CFPB certain “consumer financial protection functions”
    previously exercised by the Federal Reserve, the Comptroller
    of the Currency, the Office of Thrift Supervision, the Federal
    Deposit Insurance Corporation, the National Credit Union
    Administration, the Department of Housing and Urban
    Development, and the Federal Trade Commission).
    The CFPB may pursue enforcement actions in federal
    court, as well as before administrative law judges. The agency
    may issue subpoenas requesting documents or testimony in
    connection with those enforcement actions. See id. §§ 5562-
    5564. The CFPB may adjudicate disputes. And the CFPB
    16
    may impose a wide range of legal and equitable relief,
    including restitution, disgorgement, money damages,
    injunctions, and civil monetary penalties. Id. § 5565(a)(2).
    All of that massive power is ultimately lodged in one
    person – the Director of the CFPB – who is not supervised,
    directed, or removable at will by the President.
    Because the Director acts alone and without Presidential
    supervision or direction, and because the CFPB wields broad
    authority over the U.S. economy, the Director enjoys
    significantly more unilateral power than any single member of
    any other independent agency. By “unilateral power,” I mean
    power that is not checked by the President or by other
    commissioners or board members. Indeed, other than the
    President, the Director of the CFPB is the single most powerful
    official in the entire U.S. Government, at least when measured
    in terms of unilateral power. That is not an overstatement.
    What about the Speaker of the House? The Speaker can pass
    legislation only if 218 Members agree. The Senate Majority
    Leader? The Leader typically needs 60 Senators to invoke
    cloture, and needs a majority of Senators (usually 51 Senators
    or 50 plus the Vice President) to approve a law or nomination.
    The Chief Justice? The Chief Justice must obtain four other
    Justices’ votes in order to prevail. The Chair of the Federal
    Reserve? The Chair often needs the approval of a majority of
    the Federal Reserve Board. The Secretary of Defense? The
    Secretary is supervised and directed and removable at will by
    the President. On any decision, the Secretary must do as the
    President says. So too with the Secretary of State, and the
    Secretary of the Treasury, and the Attorney General.
    To be sure, the Dodd-Frank Act requires the Director to
    establish and consult with a “Consumer Advisory Board.” See
    id. § 5494. But the advisory board is just that: advisory. The
    17
    Director need not heed the Board’s advice. Without the
    formal authority to block unilateral action by the Director, the
    Advisory Board does not come close to the kind of check
    provided by the multi-member structure of traditional
    independent agencies.
    The Act also, in theory, allows a supermajority of the
    Financial Stability Oversight Council to veto certain
    regulations of the Director. See id. §§ 5513, 5321. But by
    statute, the veto power may be used only to prevent regulations
    (not to overturn enforcement actions or adjudications); only
    when two-thirds of the Council members agree; and only when
    a particular regulation puts “the safety and soundness of the
    United States banking system or the stability of the financial
    system of the United States at risk,” a standard unlikely to be
    met in practice in most cases. Id. § 5513(c)(3)(B)(ii); see S.
    Rep. No. 111-176, at 166 (“The Committee notes that there was
    no evidence provided during its hearings that consumer
    protection regulation would put safety and soundness at risk.”);
    see also Todd Zywicki, The Consumer Financial Protection
    Bureau: Savior or Menace?, 
    81 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 856
    , 875
    (2013) (“[S]ubstantive checks on the CFPB can be
    triggered . . . only under the extreme circumstance of a severe
    threat to the safety and soundness of the American financial
    system. It is likely that this extreme test will rarely be satisfied
    in practice.”); Recent Legislation, Dodd-Frank Act Creates the
    Consumer Financial Protection Bureau, 
    124 Harv. L. Rev. 2123
    , 2129 (2011) (“[T]he high standard for vetoing
    regulations . . . will be difficult to establish.”). In this case, for
    example, the veto power could not have been used to override
    the CFPB’s statutory interpretation or its enforcement action
    against PHH.
    The Act also technically makes the CFPB part of the
    Federal Reserve for certain administrative purposes. See, e.g.,
    18
    
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (a); see also 
    id.
     § 5493. But that is irrelevant
    to the present analysis because the Federal Reserve Board may
    not supervise, direct, or remove the CFPB Director.
    In short, when measured in terms of unilateral power, the
    Director of the CFPB is the single most powerful official in the
    entire U.S. Government, other than the President. Indeed,
    within his jurisdiction, the Director of the CFPB is even more
    powerful than the President. The Director’s view of consumer
    protection law and policy prevails over all others. In essence,
    the Director of the CFPB is the President of Consumer Finance.
    The concentration of massive, unchecked power in a single
    Director marks a dramatic departure from settled historical
    practice and makes the CFPB unique among independent
    agencies, as I will now explain.
    B
    As a single-Director independent agency exercising
    substantial executive authority, the CFPB is the first of its kind
    and an historical anomaly. Until this point in U.S. history,
    independent agencies exercising substantial executive
    authority have all been multi-member commissions or boards.
    A sample list includes:
    •   Interstate Commerce Commission (1887)
    •   Federal Reserve Board (1913)
    •   Federal Trade Commission (1914)
    •   U.S. International Trade Commission (1916)
    •   Federal Deposit Insurance Corporation (1933)
    •   Federal Communications Commission (1934)
    •   National Mediation Board (1934)
    •   Securities and Exchange Commission (1934)
    •   National Labor Relations Board (1935)
    19
    •    Federal Maritime Commission (1961)
    •    National Transportation Safety Board (1967)
    •    National Credit Union Administration (1970)
    •    Occupational Safety and Health Review Commission
    (1970)
    •    Postal Regulatory Commission (1970)
    •    Consumer Product Safety Commission (1972)
    •    Nuclear Regulatory Commission (1974)
    •    Federal Energy Regulatory Commission (1977)
    •    Federal Mine Safety and Health Review Commission
    (1977)
    •    Federal Labor Relations Authority (1978)
    •    Merit Systems Protection Board (1978)
    •    Defense Nuclear Facilities Safety Board (1988)
    •    National Indian Gaming Commission (1988)
    •    Chemical Safety and Hazard Investigation Board
    (1990)
    •    Surface Transportation Board (1995)
    •    Independent Payment Advisory Board (2010). 1
    1
    In general, an agency without a for-cause removal statute is an
    executive agency, not an independent agency, because the President
    may supervise, direct, and remove at will the heads of those agencies.
    That said, in the period from Myers (1926) to Humphrey’s Executor
    (1935), Congress created several multi-member agencies that did not
    include for-cause provisions, apparently because Congress
    interpreted Myers to outlaw independent agencies. Those agencies
    included the FCC and the SEC. After Humphrey’s Executor, those
    multi-member agencies were treated as independent agencies even
    though the relevant statutes did not include for-cause provisions.
    Cf. Free Enterprise Fund v. Public Company Accounting Oversight
    Board, 
    561 U.S. 477
    , 487 (2010) (deciding case on assumption that
    SEC is an independent agency). Because those agencies’ statutes
    do not contain express for-cause provisions, some have suggested
    that those agencies actually are and should be treated as executive
    20
    Have there been any independent agencies headed by a
    single person? In an effort to be comprehensive, the three-
    judge panel in this case issued a pre-argument order asking the
    CFPB for all historical or current examples it could find of
    independent agencies headed by a single person. The CFPB
    found only three examples: the Social Security Administration,
    the Office of Special Counsel, and the Federal Housing Finance
    Agency. At the en banc stage, the CFPB cited no additional
    examples.
    None of the three examples, however, has deep historical
    roots. Indeed, the Federal Housing Finance Agency has
    existed only since 2008, about as long as the CFPB. The other
    two are likewise relatively recent. And those other two have
    been constitutionally contested by the Executive Branch, and
    they do not exercise the core Article II executive power of
    bringing law enforcement actions or imposing fines and
    penalties against private citizens for violation of statutes or
    agency rules.
    For those reasons, as I will explain, the three examples are
    different in kind from the CFPB. Those examples therefore
    do not count for much when compared to the deeply rooted
    historical practice of independent agencies as multi-member
    agencies. To borrow the words of Justice Breyer in Noel
    Canning, as weighed against the settled historical practice,
    “these few scattered examples” are “anomalies.” NLRB v.
    Noel Canning, 
    134 S. Ct. 2550
    , 2567, slip op. at 21 (2014); see
    agencies. See Kirti Datla & Richard L. Revesz, Deconstructing
    Independent Agencies (and Executive Agencies), 
    98 Cornell L. Rev. 769
    , 834-35 (2013); Note, The SEC Is Not an Independent Agency,
    
    126 Harv. L. Rev. 781
    , 801 (2013). I do not tackle that question in
    this opinion and do not imply an answer one way or the other about
    the executive or independent status of the multi-member agencies
    that lack express for-cause removal provisions.
    21
    also Free Enterprise Fund v. Public Company Accounting
    Oversight Board, 
    561 U.S. 477
    , 505-06 (2010).
    First, the CFPB cited and primarily relied on the example
    of the Social Security Administration, which is an independent
    agency headed by a single Social Security Commissioner. See
    
    42 U.S.C. §§ 901
    (a), 902(a). But the current structure of the
    agency is relatively recent.             The Social Security
    Administration long existed first as a multi-member
    independent agency and then as a single-Director executive
    agency within various executive departments, most recently the
    Department of Health and Human Services. Only in 1994 did
    Congress change the Social Security Administration to a
    single-Director independent agency. Importantly, when the
    agency’s structure was altered in 1994, President Clinton
    issued a signing statement pronouncing that the change in the
    agency’s structure was constitutionally problematic. See
    President William J. Clinton, Statement on Signing the Social
    Security Independence and Program Improvements Act of
    1994, 2 Pub. Papers 1471, 1472 (Aug. 15, 1994). That
    agency’s structure therefore is constitutionally contested. In
    those circumstances, the historical precedent counts for little
    because it is not settled. Cf. Noel Canning, 134 S. Ct. at 2563-
    64, 2567, slip op. at 14-15, 20-21 (discounting example of
    appointments during particular inter-session recess because of
    Senate Committee’s strong opposition to those appointments);
    INS v. Chadha, 
    462 U.S. 919
    , 942 n.13 (1983) (discounting
    prior legislative veto provisions because Presidents had
    objected to those provisions). If anything, when considered
    against the “settled practice,” the Social Security example only
    highlights the anomaly of an independent agency headed by a
    single person. Noel Canning, 
    134 S. Ct. at 2567
    , slip op. at
    21.
    22
    Moreover, the Social Security Administration is not a
    precedent for the CFPB because the Social Security
    Commissioner does not possess unilateral authority to bring
    law enforcement actions against private citizens, which is the
    core of the executive power and the primary threat to individual
    liberty posed by executive power. See Morrison v. Olson, 
    487 U.S. 654
    , 706 (1988) (Scalia, J., dissenting). The Social
    Security Administration does not have power to impose fines
    or penalties on private citizens in Social Security benefits
    cases.      Instead, the bulk of the Social Security
    Administration’s authority involves adjudication of private
    claims for benefits. Although the agency does possess limited
    power to seek civil sanctions against those who file improper
    claims, the Commissioner may initiate such a proceeding “only
    as authorized by the Attorney General,” who is an executive
    officer accountable to the President. 42 U.S.C. § 1320a-8(b).
    Second, the CFPB cited the example of the Office of
    Special Counsel, an independent agency headed by a single
    Special Counsel. The Office has a narrow jurisdiction and
    mainly enforces certain personnel rules against government
    employers and employees, such as the prohibition against
    improper political activity by government employees. Like
    the Social Security Administration, the Office of Special
    Counsel lacks deep historical roots. It became a single-
    Director agency in 1978. And like the Social Security
    Administration, the constitutionality of the Special Counsel has
    been contested since its creation. Under President Carter, the
    Department of Justice opined that the Special Counsel “must
    be removable at will by the President,” and the Department
    opposed a for-cause restriction on removal of the Special
    Counsel. Memorandum Opinion for the General Counsel,
    Civil Service Commission, 
    2 Op. O.L.C. 120
    , 120 (1978).
    When Congress passed subsequent legislation regarding the
    Office of Special Counsel, President Reagan vetoed the bill due
    23
    to “serious constitutional concerns” about the Office’s status as
    an independent agency.            President Ronald Reagan,
    Memorandum of Disapproval on a Bill Concerning
    Whistleblower Protection, 2 Pub. Papers 1391, 1392 (Oct. 26,
    1988). The history of the Office of Special Counsel confirms
    what one former Special Counsel has acknowledged: The
    agency is “a controversial anomaly in the federal system.” K.
    William O’Connor, Foreword to A LEGISLATIVE HISTORY OF
    THE MERIT SYSTEM PRINCIPLES, PROHIBITED PERSONNEL
    PRACTICES AND THE OFFICE OF THE SPECIAL COUNSEL, at v
    (1985). That agency’s structure remains constitutionally
    contested and so is not a meaningful historical precedent for
    the CFPB.
    Moreover, the Office of Special Counsel is not a precedent
    for the CFPB because the Office of Special Counsel is
    primarily responsible for enforcing personnel laws against
    government agencies and government employees. Unlike the
    CFPB, the Office of Special Counsel may not enforce laws
    against private citizens or impose fines and penalties on private
    citizens. 2
    2
    Because the Social Security Administration and the Office of
    Special Counsel do not exercise the core executive power of bringing
    law enforcement actions and because they have narrow jurisdiction,
    a holding invalidating the single-Director structure of the CFPB
    would not necessarily invalidate the single-Director structure of the
    Social Security Administration and the Office of Special Counsel.
    That said, if those two agencies are unconstitutionally structured, the
    remedy would presumably be the same remedy as in Free Enterprise
    Fund: severing the for-cause provision so that the agencies would
    continue to fully operate, albeit as traditional executive agencies
    rather than independent agencies. I do not address those agencies in
    this case.
    24
    Third, the CFPB pointed to Congress’s 2008 creation of a
    single-Director Federal Housing Finance Agency.                See
    Housing and Economic Recovery Act of 2008, Pub. L. No.
    110-289, § 1101, 
    122 Stat. 2654
    , 2662 (codified at 
    12 U.S.C. §§ 4511-4512
    ). That agency is a contemporary of the CFPB
    and merely raises the same question we confront here. An
    agency created only in 2008 does not constitute an historical
    precedent for the CFPB. Cf. NLRB v. SW General, Inc., 
    137 S. Ct. 929
    , 943, slip op. at 17 (2017) (“‘[H]istorical practice’ is
    too grand a title for the Board’s evidence. The FVRA was not
    enacted until 1998 . . . .”).
    Fourth, although not a regulatory agency precedent and not
    an example cited by the CFPB as precedent for its single-
    Director structure (for good reason), there is at least one other
    modern statute that created an independent entity headed by
    one person. It is the now-defunct independent counsel law.
    But the independent counsel was distinct in numerous
    meaningful ways from the CFPB Director. Unlike the CFPB
    Director, the independent counsel exercised only executive
    power, not rulemaking or adjudicative power. Unlike the
    CFPB Director, the independent counsel had only a limited
    jurisdiction for particular defined criminal investigations
    where the Department of Justice had a conflict of interest.
    Most importantly, unlike the CFPB Director, the independent
    counsel was an inferior officer, not a principal officer. The
    independent counsel was an inferior officer, according to the
    Supreme Court, because the independent counsel could be
    supervised and directed to some extent by the Attorney
    General, who is a principal executive officer accountable to the
    President.
    Given those important distinctions, the independent
    counsel is not an historical precedent for a single principal
    officer as the head of an independent regulatory agency. That
    25
    is no doubt why the CFPB has not relied on the independent
    counsel as an historical precedent for a single-Director CFPB.3
    So in terms of historical practice, that’s all the CFPB has,
    and that’s not much. As Justice Breyer stated for the Supreme
    Court when the Court faced a similar (actually, a more robust)
    historical record in Noel Canning, the few examples offered by
    the CFPB are “anomalies.” 134 S. Ct. at 2567, slip op. at 21.
    Or as the Supreme Court put it in Free Enterprise Fund when
    confronting a similar historical record, a “handful of isolated”
    examples does not count for much when assessed against an
    otherwise settled historical practice. 
    561 U.S. at 505
    .
    3
    Recall, moreover, that the independent counsel experiment
    ended with nearly universal consensus that the experiment had been
    a mistake and that Justice Scalia had been right back in 1988 to view
    the independent counsel system as an unwise and unconstitutional
    departure from historical practice and a serious threat to individual
    liberty. See Morrison v. Olson, 
    487 U.S. 654
    , 699 (1988) (Scalia,
    J., dissenting) (“this wolf comes as a wolf”); see also Stanford
    Lawyer 4 (Spring 2015) (quoting Justice Kagan’s statement that
    Justice Scalia’s dissent in Morrison is “one of the greatest dissents
    ever written and every year it gets better”). The independent
    counsel experience strongly counsels against single-Director
    independent agencies. The independent counsel is, of course,
    distinct from the traditional special counsels who are appointed by
    the Attorney General for particular matters. Those special counsels
    ordinarily report to and are removable by the Attorney General or the
    Deputy Attorney General.
    In this section of the opinion, I am addressing the historical
    practice of how independent agencies are structured. A separate
    question is whether Morrison v. Olson constitutes a judicial
    precedent on the question of whether a single-Director independent
    regulatory agency is constitutional. The answer to that question is
    also no, for similar reasons. I will address the Morrison point more
    fully in Part IV below.
    26
    To be sure, in “all the laws enacted since 1789, it is always
    possible that Congress” created some other independent
    agencies that exercised traditional executive functions but were
    headed by single Directors. Free Enterprise Fund v. Public
    Company Accounting Oversight Board, 
    537 F.3d 667
    , 699 n.8
    (D.C. Cir. 2008) (Kavanaugh, J., dissenting); see also Noel
    Canning, 
    134 S. Ct. at 2567
    , slip op. at 21 (“There may be
    others of which we are unaware.”). But “the research of the
    parties and the Court has not found such a needle in the
    haystack.” Free Enterprise Fund, 
    537 F.3d at
    699 n.8
    (Kavanaugh, J., dissenting). “Even if such an example were
    uncovered,” there is no question that a single-Director
    independent agency “has been rare at best.” 
    Id.
     4
    In considering precedents for the single-Director structure
    of the CFPB, one may wonder about all of the executive
    4
    Some have suggested that the CFPB Director is similar to the
    Comptroller of the Currency. But unlike the Director, the
    Comptroller is not independent. The Comptroller is removable at
    will by the President. Full stop. See 
    12 U.S.C. § 2
     (“The
    Comptroller of the Currency shall be appointed by the President, by
    and with the advice and consent of the Senate, and shall hold his
    office for a term of five years unless sooner removed by the
    President, upon reasons to be communicated by him to the Senate.”).
    A predecessor Comptroller of the Treasury, established in 1789,
    likewise was not independent. In Free Enterprise Fund, the
    Supreme Court definitively explained that the original Comptroller
    of the Treasury was removable at will by the President. See 
    561 U.S. at
    500 n.6. The Free Enterprise Fund opinion also addressed
    the alleged attribution to Madison of “a belief that some executive
    officers, such as the Comptroller, could be made independent of the
    President.” 
    Id.
     The Free Enterprise Fund Court explained that
    “Madison’s actual proposal, consistent with his view of the
    Constitution, was that the Comptroller hold office for a term of
    ‘years, unless sooner removed by the President . . . .’” 
    Id.
     (quoting
    1 ANNALS OF CONGRESS 612 (1789)) (emphasis added).
    27
    departments and agencies headed by a single person. Why
    don’t they provide a precedent for the CFPB? Consider for
    example the Department of Justice, the Department of the
    Treasury, the Department of State, the Department of Defense,
    and the EPA, all headed by a single person.
    The distinction, of course, is that those departments and
    agencies are executive agencies. They operate within the
    Executive Branch chain of command under the supervision and
    direction of the President, and those agency heads are
    removable at will by the President. The President therefore is
    a check on those agencies. Those agencies are accountable to
    the President. The President in turn is accountable to the
    people of the United States for the exercise of executive power
    in the executive agencies. So a single person at the helm of an
    executive agency is perfectly constitutional. 5
    By contrast, independent agencies operate free of the
    President’s supervision and direction.      Therefore, they
    traditionally have been headed by multiple commissioners or
    board members who check one another. An independent
    agency operates as “a body of experts appointed by law and
    informed by experience.” Humphrey’s Executor v. United
    States, 
    295 U.S. 602
    , 624 (1935).
    That deeply rooted tradition – namely, that independent
    agencies are headed by multiple commissioners or board
    members – has been widely recognized by leading judges,
    congressional committees, and academics who have studied the
    issue. Consider the following:
    5
    Congress may of course establish executive agencies that are
    headed by multiple individuals (although Congress rarely does so),
    but each agency head must be removable at will by the President in
    order for the agency to maintain its status as an executive agency.
    28
    •   Justice Breyer, joined by Justices Stevens, Ginsburg,
    and Sotomayor: “Agency independence is a function
    of several different factors . . . includ[ing] . . .
    composition as a multimember bipartisan board . . . .”
    Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 547
     (Breyer, J.,
    dissenting).
    •   A Senate study:          “The traditional independent
    regulatory agency is a commission of multiple
    members . . . . The size of the commission, the length
    of the terms, and the fact that they do not all lapse at
    one time are key elements of the independent
    structure.”     Senate Committee on Governmental
    Affairs, STUDY ON FEDERAL REGULATION, S. Doc. No.
    95-91, vol. 5, at 35 (1977).
    •   The same Senate study: The “relative importance to
    be attached to group decision-making” is the “[c]hief”
    factor legislators consider when deciding whether to
    create an independent rather than an executive agency.
    Id. at 79.
    •   Professors Breger and Edles: The multi-member
    agency form has become “synonymous with
    independence.” Marshall J. Breger & Gary J. Edles,
    Established by Practice: The Theory and Operation of
    Independent Federal Agencies, 
    52 Admin. L. Rev. 1111
    , 1137 (2000).
    •   Professor Amar: “Viewed through the prism of
    practice, the Constitution allows independent agencies
    to be created when three factors converge: first, when
    an executive entity is best headed up by a committee
    rather than by a single officer . . . .” AKHIL REED
    AMAR, AMERICA’S UNWRITTEN CONSTITUTION 385
    (2012).
    •   Professor Barkow: “multimember design” is one of
    the “[t]raditional [l]odestars” of agency independence.
    29
    Rachel E. Barkow, Insulating Agencies: Avoiding
    Capture Through Institutional Design, 
    89 Tex. L. Rev. 15
    , 26 (2010).
    •   Professor Davis: Independent agencies should be
    headed by multiple members “just as we want appellate
    courts to be made up of plural members, to protect
    against the idiosyncracies of a single individual.”
    KENNETH CULP DAVIS, ADMINISTRATIVE LAW OF THE
    SEVENTIES 15 (1976).
    •   Professor Strauss:           Independent      regulatory
    commissions are “governmental agencies headed by
    multi-member boards acting collegially on the
    regulatory matters within their jurisdiction.” PETER L.
    STRAUSS, AN INTRODUCTION TO ADMINISTRATIVE
    JUSTICE IN THE UNITED STATES 15 (1989).
    •   Professors Bressman and Thompson: Independent
    agencies, unlike Executive Branch agencies, are
    “generally run by multi-member commissions or
    boards.”     Lisa Schultz Bressman & Robert B.
    Thompson, The Future of Agency Independence, 
    63 Vand. L. Rev. 599
    , 610 (2010).
    •   A Harvard Law Review analysis: “Most independent
    agencies have multimember boards.”               Recent
    Legislation, Dodd-Frank Act Creates the Consumer
    Financial Protection Bureau, 
    124 Harv. L. Rev. 2123
    ,
    2128 (2011).
    The bottom line is that independent agencies historically
    have been headed by multiple commissioners or board
    members. The CFPB’s single-Director structure flouts that
    historical practice. See Who’s Watching the Watchmen?
    Oversight of the Consumer Financial Protection Bureau:
    Hearing Before the Subcommittee on TARP, Financial
    Services and Bailouts of Public and Private Programs of the
    House Committee on Oversight and Government Reform,
    30
    112th Cong. 77 (2011) (statement of Andrew Pincus)
    (emphasis added) (“Dodd-Frank sets up for the Bureau an
    unprecedented structure that consolidates more power in the
    director than in the head of any other agency that regulates
    private individuals and entities.”); Dodd-Frank Act Creates the
    Consumer Financial Protection Bureau, 124 Harv. L. Rev. at
    2130 (emphasis added) (“[T]he CFPB’s design is troubling
    because of its unprecedented nature.”); Note, Independence,
    Congressional Weakness, and the Importance of Appointment:
    The Impact of Combining Budgetary Autonomy with Removal
    Protection, 
    125 Harv. L. Rev. 1822
    , 1824 n.15 (2012)
    (emphasis added) (CFPB’s lack of a multi-member board is
    “atypical for independent agencies and will amplify the
    Director’s independence”); Todd Zywicki, The Consumer
    Financial Protection Bureau: Savior or Menace? 
    81 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 856
    , 899 (2013) (emphasis added) (“[T]he
    agency structure Congress chose for the CFPB – a single-
    director structure, devoid of accountability, and with vast, ill-
    defined powers – appears to be unique in recent American
    history.”). 6
    In short, the CFPB is exceptional in our constitutional
    structure and unprecedented in our constitutional history.
    6
    The settled historical practice is further illustrated by the
    quorum provisions applicable to independent agencies. Those
    quorum provisions reinforce the accepted understanding that
    independent agencies must have multiple commissioners or board
    members. Cf. New Process Steel, L.P. v. NLRB, 
    560 U.S. 674
    (2010); Marshall J. Breger & Gary J. Edles, Established by Practice:
    The Theory and Operation of Independent Federal Agencies, 
    52 Admin. L. Rev. 1111
    , 1182-83 & app. (2000) (summarizing
    independent agency quorum requirements).
    31
    C
    The CFPB’s departure from historical practice matters in
    this case because historical practice matters to separation of
    powers analysis. A long line of Supreme Court precedent
    commands that we heed history and tradition in separation of
    powers cases not resolved by the constitutional text alone. 7
    As Justice Breyer wrote for the Supreme Court in Noel
    Canning, the “longstanding practice of the government can
    inform our determination of what the law is.” NLRB v. Noel
    Canning, 
    134 S. Ct. 2550
    , 2560, slip op. at 7 (2014). Justice
    Breyer quoted James Madison’s statement that it was “foreseen
    at the birth of the Constitution, that difficulties and differences
    of opinion might occasionally arise in expounding terms &
    phrases necessarily used in such a charter . . . and that it might
    require a regular course of practice to liquidate & settle the
    meaning of some of them.” 
    Id.,
     slip op. at 8. Justice Breyer
    explained, moreover, that the Court “has treated practice as an
    important interpretive factor even when the nature or longevity
    of that practice is subject to dispute, and even when that
    practice began after the founding era.” 
    Id.,
     slip op. at 8.
    All of this, Justice Breyer stated, is “neither new nor
    controversial.” 
    Id.,
     slip op. at 7. Consider the following:
    •   “In separation-of-powers cases this Court has often put
    significant weight upon historical practice.”
    7
    As a matter of first principles, there would be a strong
    argument that this case could and should be resolved in PHH’s favor
    by the constitutional text alone – on the ground that independent
    agencies violate Article II. But Humphrey’s Executor rejected that
    broad argument, and we as a lower court are bound by that case.
    The question for us is whether Humphrey’s Executor extends to
    single-Director independent agencies.
    32
    Zivotofsky v. Kerry, 
    135 S. Ct. 2076
    , 2091, slip op. at
    20 (2015).
    •   “We therefore conclude, in light of historical practice,
    that a recess of more than 3 days but less than 10 days
    is presumptively too short to fall within the Clause.”
    Noel Canning, 
    134 S. Ct. at 2567
    , slip op. at 21.
    •   “Perhaps the most telling indication of the severe
    constitutional problem with the PCAOB is the lack of
    historical precedent for this entity.” Free Enterprise
    Fund v. Public Company Accounting Oversight Board,
    
    561 U.S. 477
    , 505 (2010).
    •   This “Court has long made clear that, when we face
    difficult questions of the Constitution’s structural
    requirements, longstanding customs and practices can
    make a difference.” Commonwealth of Puerto Rico v.
    Sanchez Valle, 
    136 S. Ct. 1863
    , 1884, slip op. at 13
    (2016) (Breyer, J., dissenting).
    •   “[T]raditional ways of conducting government . . . give
    meaning to the Constitution.” Mistretta v. United
    States, 
    488 U.S. 361
    , 401 (1989).
    •   “Deeply embedded traditional ways of conducting
    government cannot supplant the Constitution or
    legislation, but they give meaning to the words of a text
    or supply them.” Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v.
    Sawyer, 
    343 U.S. 579
    , 610 (1952) (Frankfurter, J.,
    concurring).
    •   “A legislative practice such as we have here, evidenced
    not by only occasional instances, but marked by the
    movement of a steady stream for a century and a half of
    time, goes a long way in the direction of proving the
    presence      of    unassailable   ground     for     the
    constitutionality of the practice, to be found in the
    origin and history of the power involved, or in its
    nature, or in both combined.” United States v. Curtiss-
    Wright Export Corp., 
    299 U.S. 304
    , 327-28 (1936).
    33
    •   “Long settled and established practice is a
    consideration of great weight in a proper interpretation
    of constitutional provisions of this character.” The
    Pocket Veto Case, 
    279 U.S. 655
    , 689 (1929).
    •   “Such long practice under the pardoning power and
    acquiescence in it strongly sustains the construction it
    is based on.” Ex parte Grossman, 
    267 U.S. 87
    , 118-19
    (1925).
    •   A “page of history is worth a volume of logic.” New
    York Trust Co. v. Eisner, 
    256 U.S. 345
    , 349 (1921).
    •   In “determining the meaning of a statute or the
    existence of a power, weight shall be given to the usage
    itself – even when the validity of the practice is the
    subject of investigation.” United States v. Midwest Oil
    Co., 
    236 U.S. 459
    , 473 (1915).
    •   “[W]here there is ambiguity or doubt [in the words of
    the Constitution], or where two views may well be
    entertained, contemporaneous and subsequent practical
    construction are entitled to the greatest weight.”
    McPherson v. Blacker, 
    146 U.S. 1
    , 27 (1892).
    •   A “doubtful question, one on which human reason may
    pause, and the human judgment be suspended, in the
    decision of which the great principles of liberty are not
    concerned, but the respective powers of those who are
    equally the representatives of the people, are to be
    adjusted; if not put at rest by the practice of the
    government, ought to receive a considerable impression
    from that practice.” McCulloch v. Maryland, 
    17 U.S. 316
    , 401 (1819).
    Stated simply, in separation of powers cases not resolved
    by the constitutional text alone, historical practice helps define
    the constitutional limits on the Legislative and Executive
    34
    Branches.8 The Supreme Court’s recent decisions in Free
    Enterprise Fund and Noel Canning illustrate how the Court
    relies on historical practice in the separation of powers
    context. 9
    In Free Enterprise Fund, the Supreme Court considered
    the constitutionality of the new Public Company Accounting
    Oversight Board created by the 2002 Sarbanes-Oxley Act.
    8
    The Supreme Court has relied heavily on historical practice
    not just in separation of powers cases, but also in federalism cases.
    In several federalism cases over the last 25 years, the Court has
    invalidated novel congressional statutes that altered the traditional
    federal-state balance. See New York v. United States, 
    505 U.S. 144
    ,
    177 (1992) (“The take title provision appears to be unique. No other
    federal statute has been cited which offers a state government no
    option other than that of implementing legislation enacted by
    Congress.”); Printz v. United States, 
    521 U.S. 898
    , 905 (1997) (“[I]f,
    as petitioners contend, earlier Congresses avoided use of this highly
    attractive power, we would have reason to believe that the power was
    thought not to exist.”); Alden v. Maine, 
    527 U.S. 706
    , 744 (1999)
    (“The provisions of the FLSA at issue here, which were enacted in
    the aftermath of Parden, are among the first statutory enactments
    purporting in express terms to subject nonconsenting States to
    private suits.”); cf. National Federation of Independent Business v.
    Sebelius, 
    567 U.S. 519
    , 549 (2012) (binding opinion of Roberts, C.J.)
    (“But Congress has never attempted to rely on that power to compel
    individuals not engaged in commerce to purchase an unwanted
    product.”); 
    id. at 659
     (joint dissent of Scalia, Kennedy, Thomas, and
    Alito, JJ.) (“[T]he relevant history is not that Congress has achieved
    wide and wonderful results through the proper exercise of its
    assigned powers in the past, but that it has never before used the
    Commerce Clause to compel entry into commerce.”).
    9
    Of course, if the constitutional text is sufficiently clear, then
    the existence of any historical practice departing from that text is not
    persuasive. See, e.g., INS v. Chadha, 
    462 U.S. 919
    , 944-46 (1983);
    Powell v. McCormack, 
    395 U.S. 486
    , 546-47 (1969).
    35
    Independent agency heads are ordinarily removable for cause
    by the President. But the new Public Company Accounting
    Oversight Board’s members were removable only for cause by
    the SEC Commissioners, and the SEC Commissioners in turn
    were understood to be removable only for cause by the
    President. In other words, there were two levels of for-cause
    removal between the President and the Accounting Oversight
    Board.
    The Supreme Court drew a line between one level of for-
    cause removal, which was the structure of traditional
    independent agencies, and two levels of for-cause removal, the
    novel structure of the new Accounting Oversight Board. The
    Court ruled that the latter was unconstitutional. The Court
    drew that line in part because historical practice had settled on
    allowing only one level of for-cause removal between the
    President and independent agency heads. There were at most
    “only a handful of isolated” precedents for the new Board.
    Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 505
    . That mattered,
    according to the Court: “Perhaps the most telling indication
    of the severe constitutional problem with the PCAOB is the
    lack of historical precedent for this entity.” 
    Id.
     And as the
    Court noted, there was a difference between one level of for-
    cause removal and two levels of for-cause removal in terms of
    an agency’s insulation from Presidential influence. See 
    id. at 495-96
    . Therefore, the Court invalidated the structure of the
    new Board. 10
    10
    Justice Breyer dissented for four Justices in Free Enterprise
    Fund. But importantly, he dissented not because he disagreed with
    the Court’s point that historical practice matters, but rather primarily
    because he did not see a meaningful difference – in practical,
    analytical, or constitutional terms – between one level and two levels
    of for-cause removal. See Free Enterprise Fund v. Public Company
    Accounting Oversight Board, 
    561 U.S. 477
    , 525-26 (2010) (Breyer,
    J., dissenting).
    36
    In Noel Canning, the Supreme Court, speaking through
    Justice Breyer, likewise stressed the importance of history
    when assessing the constitutionality of a novel practice – in that
    case, Presidential recess appointments in Senate recesses of
    fewer than 10 days. The Court said: “Long settled and
    established practice is a consideration of great weight in a
    proper interpretation of constitutional provisions regulating the
    relationship between Congress and the President.” Noel
    Canning, 
    134 S. Ct. at 2559
    , slip op. at 7. Based on that
    history, the Supreme Court ruled that a Senate recess of “less
    than 10 days is presumptively too short” for constitutional
    purposes. 
    Id. at 2567
    , slip op. at 21.
    Why 10 days? After all, the text of the Constitution does
    not draw any such 10-day line. The Court reasoned that the
    historical practice between the President and the Senate had
    established a 10-day line.
    Specifically, the Noel Canning Court stated that it had “not
    found a single example of a recess appointment made during
    an intra-session recess that was shorter than 10 days.” 
    Id. at 2566
    , slip op. at 20. Although the Court did find “a few
    historical examples of recess appointments made during inter-
    session recesses shorter than 10 days,” the Court stated: “But
    when considered against 200 years of settled practice, we
    regard these few scattered examples as anomalies.” 
    Id. at 2567
    , slip op. at 20-21.
    According to the Court, therefore, allowing recess
    appointments in Senate recesses of fewer than 10 days would
    depart from the settled historical practice and alter the relative
    powers of the President and Senate over appointments. So,
    too, disallowing recess appointments in Senate recesses of 10
    or more days would depart from settled historical practice. In
    37
    Noel Canning, the Supreme Court relied on that historical
    practice in defining the constitutional rule. 11
    The history-based analysis of Free Enterprise Fund and
    Noel Canning underscores the broader jurisprudential principle
    long applied by the Supreme Court: In separation of powers
    cases not resolved by the constitutional text alone, historical
    practice matters.
    ***
    The CFPB’s single-Director structure is without
    meaningful historical precedent. Here, as in Free Enterprise
    Fund and prior cases, the lack of historical precedent matters.
    To borrow the words of the Supreme Court in Free Enterprise
    Fund: “Perhaps the most telling indication of the severe
    constitutional problem” with the CFPB “is the lack of historical
    precedent for this entity.” 
    561 U.S. at 505
    .
    11
    Justice Scalia concurred in the judgment for four Justices in
    Noel Canning, arguing as relevant here that the text of the
    Constitution rendered intra-session recess appointments
    unconstitutional even in Senate recesses of 10 or more days. But
    Justice Scalia did not disagree with the Court’s claim that historical
    practice often matters in separation of powers cases involving
    ambiguous constitutional text, which is the relevant point for our
    purposes. See NLRB v. Noel Canning, 
    134 S. Ct. 2550
    , 2594, slip
    op. at 5 (2014) (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment) (“Of course,
    where a governmental practice has been open, widespread, and
    unchallenged since the early days of the Republic, the practice
    should guide our interpretation of an ambiguous constitutional
    provision.”). Rather, Justice Scalia stated that the constitutional text
    in that case was sufficiently clear and dispositive that resort to
    historical practice was unnecessary and unwarranted. See 
    id. at 2592
    , slip op. at 2; see generally John F. Manning, Separation of
    Powers as Ordinary Interpretation, 
    124 Harv. L. Rev. 1939
     (2011).
    38
    II. LIBERTY
    The CFPB’s single-Director structure not only departs
    from historical practice. It also threatens individual liberty
    more than the traditional multi-member structure does.
    A
    The historical practice of structuring independent agencies
    as multi-member commissions or boards is the historical
    practice for a reason: It reflects a deep and abiding concern
    for safeguarding the individual liberty protected by the
    Constitution.
    “The Framers recognized that, in the long term, structural
    protections against abuse of power were critical to preserving
    liberty.” Bowsher v. Synar, 
    478 U.S. 714
    , 730 (1986). The
    “structural principles secured by the separation of powers
    protect the individual as well.” Stern v. Marshall, 
    564 U.S. 462
    , 483 (2011). As Justice Scalia stated: “The purpose of
    the separation and equilibration of powers in general, and of
    the unitary Executive in particular, was not merely to assure
    effective government but to preserve individual freedom.”
    Morrison v. Olson, 
    487 U.S. 654
    , 727 (1988) (Scalia, J.,
    dissenting).
    The basic constitutional concern with independent
    agencies is that the agencies are unchecked by the President,
    the official who is accountable to the people and responsible
    under Article II for the exercise of executive power.
    Recognizing the broad and unaccountable power wielded by
    independent agencies, Congress has traditionally required
    multi-member bodies at the helm of independent agencies. In
    the absence of Presidential control, the multi-member structure
    39
    of independent agencies serves as a critical substitute check on
    the excesses of any individual independent agency head.
    But in this new agency, the CFPB, that critical check is
    absent. And the lack of that traditional safeguard threatens the
    individual liberty protected by the Constitution’s separation of
    powers.
    How does a single-Director independent agency fare
    worse than multi-member independent agencies in protecting
    individual liberty? A single-Director independent agency
    concentrates enforcement, rulemaking, and adjudicative power
    in one individual. By contrast, multi-member independent
    agencies do not concentrate all of that power in one individual.
    The multi-member structure thereby helps to prevent arbitrary
    decisionmaking and abuse of power, and to protect individual
    liberty.
    The point is simple but profound. In a multi-member
    independent agency, no single commissioner or board member
    can affirmatively do much of anything. Before the agency can
    infringe your liberty in some way – for example, by enforcing
    a law against you or by issuing a rule that affects your liberty
    or property – a majority of commissioners must agree. As a
    former Chair of the Federal Trade Commission has explained,
    it takes “a consensus decision of at least a majority of
    commissioners to authorize, or forbear from, action.” Edith
    Ramirez, The FTC: A Framework for Promoting Competition
    and Protecting Consumers, 
    83 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 2049
    , 2053
    (2015). That in turn makes it harder for the agency to infringe
    your liberty.
    In addition, unlike single-Director independent agencies,
    multi-member independent agencies “can foster more
    deliberative decision making.” Kirti Datla & Richard L.
    40
    Revesz, Deconstructing Independent Agencies (and Executive
    Agencies), 
    98 Cornell L. Rev. 769
    , 794 (2013). Multi-
    member independent agencies benefit from diverse
    perspectives and different points of view among the
    commissioners and board members. 12 The multiple voices
    and perspectives make it more likely that the costs and
    downsides of proposed decisions will be more fully ventilated.
    See Marshall J. Breger & Gary J. Edles, Established by
    Practice: The Theory and Operation of Independent Federal
    Agencies, 
    52 Admin. L. Rev. 1111
    , 1113 (2000) (independent
    agencies “are also multi-member organizations, a fact that
    tends toward accommodation of diverse or extreme views
    through the compromise inherent in the process of collegial
    decisionmaking”); Jacob E. Gersen, Administrative Law Goes
    to Wall Street: The New Administrative Process, 
    65 Admin. L. Rev. 689
    , 696 (2013) (A “multimember board allows for a
    representation of divergent interests in a way that a single
    decisionmaker simply cannot.”); Glen O. Robinson, On
    Reorganizing the Independent Regulatory Agencies, 
    57 Va. L. Rev. 947
    , 963 (1971) (“It is not bipartisanship as such that is
    important; it is rather the safeguards and balanced viewpoint
    that can be provided by plural membership.”); cf. Harry T.
    Edwards, The Effects of Collegiality on Judicial Decision
    Making, 
    151 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1639
    , 1645 (2003) (“[C]ollegiality
    plays an important part in mitigating the role of partisan politics
    and personal ideology by allowing judges of differing
    perspectives and philosophies to communicate with, listen to,
    and ultimately influence one another in constructive and law-
    abiding ways.”).
    12
    By statute, certain independent agencies must include
    members of both major political parties. See, e.g., 
    15 U.S.C. § 41
    (Federal Trade Commission); 15 U.S.C. § 78d(a) (Securities and
    Exchange Commission); 
    15 U.S.C. § 2053
    (c) (Consumer Product
    Safety Commission); 
    42 U.S.C. § 7171
    (b)(1) (Federal Energy
    Regulatory Commission). Most others are bipartisan by tradition.
    41
    As compared to a single-Director independent agency
    structure, a multi-member independent agency structure – and
    its inherent requirement for compromise and consensus – will
    tend to lead to decisions that are not as extreme, idiosyncratic,
    or otherwise off the rails. Cf. Stephen M. Bainbridge, Why a
    Board? Group Decisionmaking in Corporate Governance, 
    55 Vand. L. Rev. 1
    , 12-19 (2002). A multi-member independent
    agency can go only as far as the middle vote is willing to go.
    Conversely, under a single-Director structure, an agency’s
    policy goals “will be subject to the whims and idiosyncratic
    views of a single individual.” Joshua D. Wright, The
    Antitrust/Consumer Protection Paradox: Two Policies at War
    with Each Other, 
    121 Yale L.J. 2216
    , 2260 (2012); cf. Recent
    Legislation, Dodd-Frank Act Creates the Consumer Financial
    Protection Bureau, 
    124 Harv. L. Rev. 2123
    , 2128 (2011)
    (multi-member commission structure “reduces the variance of
    policy and improves accuracy through aggregation”); Michael
    B. Rappaport, Essay, Replacing Independent Counsels with
    Congressional Investigations, 
    148 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1595
    , 1601
    n.17 (2000) (“independent agencies tend to be headed by
    multimember commissions, which function to prevent aberrant
    actions”).
    Relatedly, as compared to a single-Director independent
    agency, a multi-member independent agency (particularly
    when bipartisan) supplies “a built-in monitoring system for
    interests on both sides because that type of body is more likely
    to produce a dissent if the agency goes too far in one direction.”
    Rachel E. Barkow, Insulating Agencies: Avoiding Capture
    Through Institutional Design, 
    89 Tex. L. Rev. 15
    , 41 (2010).
    A dissent, in turn, can serve “as a ‘fire alarm’ that alerts
    Congress and the public at large that the agency’s decision
    might merit closer scrutiny.” Id.; see also Dodd-Frank Act
    Creates the Consumer Financial Protection Bureau, 124 Harv.
    42
    L. Rev. at 2128 (the “presence of dissenters” in agency
    proceedings “provides new information and forces the
    proponent to articulate a coherent rationale, thus acting as a
    constraining force”).
    Moreover, multi-member independent agencies are better
    structured than single-Director independent agencies to guard
    against “capture” of – that is, undue influence over –
    independent agencies by regulated entities or interest groups,
    for example. As Elizabeth Warren noted in her original
    proposal for a multi-member consumer protection agency:
    “With every agency, the fear of regulatory capture is ever-
    present.” Elizabeth Warren, Unsafe at Any Rate: If It’s Good
    Enough for Microwaves, It’s Good Enough for Mortgages.
    Why We Need a Financial Product Safety Commission,
    Democracy, Summer 2007, at 8, 18. Capture can infringe
    individual liberty because capture can prevent a neutral,
    impartial agency assessment of what rules to issue or what
    enforcement actions to undertake or how to resolve
    adjudications. In a multi-member agency, however, the
    capturing parties “must capture a majority of the membership
    rather than just one individual.” Lisa Schultz Bressman &
    Robert B. Thompson, The Future of Agency Independence, 
    63 Vand. L. Rev. 599
    , 611 (2010); see also ROBERT E. CUSHMAN,
    THE INDEPENDENT REGULATORY COMMISSIONS 153 (1941)
    (noting, in reference to Federal Reserve Act of 1913, that it
    “seemed easier to protect a board from political control than to
    protect a single appointed official”); Barkow, Insulating
    Agencies, 89 Tex. L. Rev. at 38 (“[O]nly one person at the apex
    can also mean that the agency is more easily captured.”);
    Robinson, On Reorganizing the Independent Regulatory
    Agencies, 57 Va. L. Rev. at 962 (“[T]he single administrator
    may be more vulnerable” to interest group pressures “because
    43
    he provides a sharper focus for the concentration of special
    interest power and influence.”). 13
    In short, when an independent agency is structured as a
    multi-member agency rather than as a single-Director agency,
    the agency can better protect individual liberty because it can
    better prevent arbitrary enforcement actions and unlawful or
    otherwise unreasonable rules. 14
    13
    This case exemplifies the reality of (and not just the potential
    for) arbitrary decisionmaking by the Director of the CFPB. The
    Director discarded the Government’s longstanding interpretation of
    the relevant statute, adopted a new interpretation of that statute,
    applied that new interpretation retroactively, and then imposed
    massive sanctions on PHH for violation of the statute – even though
    PHH’s relevant acts occurred before the Director changed his
    interpretation of the statute. Cf. Landgraf v. USI Film Products, 
    511 U.S. 244
    , 265 (1994) (“Elementary considerations of fairness dictate
    that individuals should have an opportunity to know what the law is
    and to conform their conduct accordingly.”). Notably, the Director
    unilaterally added $103 million to the $6 million in penalties that had
    been imposed by the administrative law judge.
    14
    To be sure, multi-member independent agencies are hardly
    perfect. For example, some members of multi-member independent
    agencies may occasionally move in lockstep, thereby diminishing the
    benefits of multi-member bodies. Moreover, it can be harder to find
    three or five highly qualified commissioners than just one highly
    qualified commissioner. And multi-member bodies are often not as
    efficient as single-headed agencies and can be beset by contentious
    relations among the members. That said, “[c]onvenience and
    efficiency are not the primary objectives – or the hallmarks – of
    democratic government.” Bowsher v. Synar, 
    478 U.S. 714
    , 736
    (1986). Indeed, so as to avoid falling back into the kind of tyranny
    that they had declared independence from, the Framers often made
    trade-offs against efficiency in the interest of enhancing liberty.
    44
    B
    Notably, the multi-member structure of independent
    agencies is not an accident. On the contrary, Congress has
    traditionally designed independent agencies as multi-member
    bodies in order to protect liberty and prevent arbitrary
    decisionmaking by a single unaccountable Director.
    As Franklin Roosevelt’s Administration explained in its
    comprehensive study of independent agencies, the “popular
    belief that important rule-making functions ought to be
    performed by a group rather than by a single officer, by a
    commission rather than by a department head,” was a reason
    “for the establishment of independent regulatory agencies.”
    THE PRESIDENT’S COMMITTEE ON ADMINISTRATIVE
    MANAGEMENT, REPORT OF THE COMMITTEE WITH STUDIES OF
    ADMINISTRATIVE       MANAGEMENT         IN   THE     FEDERAL
    GOVERNMENT 216 (1937). In a leading study of independent
    commissions, a member of the Roosevelt Administration
    analyzed the creation of the Federal Trade Commission and
    explained: “The two ideas, a commission and independence
    for the commission, were inextricably bound together. At no
    point was it proposed that a commission ought to be set up
    unless it be independent or that an independent officer should
    be created rather than a commission.” ROBERT E. CUSHMAN,
    THE INDEPENDENT REGULATORY COMMISSIONS 188 (1941)
    (emphasis added).
    Senator Newlands, the sponsor of the legislation creating
    the Federal Trade Commission, emphasized the need for a
    commission rather than a single Director: “If only powers of
    investigation and publicity are given a single-headed
    organization, like the Bureau of Corporations, might be the best
    for the work; but if judgment and discretion are to be exercised,
    or if we have in contemplation the exercise of any corrective
    45
    power hereafter, or if the broad ends above outlined are to be
    attained, it seems to me that a commission is required.” 51
    Cong. Rec. 11,092 (1914).
    In Humphrey’s Executor, the Supreme Court recognized
    that Congress intended independent agencies to be multi-
    member bodies. The Court repeatedly noted that the Federal
    Trade Commission is “a body of experts.” Humphrey’s
    Executor v. United States, 
    295 U.S. 602
    , 624 (1935). The
    Court stated that the nature and functions of the Commission
    evinced Congress’s “intent to create a body of experts who
    shall gain experience by length of service – a body which shall
    be independent of executive authority, except in its selection,
    and free to exercise its judgment without the leave or hindrance
    of any other official or any department of the government.”
    
    Id. at 625-26
     (first emphasis added).
    In short, Congress structured independent agencies as
    multi-member agencies for good reason – namely, to safeguard
    individual liberty from the excesses of a single officer’s
    unaccountable decisionmaking.
    C
    When examining the relevant history, we can see that the
    original design, common understanding, and consistent
    historical practice of independent agencies as multi-member
    bodies reflect the larger values of the Constitution. The
    Constitution as a whole embodies the bedrock principle that
    dividing power among multiple entities and persons helps
    protect individual liberty. The Framers created a federal
    system with the national power divided among three branches.
    The Framers “viewed the principle of separation of powers as
    the absolutely central guarantee of a just Government.”
    46
    Morrison v. Olson, 
    487 U.S. 654
    , 697 (1988) (Scalia, J.,
    dissenting).
    The principle of checks and balances influenced how the
    Framers allocated power within the three national branches.
    For example, the Framers divided the Legislative Branch into
    two houses, each with multiple members. No one person
    operates as Legislator in Chief. Rather, 535 Members of
    Congress do so, divided into two Houses. Likewise, the
    Framers established “one supreme Court” composed of
    multiple “Judges” rather than a single judge. No one person
    operates as the Supreme Justice. Rather, the Court consists of
    one Chief Justice and several Associate Justices, all of whom
    have equal votes on cases.
    Of course, the one exception to the Constitution’s division
    of power among multiple parties within the branches is the
    President, who is the lone head of the entire Executive Branch.
    But the President is the exception that proves the rule. For
    starters, the Framers were concerned that dividing the
    executive power among multiple individuals would render the
    Executive Branch too weak as compared to the more
    formidable Legislative Branch. See THE FEDERALIST NO. 48
    (Madison) (It is “against the enterprising ambition” of the
    Legislative Branch “that the people ought to indulge all their
    jealousy and exhaust all their precautions. The legislative
    department derives a superiority in our governments . . . .”).
    The Framers sought “[e]nergy in the executive.” THE
    FEDERALIST NO. 70 (Hamilton).
    At the same time, the Framers certainly recognized the risk
    that a single President could lead to tyranny or arbitrary
    decisionmaking. To mitigate the risk to liberty from a single
    President, the Framers ensured that the President had “a due
    dependence on the people.” 
    Id.
     The President is nationally
    47
    elected. In choosing the President, “the whole Nation has a
    part, making him the focus of public hopes and expectations.”
    Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 
    343 U.S. 579
    , 653
    (1952) (Jackson, J., concurring). Presidential candidates are
    put through the wringer precisely because of the power they
    may someday wield.          In other words, the Framers
    concentrated executive power in a single President on the
    condition that the President would be nationally elected and
    nationally accountable.
    The President is therefore the exception to the ordinary
    constitutional practice of dividing power among multiple
    entities and persons.        Apart from the President, the
    Constitution reflects the basic commonsense principle that
    multi-member bodies – the House, the Senate, the Supreme
    Court – do better than single-member bodies in avoiding
    arbitrary decisionmaking and abuses of power, and thereby
    protecting individual liberty.
    That background constitutional principle buttresses the
    conclusion that a single-Director independent agency lies
    outside the norm and poses a risk to individual liberty. After
    all, the Director of the CFPB is not elected by the people and
    is of course not remotely comparable to the President in terms
    of accountability to the people. And in addition to exercising
    executive enforcement authority, the Director of the CFPB
    unilaterally exercises quasi-legislative power, even though that
    power is ordinarily exercised by multi-member legislative
    bodies. Moreover, the Director of the CFPB unilaterally
    exercises appellate quasi-judicial power, even though that
    power is ordinarily exercised by multi-member bodies.
    48
    ***
    Justice Kennedy has stated: “Liberty is always at stake
    when one or more of the branches seek to transgress the
    separation of powers.” Clinton v. City of New York, 
    524 U.S. 417
    , 450 (1998) (Kennedy, J., concurring). In this case, the
    CFPB’s novel single-Director structure departs from history,
    transgresses the separation of powers, and threatens individual
    liberty.
    III. PRESIDENTIAL AUTHORITY
    The single-Director structure of the CFPB not only departs
    from history and threatens individual liberty.          It also
    diminishes the President’s power to exercise influence over the
    CFPB, as compared to the President’s power to exercise
    influence over traditional multi-member independent agencies.
    That additional diminution of Presidential authority
    exacerbates the Article II problem posed by the single-Director
    CFPB.
    In traditional multi-member agencies, the President may
    designate the chair of the agency, and the President may
    remove a chair at will from the chair position. (Of course, the
    President may not remove that official from the commission or
    board altogether, only from the position as chair.) By contrast,
    the CFPB has only one Director, and the President may not
    designate a new Director until the former Director leaves office
    or the Director’s term expires. That structure diminishes the
    President’s power to influence the direction of the CFPB, as
    compared to the President’s power to influence the direction of
    traditional multi-member independent agencies.
    49
    That diminution of Presidential power runs afoul of the
    Article II principle articulated by the Supreme Court in Free
    Enterprise Fund. Indeed, this case involves a greater
    diminution of Presidential power than occurred in Free
    Enterprise Fund.
    A
    As the Supreme Court stated in Free Enterprise Fund, the
    “landmark case of Myers v. United States reaffirmed the
    principle that Article II confers on the President the general
    administrative control of those executing the laws.” Free
    Enterprise Fund v. Public Company Accounting Oversight
    Board, 
    561 U.S. 477
    , 492-93 (2010). In other words, when it
    comes to the “responsibility to take care that the laws be
    faithfully executed,” Article II of the Constitution means that
    the “buck stops with the President.” 
    Id. at 493
    . At the same
    time, the Free Enterprise Fund Court acknowledged that the
    general rule of Presidential removal was cabined by the Court’s
    decision in Humphrey’s Executor.
    But as the Supreme Court indicated in Free Enterprise
    Fund, an independent agency’s structure violates Article II
    when it is not historically rooted and when it causes an
    additional diminution of Presidential control beyond that
    caused by a traditional independent agency. See 
    id. at 501
    (“We deal with the unusual situation, never before addressed
    by the Court, of two layers of for-cause tenure. And though it
    may be criticized as ‘elementary arithmetical logic,’ two layers
    are not the same as one.”).
    The CFPB’s single-Director structure contravenes that
    diminution principle. As a result of the CFPB’s novel single-
    Director structure and the five-year fixed term for the Director,
    a President may be stuck for years – or even for his or her entire
    50
    four-year term – with a single Director who was appointed by
    a prior President and who has different policy views.
    Nothing comparable happens in traditional multi-member
    independent agencies. Rather, the traditional multi-member
    structure ordinarily allows the current President to exercise
    some influence over the agency through Presidential
    appointment. That is because the President may designate
    agency chairs and may remove agency chairs at will from their
    positions as chairs. 15
    The power to designate and remove chairs at will is
    important because, by statute, the “chairs of multimember
    agencies have been granted budget, personnel, and agenda
    control.” Kirti Datla & Richard L. Revesz, Deconstructing
    Independent Agencies (and Executive Agencies), 
    98 Cornell L. Rev. 769
    , 818 (2013). “In many agencies, the chair has the
    right to appoint staff directly and is the public voice of the
    agency. These powers allow the chair to exercise significant
    control over the agency’s agenda.” Rachel E. Barkow,
    15
    For example, the President unilaterally designates (and may
    unilaterally remove at will from the position as chair) the chairs of
    the following agencies: the Defense Nuclear Facilities Safety Board,
    
    42 U.S.C. § 2286
    (c)(1); the Federal Communications Commission,
    
    47 U.S.C. § 154
    (a); the Federal Energy Regulatory Commission, 
    42 U.S.C. § 7171
    (b)(1); the Federal Maritime Commission, 
    46 U.S.C. § 301
    (c)(1); the Federal Labor Relations Authority, 
    5 U.S.C. § 7104
    (b); the Federal Trade Commission, 
    15 U.S.C. § 41
    ; the Federal
    Mine Safety and Health Review Commission, 
    30 U.S.C. § 823
    (a);
    the National Labor Relations Board, 
    29 U.S.C. § 153
    (a); the Nuclear
    Regulatory Commission, 
    42 U.S.C. § 5841
    (a); the Occupational
    Safety and Health Review Commission, 
    29 U.S.C. § 661
    (a); the
    Postal Regulatory Commission, 
    39 U.S.C. § 502
    (d); the Securities
    and Exchange Commission, 15 U.S.C. § 78d note; and the Surface
    Transportation Board, 
    49 U.S.C. § 1301
    (c).
    51
    Insulating Agencies: Avoiding Capture Through Institutional
    Design, 
    89 Tex. L. Rev. 15
    , 39 (2010).
    Professor Revesz is one of the Nation’s leading scholars of
    the administrative state. He and Kirti Datla have succinctly
    summarized the President’s authority with respect to chairs:
    The chair of a multimember agency usually holds the
    position of chair – but not as a member of the agency – at
    the will of the President. After removal of an existing
    chair, the President can then appoint a new chair with
    preferences closer to his. The ability of the President to
    retain policy influence through the selection of the chair is
    important because . . . the chair of a multimember agency
    is ordinarily its most dominant figure. While there is room
    for debate, it is clear that the ability to appoint the head of
    an independent agency allows the President to retain some
    control over that agency’s activities. An appointed chair
    will align with the President for multiple reasons.
    Datla & Revesz, Deconstructing Independent Agencies, 98
    Cornell L. Rev. at 819 (internal quotation marks omitted)
    (emphases added); see also Glen O. Robinson, Independent
    Agencies: Form and Substance in Executive Prerogative, 
    1988 Duke L.J. 238
    , 245 n.24 (1988) (“It is important to note that
    since Humphrey’s Executor the President generally has been
    given power to designate agency chairmen. . . . From personal
    experience I can report that the FCC’s chairman and a handful
    of staff – usually selected by the chair – can and usually do
    exercise nearly total control over that agency’s basic policy
    agenda.”).
    To be sure, the chair alone ordinarily may not affirmatively
    issue rules, initiate enforcement actions, or adjudicate disputes.
    But the chair both controls the agenda and may prevent certain
    52
    actions from occurring. So the President’s ability to designate
    a chair is valuable, even in circumstances where the agency as
    a whole continues to be controlled by commissioners or board
    members who might oppose the President’s views.
    By exercising their power to appoint chairs of the major
    multi-member independent agencies, Presidents may gain
    some control over the direction of those agencies within days
    of taking office at the start of their first terms. For example,
    President Trump replaced the chairs of the FTC, FCC, SEC,
    and NLRB within one week of taking office in January 2017.
    President Obama did the same by March 2009.
    But a President has no such power when it comes to the
    single Director of the CFPB, who serves a fixed five-year term.
    Unlike with the FTC, FCC, SEC, and NLRB, for example, the
    President was not able to designate a new Director of the CFPB
    in January 2017.
    That problem will only grow worse for the next few
    Presidents. The most recent CFPB Director left office in
    November 2017. Assuming for present purposes that a new
    Director is appointed in 2018 for a five-year term, that Director
    may serve until 2023 – several years after the 2020 election.
    The President who is elected (or re-elected) in 2020 will have
    no power to remove that Director until 2023, some two or three
    years into that Presidential term. A new Director then will be
    appointed in 2023. That Director could serve until 2028 –
    nearly the entire term of the President elected in 2024.
    Another new Director may be appointed in 2028. That
    Director could serve until 2033, meaning for the entirety of the
    term of the President elected in 2028.
    Those very realistic scenarios expose the CFPB’s flagrant
    disregard of constitutional text, history, structure, and
    53
    precedent (not to mention, common sense). And those
    scenarios convincingly demonstrate that the single-Director
    CFPB, with its fixed five-year Director term, causes a
    diminution of Presidential power greater than the diminution
    that occurs in traditional multi-member independent agencies.
    There is more.        In a multi-member agency, the
    commissioners or board members other than the chair serve
    staggered terms and are replaced by the President as their terms
    expire.     A tradition has developed by which some
    commissioners or board members of the opposite party resign
    from independent agencies when a new President takes office.
    See Datla & Revesz, Deconstructing Independent Agencies, 98
    Cornell L. Rev. at 820-21. Even apart from that tradition, the
    staggered terms mean that a President will have ever-increasing
    influence (through appointments) over an independent agency
    during the course of that President’s term. That does not occur
    with the single-Director CFPB. Until the Director’s term
    expires, the new President has zero influence through
    appointment, and the zero remains zero until the Director’s
    term expires. Although this line of reasoning “may be
    criticized as elementary arithmetical logic,” some influence
    exceeds zero influence. Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 501
    .
    This is a much starker case of unconstitutionality than Free
    Enterprise Fund. In Free Enterprise Fund, the second for-
    cause provision did not afford PCAOB members all that much
    additional insulation from the President. The case therefore
    involved an important but marginal additional diminution of
    Presidential authority beyond the diminution that occurs in a
    traditional independent agency.
    Here, by contrast, Presidents will be stuck for years at a
    time with CFPB Directors appointed by prior Presidents. This
    54
    case therefore involves a substantial additional diminution of
    Presidential authority beyond the diminution that occurs in a
    traditional independent agency. The additional diminution
    exacerbates the Article II problem posed by the single-Director
    CFPB.
    B
    The CFPB says that a single head of an independent
    agency might be more responsive on an ongoing basis to the
    President than multiple heads of an independent agency are,
    thereby mitigating the Article II concern with a single-Director
    independent agency. That argument is wrong, both as a matter
    of theory and as a matter of fact.
    To begin with, whether headed by one, three, or five
    members, an independent agency’s heads are not removable at
    will by the President. With independent agencies, the
    President is limited (after designation of the chair and
    appointment of new members) in essence to indirect cajoling.
    Cf. Elena Kagan, Presidential Administration, 
    114 Harv. L. Rev. 2245
    , 2323 (2001) (“[A] for-cause removal provision
    would buy little substantive independence if the President,
    though unable to fire an official, could command or, if
    necessary, supplant his every decision.”).16 As Justice Scalia
    16
    The for-cause removal restrictions attached to independent
    agencies ordinarily prohibit removal except in cases of inefficiency,
    neglect of duty, or malfeasance. Those restrictions have significant
    impact both in law and in practice. See Free Enterprise Fund v.
    Public Company Accounting Oversight Board, 
    561 U.S. 477
    , 502
    (2010) (for-cause restrictions “mean what they say”). Humphrey’s
    Executor and Wiener v. United States show, for example, that for-
    cause removal requirements prohibit dismissal by the President due
    to lack of trust in the administrator, see Humphrey’s Executor v.
    United States, 
    295 U.S. 602
    , 618-19, 625-26 (1935), differences in
    55
    once memorably noted, an attempt by the President to
    supervise, direct, or threaten to remove the head of an
    independent agency with respect to a particular substantive
    decision is statutorily impermissible and likely to trigger “an
    impeachment motion in Congress.” Tr. of Oral Arg. at 60,
    Free Enterprise Fund v. Public Company Accounting
    Oversight Board, 
    561 U.S. 477
     (2010). That is true whether
    there are one, three, or five heads of the independent agency.
    The independent status of an independent agency erects a high
    barrier between the President and the independent agency,
    regardless of how many people head the independent agency
    on the other side of the barrier.
    Moreover, even assuming that ongoing influence of
    independent agencies can occur in indirect ways, it is not
    plausible to say that a President could have more indirect
    ongoing influence over (i) a single Director who has policy
    views contrary to the President’s than the President has over
    (ii) a multi-member independent agency headed by a chair who
    policy outlook, 
    id.,
     or the mere desire to install administrators of the
    President’s choosing, Wiener v. United States, 
    357 U.S. 349
    , 356
    (1958).
    To cabin the effects of Humphrey’s Executor on the Presidency,
    some have proposed reading the standard for-cause removal
    restrictions in the statutes creating independent agencies to allow for
    Presidential removal of independent agency heads based on policy
    differences.     But as the Supreme Court recently explained,
    Humphrey’s Executor refuted the idea that “simple disagreement”
    with an agency head’s “policies or priorities could constitute ‘good
    cause’ for its removal.” Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 502
    .
    The Free Enterprise Fund Court expressly confirmed that
    Humphrey’s Executor “rejected a removal premised on a lack of
    agreement on either the policies or the administering of the Federal
    Trade Commission.” 
    Id.
    56
    is appointed by the President and shares the same policy views
    as the President.
    In short, given the President’s inability to designate a new
    CFPB Director at the beginning of the Presidency – in contrast
    to the President’s ability to appoint chairs of the FTC, FCC,
    SEC, and NLRB, for example – the single-Director CFPB
    structure diminishes the President’s power more than the
    traditional multi-member independent agency does. 17
    17
    The CFPB says that the Chair of the Federal Reserve Board
    is not removable at will from the chair position. That is not apparent
    from the statutory language. Cf. infra note 20; see also Adrian
    Vermeule, Conventions of Agency Independence, 
    113 Colum. L. Rev. 1163
    , 1196 (2013) (While “the members of the Federal Reserve
    Board enjoy statutory for-cause protection, the Chair and Vice Chairs
    do not, qua Chairs.”). But even assuming the CFPB’s assertion is
    correct, such an exception would simply reflect the unique function
    of the Federal Reserve Board with respect to monetary policy. The
    Chair of the Federal Reserve Board would be akin to what Justice
    Breyer in Noel Canning referred to as an historical anomaly – here,
    an anomaly due to the Federal Reserve’s special functions in setting
    monetary policy and stabilizing the financial markets. The Federal
    Reserve Board is certainly not a model or precedent for wholesale
    creation of a vast independent regulatory state run by single-Director
    independent agencies that oppose a particular President. If the
    CFPB is right in this case, Congress could create an independent
    Federal Reserve headed by one Director. The CFPB apparently
    thinks that would be fine. I disagree. Indeed, that question should
    not be a close call. Apart from the Federal Reserve Board, there are
    a few other relatively minor examples where the President arguably
    may not have the ability to designate and remove chairs at will. But
    as discussed above, there can be no doubt that the common practice
    in traditional independent agencies is that the President may
    designate a chair and remove a chair at will.
    57
    The CFPB also says that Congress’s creation of the single-
    Director structure is unlikely to afford Congress any greater
    influence over the CFPB than Congress has over a multi-
    member independent agency. Perhaps true, perhaps not.
    Either way, however, the Supreme Court has stressed that
    congressional aggrandizement is not a necessary feature of an
    Article II violation in this context. The Court squarely said as
    much in Free Enterprise Fund. “Even when a branch does not
    arrogate power to itself, therefore, it must not impair another in
    the performance of its constitutional duties.” 
    561 U.S. at 500
    .
    And to take an obvious example of the point, if Congress
    enacted legislation converting the Department of Justice into
    an independent agency, there would be no formal
    congressional aggrandizement. But there is little doubt that
    such legislation would violate Article II. See Morrison v.
    Olson, 
    487 U.S. 654
    , 695-96 (1988).
    In considering the Presidential power point, keep in mind
    that the CFPB repeatedly compares itself to the FTC. That
    comparison is wrong as a matter of history and liberty, as
    discussed above. But the comparison is also wrong as a matter
    of Presidential authority. When the three-judge panel first
    heard this case in 2016, some of the threats to Presidential
    power may have appeared theoretical. In 2017, those threats
    became much more concrete. In January 2017, the President
    designated new Chairs of the FTC, FCC, SEC, and NLRB,
    among other multi-member independent                 agencies.
    Meanwhile, the President was legally unable to designate a new
    CFPB Director. The President’s inability to do so led to a
    variety of episodes throughout 2017 that highlighted the
    diminution of Presidential power over the CFPB, as compared
    to the President’s power over the traditional multi-member
    independent agencies. For example, during 2017, the Director
    of the CFPB took several major actions contrary to the
    President’s policy views.
    58
    In the wake of the CFPB’s activities over the past year, the
    question that the Supreme Court asked in Free Enterprise Fund
    is right on point: “where, in all this, is the role for oversight
    by an elected President?” 
    561 U.S. at 499
    . By disabling the
    President from supervising and directing the Director of the
    CFPB, the Dodd-Frank Act contravenes the Supreme Court’s
    statement in Free Enterprise Fund: “Congress cannot reduce
    the Chief Magistrate to a cajoler-in-chief.” 
    Id. at 502
    .
    In sum, the novel single-Director structure of the CFPB
    diminishes Presidential authority more than the traditional
    multi-member agencies do. That diminution of Presidential
    authority exacerbates the Article II problem with the single-
    Director CFPB.
    C
    The CFPB’s departure from historical practice, threat to
    individual liberty, and diminution of Presidential authority
    combine to make this an overwhelming case of
    unconstitutionality.
    But suppose that there were no additional diminution of
    Presidential authority caused by the single-Director structure
    of the CFPB, beyond that which occurs with traditional multi-
    member independent agencies. Would the single-Director
    structure still be unconstitutional? The answer is yes.
    Neither Humphrey’s Executor nor any later case has
    granted Congress a free pass, without boundaries, to create
    independent agencies that depart from history and threaten
    individual liberty. Humphrey’s Executor is not a blank check
    for Congress. Humphrey’s Executor does not mean that
    anything goes. In that respect, keep in mind (in case I have
    not mentioned it enough already) that the Constitution’s
    59
    separation of powers is not solely or even primarily concerned
    with preserving the powers of the branches. The separation of
    powers is primarily designed to protect individual liberty.
    As I have explained, the single-Director CFPB departs
    from settled historical practice and threatens individual liberty
    far more than a multi-member independent agency does. The
    single-Director CFPB therefore poses a constitutional problem
    even if (counter-factually) it does not occasion any additional
    diminution of Presidential power beyond that caused by
    traditional multi-member independent agencies.
    IV. VERTICAL STARE DECISIS AND JUDICIAL DEFERENCE
    Notwithstanding all of the above, the CFPB argues that, as
    a matter of vertical stare decisis, this case is controlled
    by (i) Humphrey’s Executor; (ii) Morrison; or (iii) general
    principles of judicial deference. The CFPB is incorrect.
    First, the CFPB contends that Humphrey’s Executor
    controls this case – in other words, that Humphrey’s Executor
    by its terms upheld all independent agencies, including single-
    Director independent agencies.          That is wrong.       In
    Humphrey’s Executor, the Supreme Court did not say (or
    articulate a principle) that single-Director independent
    agencies are constitutional. Not even close.
    After all, Humphrey’s representative argued to the
    Supreme Court that the “nature” of the Federal Trade
    Commission justified independence from the President:
    “With the increasing complexity of human activities many
    situations arise where governmental control can be secured
    only by the ‘board’ or ‘commission’ form of legislation.”
    Brief for Samuel F. Rathbun, Executor, at 41, Humphrey’s
    Executor v. United States, 
    295 U.S. 602
     (1935) (citation and
    60
    internal quotation marks omitted). In its opinion, the Court
    agreed. The Court noted that the Federal Trade Commission
    “is to be non-partisan” and, like the Interstate Commerce
    Commission, be composed of members “called upon to
    exercise the trained judgment of a body of experts.”
    Humphrey’s Executor, 
    295 U.S. at 624
    . The Court stated that
    the nature and functions of the FTC evinced Congress’s “intent
    to create a body of experts who shall gain experience by length
    of service – a body which shall be independent of executive
    authority, except in its selection, and free to exercise its
    judgment without the leave or hindrance of any other official
    or any department of the government.” 
    Id. at 625-26
    (emphasis omitted).
    The CFPB responds that the Humphrey’s Executor Court’s
    multiple references to a “body of experts” were not relevant to
    the Court’s constitutional holding. That is incorrect. The
    Court repeatedly referenced the Federal Trade Commission’s
    status as a body of experts in concluding that Congress could
    permissibly insulate the FTC commissioners from Presidential
    removal. The Court wrote: “The Federal Trade Commission
    is an administrative body created by Congress to carry into
    effect legislative policies embodied in the statute in accordance
    with the legislative standard therein prescribed, and to perform
    other specified duties as a legislative or as a judicial aid.” 
    Id. at 628
    . “Such a body,” according to the Court, “cannot in any
    proper sense be characterized as an arm or an eye of the
    executive,” and thus such a body can be made independent of
    the President. 
    Id.
    In short, Humphrey’s Executor repeatedly emphasized the
    multi-member structure of the FTC. In doing so, Humphrey’s
    Executor drew (at least implicitly) the same distinction
    between multi-member agencies and single-Director agencies
    that I am drawing in this case. At best for the CFPB,
    61
    Humphrey’s Executor leaves open the single-Director
    question. Humphrey’s Executor does not hold that single-
    Director independent agencies are constitutional. 18
    18
    In its brief, PHH has expressly preserved the argument that
    Humphrey’s Executor should be overruled. The reasoning of
    Humphrey’s Executor is inconsistent with the reasoning in the
    Court’s prior decision in Myers. See Humphrey’s Executor v.
    United States, 
    295 U.S. 602
    , 626 (1935) (“In so far as” the
    expressions in Myers are “out of harmony with the views here set
    forth, these expressions are disapproved.”). The Humphrey’s
    Executor decision subsequently has received significant criticism.
    See Geoffrey P. Miller, Independent Agencies, 
    1986 Sup. Ct. Rev. 41
    , 93 (“Humphrey’s Executor, as commentators have noted, is one
    of the more egregious opinions to be found on pages of the United
    States Supreme Court Reports.”); Peter L. Strauss, The Place of
    Agencies in Government: Separation of Powers and the Fourth
    Branch, 
    84 Colum. L. Rev. 573
    , 611-12 (1984) (“Remarkably, the
    Court did not pause to examine how a purpose to create a body
    ‘subject only to the people of the United States’ – that is, apparently,
    beyond control of the constitutionally defined branches of
    government – could itself be sustained under the Constitution.”).
    Moreover, the reasoning of Humphrey’s Executor is in tension with
    the reasoning of the Supreme Court’s recent decision in Free
    Enterprise Fund. See In re Aiken County, 
    645 F.3d 428
    , 444-46
    (D.C. Cir. 2011) (Kavanaugh, J., concurring); Neomi Rao, Removal:
    Necessary and Sufficient for Presidential Control, 
    65 Ala. L. Rev. 1205
    , 1208 (2014).
    For those reasons, among others, PHH preserves the argument
    that Humphrey’s Executor should be overruled by the Supreme
    Court. Overruling Humphrey’s Executor would not mean the end
    of the agencies that are now independent. The agencies would
    instead transform into executive agencies supervised and directed by
    the President. So the question is not the existence of the agencies;
    the question is the President’s control over the agencies and the
    resulting accountability of those agencies to the people.
    In any event, it is not our job to decide whether to overrule
    Humphrey’s Executor. As a lower court, we must follow Supreme
    62
    Second, the CFPB argues that Morrison v. Olson controls
    this case. That suggestion is even further afield. Morrison
    upheld the independent counsel law. But the independent
    counsel differed in three critical ways from the ordinary
    independent agency. The independent counsel had only a
    narrowly defined jurisdiction in cases where the Department of
    Justice had a conflict of interest. The independent counsel had
    only enforcement authority, not rulemaking or adjudicative
    authority. And the independent counsel was an inferior
    officer, not a principal officer (a point the Supreme Court
    emphasized in Free Enterprise Fund). The independent
    counsel was an inferior officer, the Morrison Court said,
    because she could be supervised and directed by the Attorney
    General. Morrison did not hold – or even hint – that a single
    principal officer could be the sole head of an independent
    regulatory agency with broad enforcement, rulemaking, and
    adjudication powers.
    Moreover, no party in Morrison argued that the Office of
    the Independent Counsel was unconstitutional because a single
    person headed it. And it is black-letter law that cases are not
    precedent for issues that were not raised or decided. See
    BRYAN A. GARNER ET AL., THE LAW OF JUDICIAL PRECEDENT
    46, 84, 226-28 (2016). For that reason, too, it is impossible to
    rely on the result in Morrison as a binding precedent on the
    single-Director question.
    The CFPB separately argues that the so-called Morrison
    “test” – as distinct from Morrison’s result – dictates a particular
    conclusion in this case. In Morrison, the Court said that
    Court precedent, including Humphrey’s Executor. But it is
    emphatically our job to apply Humphrey’s Executor in a manner
    consistent with settled historical practice, the Constitution’s
    protection of individual liberty, and Article II’s assignment of
    executive authority to the President.
    63
    removal restrictions could not be “of such a nature that they
    impede the President’s ability to perform his constitutional
    duty.” Morrison v. Olson, 
    487 U.S. 654
    , 691 (1988). As
    relevant here, Morrison and Free Enterprise Fund together
    mean that Congress may not diminish Presidential control over
    independent agencies more than the diminution that occurs
    with traditional multi-member agencies.
    As explained above, the single-Director independent
    agency structure does diminish Presidential authority more
    than traditional multi-member independent agencies do. So
    the CFPB flunks the Morrison and Free Enterprise Fund test.
    Even if that were not the case, however, the Morrison
    “test” is not the exclusive way that a novel independent agency
    structure may violate Article II.         Neither Humphrey’s
    Executor nor any later case gives Congress blanket permission
    to create independent agencies that depart from history and
    threaten individual liberty.
    In that regard, I repeat what I wrote 10 years ago in Free
    Enterprise Fund:
    [T]he lengthy recitation of text, original understanding,
    history, and precedent above leads to the following
    principle: Humphrey’s Executor and Morrison represent
    what up to now have been the outermost constitutional
    limits of permissible congressional restrictions on the
    President’s removal power. Therefore, given a choice
    between drawing the line at the holdings in Humphrey’s
    Executor and Morrison or extending those cases to
    authorize novel structures such as the PCAOB that further
    attenuate the President’s control over executive officers,
    we should opt for the former. We should resolve
    questions about the scope of those precedents in light of
    64
    and in the direction of the constitutional text and
    constitutional history. . . . In this case, that sensible
    principle dictates that we hold the line and not allow
    encroachments on the President’s removal power beyond
    what Humphrey’s Executor and Morrison already permit.
    Free Enterprise Fund v. Public Company Accounting
    Oversight Board, 
    537 F.3d 667
    , 698 (D.C. Cir. 2008)
    (Kavanaugh, J., dissenting).
    Third, in addition to invoking Humphrey’s Executor and
    Morrison, the CFPB and its amici cite various arguments for
    judicial deference to Congress’s choice of a single-Director
    structure. Those scattershot arguments are all unavailing.
    Some speak of the CFPB as a one-off congressional
    experiment (like the independent counsel law) and suggest that
    we should let it go as a matter of judicial deference to Congress.
    But even apart from the fundamental point that our job as
    judges is to enforce the law, not abdicate to the political
    branches, cf. Boumediene v. Bush, 
    553 U.S. 723
    , 765-66
    (2008), we cannot think of this as a one-off case because we
    could not cabin the consequences in any principled manner if
    we were to uphold the CFPB’s single-Director structure. As
    the Supreme Court has warned: “Slight encroachments create
    new boundaries from which legions of power can seek new
    territory to capture.” Stern v. Marshall, 
    564 U.S. 462
    , 503
    (2011). Justice Frankfurter captured it well in his opinion in
    Youngstown: “The accretion of dangerous power does not
    come in a day. It does come, however slowly, from the
    generative force of unchecked disregard of the restrictions that
    fence in even the most disinterested assertion of authority.”
    Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 
    343 U.S. 579
    , 594
    (1952) (Frankfurter, J., concurring).
    65
    That fairly describes what a ruling upholding the CFPB’s
    single-Director structure would mean.          As the CFPB
    acknowledged at oral argument before the three-judge panel, a
    ruling in its favor would necessarily allow all extant
    independent agencies to be headed by one person. The
    CFPB’s position, if accepted, would give Congress the green
    light to convert other heads of independent agencies into single
    Directors rather than multi-member commissions. A single-
    Director SEC, with the power to unilaterally impose $500
    million penalties? A single-Director FCC, with the power to
    unilaterally mandate or rescind “net neutrality”? A single-
    Director NLRB, with the power to unilaterally supervise
    employer-employee relations nationwide? A single-Director
    Federal Reserve, with the power to unilaterally set monetary
    policy for the United States? That’s what the CFPB’s position
    would usher in.
    “In the past, when faced with novel creations of this sort,
    the Supreme Court has looked down the slippery slope – and
    has ordinarily refused to take even a few steps down the hill.”
    Free Enterprise Fund, 
    537 F.3d at 700
     (Kavanaugh, J.,
    dissenting). We should heed that caution and not start down
    the hill in this case.
    More broadly, some suggest that judges should generally
    defer to Congress’s understanding of the Constitution’s
    separation of powers. But that hands-off attitude would flout
    a long, long line of Supreme Court precedent. See Free
    Enterprise Fund v. Public Company Accounting Oversight
    Board, 
    561 U.S. 477
    , 508 (2010) (invalidating structure of
    Public Company Accounting Oversight Board); Boumediene,
    
    553 U.S. at 765-66, 792
     (invalidating provision of Military
    Commissions Act); Clinton v. City of New York, 
    524 U.S. 417
    ,
    448-49 (1998) (invalidating Line Item Veto Act); Metropolitan
    Washington Airports Authority v. Citizens for the Abatement of
    66
    Aircraft Noise, Inc., 
    501 U.S. 252
    , 265-77 (1991) (invalidating
    structure of Metropolitan Washington Airports Authority
    Board of Review); Bowsher v. Synar, 
    478 U.S. 714
    , 733-34
    (1986) (invalidating Comptroller General’s powers under
    reporting provisions of Balanced Budget and Emergency
    Deficit Control Act); INS v. Chadha, 
    462 U.S. 919
    , 942 n.13,
    957-59 (1983) (invalidating legislative veto provision of
    Immigration and Nationality Act); Buckley v. Valeo, 
    424 U.S. 1
    , 134-35, 140 (1976) (invalidating structure of Federal
    Election Commission); Myers v. United States, 
    272 U.S. 52
    (1926) (invalidating provision requiring Senate consent to
    President’s removal of executive officer).
    Citing the fact that President Obama signed the Dodd-
    Frank Act that created the CFPB, some argue that the
    Executive Branch has somehow waived any objection to this
    Article II violation. But President George W. Bush signed the
    Sarbanes-Oxley Act that created the PCAOB. That fact did
    not deter the Supreme Court in Free Enterprise Fund. The
    Court firmly declared that “the separation of powers does not
    depend on the views of individual Presidents, nor on whether
    the encroached-upon branch approves the encroachment.”
    Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 497
    . A President cannot
    “choose to bind his successors by diminishing their powers.”
    
    Id.
    Some argue that the courts need not intervene to address
    the CFPB’s structural flaw because the CFPB is checked by
    Congress through Congress’s oversight power and ultimate
    control over appropriations. But Congress cannot supervise
    or direct the Director on an ongoing basis regarding what rules
    67
    to issue, what enforcement actions to bring (or decline to
    bring), or how to resolve adjudications. 19
    In urging judicial deference to the single-Director
    structure, the CFPB also points out that the CFPB’s decisions
    are checked by the courts, so we should not worry too much
    about the CFPB’s single-Director structure. But much of
    what an agency does – determining what rules to issue within
    a broad statutory authorization and when, how, and against
    whom to bring enforcement actions to enforce the law – occurs
    in the twilight of discretion. Those discretionary actions have
    a critical impact on individual liberty. Yet courts do not
    review or only deferentially review such exercises of agency
    19
    Moreover, Congress’s ability to check the CFPB is less than
    its ability to check traditional independent agencies. The CFPB is
    not subject to the ordinary annual appropriations process. Instead,
    the Dodd-Frank Act requires the Federal Reserve to transfer “from
    the combined earnings of the Federal Reserve System” the amount
    “determined by the Director,” not to exceed 12 percent of the “total
    operating expenses of the Federal Reserve System.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5497
    (a)(1)-(2). As those who have labored in Washington well
    understand, the regular appropriations process brings at least some
    measure of oversight by Congress. The CFPB is exempt from that
    check. To be sure, Section 5497 is not an entrenched statute
    shielded from future congressional alteration, nor could it be. See,
    e.g., Manigault v. Springs, 
    199 U.S. 473
    , 487 (1905). But changing
    that statutory provision would require Congress to enact a new law.
    In short, the CFPB’s current exemption from the ordinary
    appropriations process arguably enhances the concern in this case
    about the massive power lodged in a single, unaccountable Director.
    That said, the single-Director CFPB would constitute an Article
    II problem even if the CFPB were subject to the usual appropriations
    process. The CFPB’s exemption from the ordinary appropriations
    process is at most just “extra icing on” an unconstitutional “cake
    already frosted.” Yates v. United States, 
    135 S. Ct. 1074
    , 1093, slip
    op. at 6 (2015) (Kagan, J., dissenting).
    68
    discretion. See Chevron U.S.A. Inc. v. Natural Resources
    Defense Council, Inc., 
    467 U.S. 837
    , 844-45 (1984); Motor
    Vehicle Manufacturers Association of U.S., Inc. v. State Farm
    Mutual Automobile Insurance Co., 
    463 U.S. 29
    , 41-43 (1983);
    Heckler v. Chaney, 
    470 U.S. 821
    , 831-33 (1985). The
    probability of judicial review of some agency action has never
    excused or mitigated an Article II problem in the structure of
    the agency. See, e.g., Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. 477
    ;
    Buckley, 
    424 U.S. 1
    .
    ***
    In sum, the CFPB’s single-Director structure departs from
    settled historical practice, threatens individual liberty, and
    diminishes the President’s Article II authority to exercise the
    executive power. Applying the Supreme Court’s separation
    of powers precedents, I conclude that the CFPB is
    unconstitutionally structured because it is an independent
    agency that exercises substantial executive power and is
    headed by a single Director.
    V. REMEDY
    Having concluded that the CFPB is unconstitutionally
    structured, I reach the question of the appropriate remedy.
    In light of this one specific constitutional flaw in the Dodd-
    Frank Act, must that whole Act be struck down? Or must we
    strike down at least those statutory provisions creating the
    CFPB and defining the CFPB’s duties and authorities? Or do
    we more narrowly strike down and sever the for-cause removal
    provision that is the source of the constitutional problem?
    Not surprisingly, PHH wants us, at a minimum, to strike
    down the CFPB and prevent its continued operation. The
    69
    United States as amicus curiae agrees with PHH on the merits,
    but disagrees on the remedy. According to the United States,
    the Supreme Court’s case law requires us to impose the
    narrower remedy of simply severing the for-cause removal
    provision. I agree with the United States’ reading of the
    Supreme Court precedent.
    In Free Enterprise Fund, the Supreme Court confronted a
    similar issue with respect to the Public Company Accounting
    Oversight Board. Having found that Board’s structure
    unconstitutional, would the Court invalidate the agency (or
    even the whole Sarbanes-Oxley Act) or simply sever the for-
    cause provision? The Court stated: “Generally speaking,
    when confronting a constitutional flaw in a statute, we try to
    limit the solution to the problem, severing any problematic
    portions while leaving the remainder intact.” Free Enterprise
    Fund v. Public Company Accounting Oversight Board, 
    561 U.S. 477
    , 508 (2010). Applying that principle, the Free
    Enterprise Fund Court severed the second for-cause provision
    and otherwise left the PCAOB intact.
    Severability is appropriate, the Free Enterprise Fund
    Court stated, so long as (i) Congress would have preferred the
    law with the offending provision severed over no law at all; and
    (ii) the law with the offending provision severed would remain
    “fully operative as a law.” 
    Id. at 509
    . Both requirements are
    met here.
    First, in considering Congress’s intent with respect to
    severability, courts must decide – or often speculate, truth be
    told – whether Congress would “have preferred what is left of
    its statute to no statute at all.” Ayotte v. Planned Parenthood
    of Northern New England, 
    546 U.S. 320
    , 330 (2006); see also
    Alaska Airlines, Inc. v. Brock, 
    480 U.S. 678
    , 685 (1987) (The
    “unconstitutional provision must be severed unless the statute
    70
    created in its absence is legislation that Congress would not
    have enacted.”). Importantly, courts need not speculate and
    can presume that Congress wanted to retain the constitutional
    remainder of the statute when “Congress has explicitly
    provided for severance by including a severability clause in the
    statute.” 
    Id. at 686
    ; see also 
    id.
     (The “inclusion of such a
    clause creates a presumption that Congress did not intend the
    validity of the statute in question to depend on the validity of
    the constitutionally offensive provision.”).
    The statute at issue in Free Enterprise Fund had no
    express severability clause. By contrast, in this case, the
    Dodd-Frank Act contains an express severability clause that
    instructs: “If any provision” of the Act “is held to be
    unconstitutional, the remainder of” the Act “shall not be
    affected thereby.” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5302
    .
    This case therefore presents an even easier case than Free
    Enterprise Fund for severability of the for-cause provision.
    Through its express severability clause, the Dodd-Frank Act
    itself all but answers the question of presumed congressional
    intent. It will be the rare case when a court may ignore a
    severability provision set forth in the text of the relevant
    statute. See Alaska Airlines, 
    480 U.S. at 686
    . I see no
    justification for tilting at that windmill in this case.
    Second, we also must look at “the balance of the
    legislation” to assess whether the statute is capable “of
    functioning” without the offending provisions “in a manner
    consistent with the intent of Congress.” 
    Id. at 684-85
    (emphasis omitted). That prong of the analysis in essence
    turns on whether the truncated statute is “fully operative as a
    law.” Free Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 509
    . To take just
    one example, in Marbury v. Madison, the Court concluded that
    Section 13 of the Judiciary Act of 1789 was unconstitutional in
    71
    part. 
    5 U.S. 137
    , 179-80 (1803). But the Court did not
    disturb the remainder of the Judiciary Act. 
    Id. at 179-80
    .
    Here, as in Free Enterprise Fund, the Dodd-Frank Act and
    its CFPB-related provisions will remain “fully operative as a
    law” without the for-cause removal restriction.             Free
    Enterprise Fund, 
    561 U.S. at 509
    . Operating without the for-
    cause removal provision and under the supervision and
    direction of the President, the CFPB may still “regulate the
    offering and provision of consumer financial products or
    services under the Federal consumer financial laws,” 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (a), much as the Public Company Accounting Oversight
    Board has continued fulfilling its statutorily authorized mission
    in the wake of the Supreme Court’s decision in Free Enterprise
    Fund. 20 Moreover, the CFPB’s operation as an executive
    agency will not in any way prevent the overall Dodd-Frank Act
    from operating as a law.
    To be sure, one might ask whether, instead of severing the
    for-cause removal provision, which would make the CFPB an
    20
    The Dodd-Frank Act contains a five-year tenure provision for
    the Director, see 
    12 U.S.C. § 5491
    (c)(1), akin to the similar 10-year
    tenure provision for the Director of the FBI and the 5-year tenure
    provision for the Commissioner of the IRS. See Crime Control Act
    of 1976, § 203, reprinted in 
    28 U.S.C. § 532
     note (FBI Director “may
    not serve more than one ten-year term”); 
    26 U.S.C. § 7803
    (a)(1)(B)
    (term of the IRS Commissioner “shall be a 5-year term”). But under
    Supreme Court precedent, those kinds of tenure provisions do not
    prevent the President from removing at will a Director at any time
    during the Director’s tenure. See Parsons v. United States, 
    167 U.S. 324
    , 343 (1897). Therefore, I would not invalidate and sever the
    tenure provision. If such a tenure provision did impair the
    President’s ability to remove the Director at will during the
    Director’s term, then it too would be unconstitutional, and also would
    have to be invalidated and severed.
    72
    executive agency, we should rewrite and add to the Dodd-
    Frank Act by restructuring the CFPB as a multi-member
    independent agency. But doing so would require us to create
    a variety of new offices, designate one of the offices as chair,
    and specify various administrative details of the reconstituted
    agency. In Free Enterprise Fund, the Supreme Court firmly
    rejected that approach. As the Supreme Court said, all of that
    “editorial freedom” would take courts far beyond our judicial
    capacity and proper judicial role. 
    561 U.S. at 510
    . In
    comparable circumstances, no Supreme Court case has adopted
    such an approach. We therefore may not do so here.
    Congress of course remains free, if it wishes, to reconstruct the
    CFPB as a traditional multi-member independent agency.
    In similar circumstances, the Supreme Court in Free
    Enterprise Fund severed the unconstitutional for-cause
    provision but did not otherwise disturb the Sarbanes-Oxley Act
    or the operation of the new Public Company Accounting
    Oversight Board created by that Act. See 
    id. at 508-10
    .
    Similarly, in a recent case involving the Copyright Royalty
    Board, we severed the for-cause provision that rendered that
    Board unconstitutional, but did not otherwise disturb the
    copyright laws or the operation of the Copyright Royalty
    Board. See Intercollegiate Broadcasting System, Inc. v.
    Copyright Royalty Board, 
    684 F.3d 1332
    , 1340-41 (D.C. Cir.
    2012).
    In light of the Dodd-Frank Act’s express severability
    clause, and because the Act and the CFPB may function
    without the CFPB’s for-cause removal provision, we must
    remedy the constitutional violation by severing the for-cause
    removal provision from the statute. Under that approach, the
    CFPB would continue to operate, but would do so as an
    executive agency. The President of the United States would
    73
    have the power to supervise and direct the Director of the
    CFPB, and to remove the Director at will at any time.
    ***
    The CFPB violates Article II of the Constitution because
    the CFPB is an independent agency that exercises substantial
    executive power and is headed by a single Director. We
    should invalidate and sever the for-cause removal provision
    and hold that the Director of the CFPB may be supervised,
    directed, and removed at will by the President. I respectfully
    dissent.
    RANDOLPH, Senior Circuit Judge, dissenting:
    I entirely agree with Judge Kavanaugh’s dissenting
    opinion.1 I write to identify a separate constitutional issue that
    provides an additional reason for setting aside not only the order
    of the Director of the Consumer Financial Protection Bureau,
    but also all proceedings before the CFPB’s Administrative Law
    Judge, including his Recommended Decision.
    After the CFPB’s enforcement unit filed a Notice of
    Charges against PHH, an Administrative Law Judge held a nine-
    day hearing and issued a recommended decision, concluding
    that petitioners had violated the Real Estate Settlement
    Procedures Act of 1974. In PHH’s administrative appeal, the
    Director “affirm[ed]” the ALJ’s conclusion that PHH had
    violated that Act.
    I believe the ALJ who presided over the hearing was an
    “inferior Officer” within the meaning of Article II, section 2,
    clause 2 of the Constitution. That constitutional provision
    requires “inferior Officers” to be appointed by the President, the
    “Courts of Law,” or the “Heads of Departments.” This ALJ was
    not so appointed. Pursuant to an agreement between the CFPB
    and the Securities and Exchange Commission, the SEC’s Chief
    Administrative Law Judge assigned him to the case. In addition
    to the unconstitutional structure of the CFPB, this violation of
    1
    I do not agree that “[i]n practical effect,” Judge Griffith’s
    “approach yields a result somewhat similar to Judge Kavanaugh’s
    proposed remedy.” Concurring Op. at 22 (Griffith, J.). There are
    substantial differences between the President’s power of removal “for
    cause” and the President’s power to remove an individual who has no
    such protection. One of the biggest is that non-“for cause” employees
    are not entitled due process before being removed from office, see Bd.
    of Regents of State Colleges v. Roth, 
    408 U.S. 564
    , 578 (1972), but
    “for cause” employees are so entitled. Experience under the Civil
    Service Reform Act of 1978 proves how time-consuming and
    cumbersome pre-removal due process procedures can be.
    2
    the Appointments Clause rendered the proceedings against PHH
    unconstitutional.
    This case is indistinguishable from Freytag v.
    Commissioner of Internal Revenue, 
    501 U.S. 868
     (1991). My
    reasoning is set forth in Landry v. Federal Deposit Insurance
    Corp., 
    204 F.3d 1125
    , 1140-44 (D.C. Cir. 2000) (Randolph, J.,
    concurring in part and concurring in the judgment). There is no
    need to repeat what I wrote there. The majority opinion in
    Landry disagreed with my position, but PHH has preserved the
    issue for judicial review. The CFPB has argued that PHH
    waived the issue because it did not raise it before the CFPB. But
    the Freytag petitioners also raised their constitutional objection
    to the appointment of the special trial judge for the first time on
    appeal. See Freytag, 
    501 U.S. at 892-95
     (Scalia, J., concurring).
    There is no difference between this case and Freytag, except
    that in light of the majority opinion in Landry it would have
    been futile for PHH to object, a point that cuts in PHH’s favor.
    Since the panel decision in this case, several developments
    have occurred with respect to the Appointments Clause issue.
    The Tenth Circuit in Bandimere v. SEC, 
    844 F.3d 1168
     (10th
    Cir. 2016), pet. for cert. pending, No. 17-475 (filed Sept. 29,
    2017), disagreed with the majority opinion in Landry and held
    that the SEC’s ALJs are invested with powers that require their
    appointment as inferior officers under the Appointments Clause.
    In addition, the Fifth Circuit granted a stay of an FDIC order
    because the respondent had established a likelihood of success
    on his claim that the ALJ who presided over his proceeding was
    an officer who was not properly appointed under the
    Appointments Clause. Burgess v. FDIC, 
    871 F.3d 297
     (5th Cir.
    2017). In so ruling, the Fifth Circuit also expressly disagreed
    with Landry.
    3
    In the meantime, our court, sitting en banc, split 5 to 5 in
    Lucia v. SEC, a case in which the panel – relying on Landry –
    had reached a conclusion in direct conflict with Bandimere.
    Raymond J. Lucia Cos. v. SEC, 
    868 F.3d 1021
     (D.C. Cir. 2017)
    (en banc). On June 26, 2017, the equally-divided en banc court
    issued a per curiam order denying the petition for review.
    On November 29, 2017, the Solicitor General, on behalf of
    the SEC, filed a response to Lucia’s certiorari petition. The
    Solicitor General confessed error and acquiesced in certiorari.
    That is, the S.G. agreed that the SEC’s ALJs are “inferior
    officers” within the meaning of the Appointments Clause and,
    as such, were not properly appointed. Brief for the Respondent
    at 10-19, Lucia v. SEC, No. 17-130 (filed Nov. 29, 2017). On
    January 12, 2018, the Supreme Court granted certiorari. 
    2018 WL 386565
     (S. Ct. Jan. 12, 2018).
    Given this state of affairs, the en banc majority should
    withhold any order remanding this case to the CFPB until the
    Supreme Court decides Lucia. Cf. Order, Timbervest, LLC v.
    SEC, No. 15-1416 (D.C. Cir. Aug. 8, 2017); Order, J.S. Oliver
    Capital Mgmt. v. SEC, No. 16-72703 (9th Cir. Oct. 25, 2017).
    As the Court held in Freytag, Appointments Clause violations
    go “to the validity” of the underlying proceedings. 501 U.S. at
    879. Suppose the Supreme Court agrees with the Solicitor
    General in Lucia, which seems entirely probable. Then not only
    the CFPB Director’s order, but also all proceedings before the
    ALJ, including the ALJ’s Recommended Decision, would be
    invalid.
    Nevertheless, the majority – relying on the order granting
    en banc in PHH – remands the case to the CFPB without
    waiting for the Supreme Court to decide Lucia. Maj. Op. at 17.
    The en banc order stated: “While not otherwise limited, the
    parties are directed to address” the consequences of a decision
    4
    that the ALJ in Lucia was an inferior officer. Order, PHH Corp.
    v. CFPB, No. 15-1177 (D.C. Cir. Feb. 16, 2017) (emphasis
    added).
    Two points about the order are worth noting. The first is
    that the order limited neither the issues to be argued nor the
    issues to be decided. The second is that the order embodied the
    en banc court’s judgment that the proper disposition of this case
    required consideration of the outcome in Lucia. Of course, the
    posture has changed. At the time of the en banc order, Lucia
    was pending in this court; now Lucia is pending in the Supreme
    Court. That difference makes it all the more important that we
    wait for the Supreme Court’s decision.
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 15-1177

Citation Numbers: 881 F.3d 75

Filed Date: 1/31/2018

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 1/12/2023

Authorities (123)

Holmes v. Osborn , 57 Ariz. 522 ( 1941 )

Securities and Exchange Commission v. Blinder, Robinson & ... , 855 F.2d 677 ( 1988 )

Mary E. Seebach v. Joseph M. Cullen, District Director, ... , 338 F.2d 663 ( 1964 )

clement-l-mceachern-v-john-w-macy-jr-chairman-the-united-states-civil , 341 F.2d 895 ( 1965 )

shawn-paul-humphries-v-jon-e-ozmint-director-south-carolina-department , 397 F.3d 206 ( 2005 )

American Federation of Government Employees, Afl-Cio, Local ... , 388 F.3d 405 ( 2004 )

Landry v. Federal Deposit Insurance Corp. , 204 F.3d 1125 ( 2000 )

Charles S. Thomas, Secretary of the Department of the Navy ... , 225 F.2d 953 ( 1955 )

Richard D. Meehan v. John W. MacY Jr., Chairman, Civil ... , 425 F.2d 472 ( 1969 )

Free Enterprise Fund v. Public Co. Accounting Oversight ... , 537 F.3d 667 ( 2008 )

Mountain States Legal Foundation v. Bush , 306 F.3d 1132 ( 2002 )

In Re Aiken County , 645 F.3d 428 ( 2011 )

Richard D. Meehan v. John W. MacY Jr., Chairman, Civil ... , 392 F.2d 822 ( 1968 )

G. S. Leonard v. John W. Douglas, Assistant Attorney ... , 321 F.2d 749 ( 1963 )

Richard D. Meehan v. John W. MacY Jr., Chairman, Civil ... , 425 F.2d 469 ( 1968 )

Jerry G. Brennan v. Department of Health and Human Services , 787 F.2d 1559 ( 1986 )

Federal Election Commission v. Nra Political Victory Fund , 6 F.3d 821 ( 1993 )

Long v. Social Security Administration , 635 F.3d 526 ( 2011 )

State, Ex Rel. v. Comm. , 147 Ohio St. 430 ( 1947 )

national-petroleum-refiners-association-v-federal-trade-commission , 482 F.2d 672 ( 1973 )

View All Authorities »