Beach v. State , 379 Mont. 74 ( 2015 )


Menu:
  •                                                                                            May 5 2015
    OP 14-0685
    Case Number: OP 14-0685
    IN THE SUPREME COURT OF THE STATE OF MONTANA
    
    2015 MT 118
                                       _________________
    BARRY ALLAN BEACH,
    Petitioner,
    OPINION
    v.                                                           AND
    ORDER
    STATE OF MONTANA,
    Respondent.
    _________________
    ¶1     Barry Allan Beach petitions for a writ of habeas corpus, arguing that his sentence
    of one hundred years of imprisonment without the possibility of parole is unconstitutional
    under Miller v. Alabama, 567 U.S. ___, 
    132 S. Ct. 2455
    (2012). The dispositive issue is
    whether Miller’s rule requiring a sentencing judge to consider a juvenile1 offender’s age
    when sentencing that offender to life without parole applies retroactively on collateral
    review. We conclude that it does not. We deny Beach’s petition.
    PROCEDURAL AND FACTUAL BACKGROUND
    ¶2     In 1984, a Roosevelt County jury convicted Beach of deliberate homicide for a
    crime committed in 1979, when Beach was seventeen. Under Montana’s sentencing
    scheme, the District Court could impose a maximum sentence of one hundred years’
    1
    In this opinion, “juvenile” refers to a person who committed a crime when under the age of
    eighteen.
    1
    imprisonment without the possibility of parole. See §§ 45-5-102(2), 46-18-202(2), -222,
    -305, MCA (1978).      On May 11, 1984, following its consideration of a written
    presentence investigation report and statements by both Beach and the prosecutor in open
    court, the District Court imposed the maximum sentence.        Beach concedes that the
    sentence was within the discretion of the District Court and that the sentence was not
    mandated by law. The record does not show that the court expressly considered Beach’s
    youth when imposing the sentence.
    ¶3    In the years since, Beach repeatedly has attacked his conviction and sentence. See
    Beach v. McCormick, No. 98-35957, 1999 U.S. App. Lexis 20999 (9th Cir.), cert. denied
    
    528 U.S. 1194
    , 
    120 S. Ct. 1255
    (2000); State v. Beach, 
    2013 MT 130
    , 
    370 Mont. 163
    ,
    
    302 P.3d 47
    ; Beach v. State, 
    2009 MT 398
    , 
    353 Mont. 411
    , 
    220 P.3d 667
    ; Beach v. Day,
    
    275 Mont. 370
    , 
    913 P.2d 622
    (1996); State v. Beach, 
    217 Mont. 132
    , 
    705 P.2d 94
    (1985).
    Beach now petitions for a writ of habeas corpus, attacking the constitutionality of his
    sentence under the United States Supreme Court’s recent decision in Miller.
    STANDARD OF REVIEW
    ¶4    This Court determines the retroactivity of a constitutional rule as a matter of law.
    State v. Reichmand, 
    2010 MT 228
    , ¶ 6, 
    358 Mont. 68
    , 
    243 P.3d 423
    .
    DISCUSSION
    I.
    ¶5    As an initial matter, the State urges that Beach’s habeas corpus petition is
    procedurally barred.
    2
    ¶6     Article II, Section 19 of the Montana Constitution provides, “The privilege of the
    writ of habeas corpus shall never be suspended.” Under Montana’s statutory scheme for
    reviewing claims by convicted offenders, habeas corpus is not the method for collaterally
    reviewing the conviction or sentence of a person who has been adjudged guilty of a crime
    and has exhausted direct appeal. Section 46-22-101(2), MCA. Rather, a petition for
    postconviction relief is the method by which an offender who has been found guilty may
    collaterally attack his conviction or sentence. Section 46-21-101(1), MCA. Petitions for
    postconviction remedies carry strict limitations. See § 46-21-102, MCA. In Lott v. State,
    
    2006 MT 279
    , 
    334 Mont. 270
    , 
    150 P.3d 337
    , we held that statutory limitations on the
    availability of the writ of habeas corpus are unconstitutional under Article II, Section 19
    of the Montana Constitution as applied to an offender sentenced to a “facially invalid
    sentence” where the facial invalidity stems from a rule created after time limits for
    directly appealing or petitioning for postconviction relief have expired. Lott, ¶ 22.
    ¶7     The State argues that Lott does not apply because Beach’s sentence is not facially
    invalid. Beach counters that the recent United States Supreme Court decision in Miller
    makes his sentence facially invalid. Miller requires following a certain procedure before
    sentencing a juvenile to life without the possibility of parole. Miller, 567 U.S. at ___,
    132 S. Ct. at 2471. Beach is imprisoned under a sentence that he argues equates to life
    without parole. Because Miller was not announced until 2012, Beach could not have
    raised a claim under that case until after time limits for direct review and postconviction
    relief had run. In these circumstances, we are satisfied that Beach’s claim sufficiently
    3
    calls into question the facial validity of his sentence to lift the statutory bar to a petition
    for habeas corpus relief.
    II.
    ¶8     The United States Constitution’s Eighth Amendment prohibits cruel and unusual
    punishment.     “The concept of proportionality is central to the Eighth Amendment.”
    Graham v. Florida, 
    560 U.S. 48
    , 59, 
    130 S. Ct. 2011
    , 2021 (2010). While in practice the
    concept of proportionality does not affect most sentences, see generally, Ewing v.
    California, 
    538 U.S. 11
    , 
    123 S. Ct. 1179
    (2003), proportionality bears on the harshest
    types of punishments when an Eighth Amendment challenge is raised.
    ¶9     Because of the concept of proportionality, the Eighth Amendment requires
    individualized sentencing in death penalty proceedings to determine whether that
    punishment corresponds to an offender’s character, circumstance, and crime. Lockett v.
    Ohio, 
    438 U.S. 586
    , 604, 
    98 S. Ct. 2954
    , 2964-65 (1978); Woodson v. North Carolina,
    
    428 U.S. 280
    , 303-05, 
    96 S. Ct. 2978
    , 2991-92 (1976).             Further, the death penalty
    categorically represents an unconstitutionally disproportionate punishment when imposed
    for certain crimes (like non-homicide offenses, Kennedy v. Louisiana, 
    554 U.S. 407
    , 438,
    
    128 S. Ct. 2641
    , 2660 (2008)), and on certain classes of offenders with lesser capacities
    (like intellectually disabled persons, Atkins v. Virginia, 
    536 U.S. 304
    , 321, 
    122 S. Ct. 2242
    , 2252 (2002), and juveniles, Roper v. Simmons, 
    543 U.S. 551
    , 575, 
    125 S. Ct. 1183
    ,
    1198 (2005)).
    4
    ¶10   The Supreme Court recently made clear that a sentence of life imprisonment
    without the possibility of release, though not the harshest punishment for an adult
    offender, is subject to more exacting scrutiny when imposed on a juvenile. In Graham,
    the Supreme Court held that life without parole represents a categorically
    disproportionate sentence for a juvenile convicted of a non-homicide offense. 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 75
    , 130 S. Ct. at 2030.          Next, in Miller, the Court considered the
    proportionality of life without parole imposed on a juvenile for a homicide offense. The
    Miller Court declined to address whether the Eighth Amendment categorically bars a life
    without parole sentence imposed on a juvenile convicted of homicide. Miller, 567 U.S. at
    ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2469. The Court instead specified that appropriate circumstances to
    impose such a sentence are “uncommon.” Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2469.
    To ensure that imposing life without parole on a juvenile homicide offender is
    proportional, the Eighth Amendment requires that, before imposing such a sentence, a
    sentencer “take into account how children are different, and how those differences
    counsel against irrevocably sentencing them to a lifetime in prison.” Miller, 567 U.S. at
    ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2469. Accordingly, the Eighth Amendment “forbids a sentencing
    scheme that mandates life in prison without possibility of parole for juvenile offenders”
    because such a scheme prevents a sentencer from taking into account constitutionally
    necessary considerations. Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2469.
    ¶11   Beach argues that his sentence equates to life without parole. Beach concedes that
    Miller’s holding forbidding mandatory life without parole sentences does not apply to his
    5
    case because his sentence was not mandatory. Both at the time of Beach’s offense and
    now, Montana sentencing statutes have prescribed an individualized sentencing
    procedure that allows the sentencing court, after considering all circumstances of the
    offender and the offense, to fashion a sentence within the range provided by the statute
    under which the offender was convicted.             See §§ 46-18-101, -201, MCA (1978);
    §§ 46-18-101, -201, MCA (2013).           Nevertheless, Beach argues that his sentence is
    unconstitutional under Miller because his sentencer did not consider how Beach’s age
    counseled against his sentence.2
    ¶12    Beach’s conviction and sentence became final for purposes of direct review in
    1985. Miller was announced in 2012. Beach may benefit from Miller only if Miller
    creates a rule that applies to a sentence imposed years before Miller was issued.
    III.
    A.
    ¶13    Beginning with Linkletter v. Walker, 
    381 U.S. 618
    , 
    85 S. Ct. 1731
    (1965), the
    United States Supreme Court struggled for over two decades with how and when to apply
    constitutional rules retroactively in criminal cases.        Justice Harlan was the most
    influential critic of the Court’s retroactivity approach during this period. In dissents in
    Mackey v. United States, 
    401 U.S. 667
    , 
    91 S. Ct. 1160
    (1971), and Desist v. United
    States, 
    394 U.S. 244
    , 
    89 S. Ct. 1030
    (1969), Justice Harlan devised an alternative
    approach for determining retroactivity.
    2
    In this opinion, we assume without deciding that Beach was sentenced to the equivalent of life
    without parole.
    6
    ¶14    The distinction between direct and collateral review represents the central feature
    of Justice Harlan’s framework. Justice Harlan believed that the judicial function requires
    applying all rules of constitutional law to cases yet to be tried and on direct review.
    
    Mackey, 401 U.S. at 681
    .3 But Justice Harlan also believed that new rules generally
    should not apply retroactively to offenders on collateral review because of the interest in
    finality that attaches once direct review ends, administrative costs associated with retrial
    years after the fact, and the historic functions of habeas corpus.4 
    Mackey, 401 U.S. at 689-92
    .     Justice Harlan conceived of two exceptions to the general rule of
    non-retroactivity on collateral review. The first exception is for new substantive rules
    that place “certain kinds of primary, private individual conduct beyond the power of the
    criminal law-making authority to proscribe.” 
    Mackey, 401 U.S. at 692
    . Justice Harlan
    reasoned that substantive rules lessen the interest in finality because “[t]here is little
    3
    Justice Harlan’s dissent in Mackey was never printed in the Supreme Court Reporter. We cite
    only to where it appears in the United States Reports.
    4
    In Montana, direct review occurs when an offender is convicted by a state court and, in the
    months following that conviction, appeals her decision to the Montana Supreme Court and (if
    federal issues are involved) seeks appeal with the United States Supreme Court. Under Justice
    Harlan’s framework, a rule announced by the United States Supreme Court will benefit an
    offender while her claim is still pending on direct review. After an offender exhausts direct
    review, her claim becomes final, and she thereafter may seek only collateral review. Collateral
    review has two stages. In the first stage, the offender may petition Montana courts, including
    this Court, for collateral review (usually styled as a petition for postconviction relief, but
    sometimes, as in this case, styled as a petition for a writ of habeas corpus), and may appeal this
    Court’s decision on federal issues to the United States Supreme Court. In the second collateral
    review stage, the offender may seek federal habeas corpus review on federal issues from a
    federal district court, a federal court of appeals, and the United States Supreme Court. Under
    Justice Harlan’s framework, a new rule announced after an offender’s conviction has become
    final—when only collateral review remains—generally will not apply retroactively to benefit an
    offender.
    7
    societal interest in permitting the criminal process to rest at a point where it ought
    properly never to repose.” 
    Mackey, 401 U.S. at 693
    . Moreover, because conduct that is
    no longer punishable cannot be retried, overturning a conviction based on a substantive
    rule does not tax the state through requiring another trial. Substantive rules also echo the
    historic availability of habeas corpus to attack a court’s jurisdiction to imprison a person.
    
    Mackey, 401 U.S. at 692
    -93.
    ¶15    Justice Harlan’s second exception encapsulates procedural rules that are “implicit
    in the concept of ordered liberty” and “alter our understanding of the bedrock procedural
    elements” necessary to the fairness and accuracy of a conviction. 
    Mackey, 401 U.S. at 693
    (citation omitted); 
    Desist, 394 U.S. at 262
    , 89 S. Ct. at 1041. Justice Harlan offered
    the rule from Gideon v. Wainwright, 
    372 U.S. 335
    , 345, 
    83 S. Ct. 792
    , 806 (1963)
    (requiring that an indigent defendant be provided counsel), as an example of a rule
    satisfying this exception. 
    Mackey, 401 U.S. at 694
    .
    ¶16    In Griffith v. Kentucky, 
    479 U.S. 314
    , 
    107 S. Ct. 708
    (1987), the United States
    Supreme Court adopted the first leg of Justice Harlan’s framework, stating that any
    newly-announced constitutional rule will apply to cases still pending on direct review.
    
    Griffith, 479 U.S. at 328
    , 107 S. Ct. at 716. Then, in Teague v. Lane, 
    489 U.S. 288
    , 
    109 S. Ct. 1060
    (1989), a plurality of the Court adopted the remainder of Justice Harlan’s
    framework, holding that new rules generally will not apply retroactively to cases on
    collateral review. 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 310
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1075. A rule is new when “not
    dictated by precedent existing at the time the . . . conviction became final.” Teague, 
    489 8 U.S. at 301
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1070 (emphasis in original). Echoing Justice Harlan, after
    Teague, “[a] new rule applies retroactively in a collateral proceeding only if (1) the rule is
    substantive or (2) the rule is a watershed rul[e] of criminal procedure implicating the
    fundamental fairness and accuracy of the criminal proceeding.” Whorton v. Bockting,
    
    549 U.S. 406
    , 416, 
    127 S. Ct. 1173
    , 1180 (2007) (internal quotation marks and citations
    omitted).5
    ¶17    Although this framework originally focused on the retroactivity of rules used to
    attack convictions, the Supreme Court has refined the framework in cases attacking
    sentences. In Penry v. Lynaugh, 
    492 U.S. 302
    , 
    109 S. Ct. 2934
    (1989), Penry argued on
    collateral review that the Eighth Amendment prohibits imposing the death penalty on an
    intellectually disabled person. 
    Penry, 492 U.S. at 328
    , 109 S. Ct. at 2952. Before
    reaching the merits of that claim, the Court conducted the Teague retroactivity analysis.
    The Court noted that Justice Harlan’s description of a substantive rule—one that places
    “certain kinds of primary, private individual conduct beyond the power of the criminal
    law-making authority to proscribe”—is phrased in terms of “substantive categorical
    guarantees accorded by the Constitution, regardless of the procedures followed.” 
    Penry, 492 U.S. at 329
    , 109 S. Ct. at 2952 (emphasis added). Because, in the context of
    sentencing, rules that “deprive[ ] the State of the power to impose a certain penalty” or
    5
    We recognize that courts (including this Court and the United States Supreme Court) have
    struggled with whether a substantive rule is an exception to the general rule of non-retroactivity,
    or whether the general rule of non-retroactivity simply does not apply to substantive rules. See
    Schriro v. Summerlin, 
    542 U.S. 348
    , 351 n.4, 
    124 S. Ct. 2519
    , 2523 n.4 (2004); State v.
    Whitehorn, 
    2002 MT 54
    , ¶ 37, 
    309 Mont. 63
    , 
    43 P.3d 922
    (2002). We think this a distinction
    without significance. In this opinion, we refer to substantive rules as exceptions to the general
    rule of non-retroactivity.
    9
    prohibit a “certain category of punishment for a class of defendants because of their
    status or offense” also are categorical guarantees, the Court determined that these types of
    sentencing rules are substantive. 
    Penry, 492 U.S. at 329
    -30, 109 S. Ct. at 2952-53. The
    Court accordingly concluded that Penry’s claim called for a substantive rule not subject
    to the general rule of non-retroactivity. 
    Penry, 492 U.S. at 330
    , 109 S. Ct. at 2953.
    ¶18    By contrast, the Court has held that sentencing rules that do not “prohibit the
    imposition of [a particular sentence] on a particular class of persons” are not substantive.
    Saffle v. Parks, 
    494 U.S. 484
    , 495, 
    110 S. Ct. 1257
    , 1263-64 (1990) (concluding that a
    prohibition against instructing a death penalty jury to avoid sympathy when determining
    punishment is not a substantive rule). See also Sawyer v. Smith, 
    497 U.S. 227
    , 242, 
    110 S. Ct. 2822
    , 2831 (1990) (concluding that the substantive rule exception “has no
    application” to a new rule prohibiting the imposition of capital punishment by a jury that
    has been led to believe that the ultimate decision to impose the death penalty rests
    elsewhere).
    ¶19    The United States Supreme Court further clarified the scope of the exceptions to
    the general rule of non-retroactivity for sentencing rules in Schriro v. Summerlin, 
    542 U.S. 348
    , 
    124 S. Ct. 2519
    (2004). The offender in that case sought to benefit from the
    rule announced in Ring v. Arizona, 
    536 U.S. 584
    , 
    122 S. Ct. 2428
    (2002), requiring that a
    jury rather than a judge find aggravating factors necessary to impose a death sentence.
    
    Schriro, 542 U.S. at 351
    , 122 S. Ct. at 2522. The Schriro Court stated, “A rule is
    substantive rather than procedural if it alters the range of conduct or the class of persons
    10
    that the law punishes. . . . In contrast, rules that regulate only the manner of determining
    the defendant’s culpability are procedural.” 
    Schriro, 542 U.S. at 353
    , 124 S. Ct. at 2523
    (emphasis in original). Substantive sentencing rules that “place particular conduct or
    persons covered by the statute beyond the state’s power to punish” are retroactive
    because they “necessarily carry a significant risk” that the offender “faces a punishment
    that the law cannot impose upon him.” 
    Schriro, 542 U.S. at 352
    , 124 S. Ct. at 2522-23
    (internal quotation marks and citation omitted). The Court concluded that the Ring rule
    was not substantive because “the range of conduct punished by death . . . was the same
    before Ring as after.” 
    Schriro, 542 U.S. at 354
    , 124 S. Ct. at 2524.
    ¶20    The Court instead determined that the Ring rule was procedural because it “altered
    the range of permissible methods for determining whether a defendant’s conduct is
    punishable by death.” 
    Schriro, 542 U.S. at 353
    , 124 S. Ct. at 2523. The Court held that
    the Ring rule was not a watershed procedural rule, however, because it did not create an
    “impermissibly large risk” of inaccuracy. 
    Schriro, 542 U.S. at 356
    , 124 S. Ct. at 2525
    (citations omitted).   The Schriro Court’s determination that the Ring rule was not
    watershed is consistent with its application of that exception. Since adopting Justice
    Harlan’s framework in 1989, the Supreme Court has never concluded that a new rule fits
    into the watershed procedural rule exception, and has stated that it is “unlikely” it ever
    will. 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 313
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1077. During that time, the Supreme Court
    has provided only one example of a rule that meets the watershed procedural rule
    exception—the rule announced in Gideon.
    11
    B.
    ¶21   The Montana Supreme Court has applied the federal retroactivity framework since
    State v. Egelhoff, 
    272 Mont. 114
    , 125-27, 
    900 P.2d 260
    , 267 (1995). For example, in
    State v. Whitehorn, 
    2002 MT 54
    , 
    309 Mont. 63
    , 
    50 P.3d 121
    , we examined the
    retroactivity of the rule we announced in State v. Guillaume, 
    1999 MT 29
    , 
    293 Mont. 224
    , 
    975 P.2d 312
    .
    ¶22   Guillaume held that applying a weapons enhancement statute on top of an offense
    that already includes use of a weapon in the elements of the offense is unconstitutional
    under Montana’s double jeopardy clause.           Guillaume, ¶ 16.   In Whitehorn, after
    surveying the federal retroactivity framework, we held that Guillaume was retroactive
    because it created a substantive rule: the rule prohibited imposition of a certain
    punishment (an additional punishment for use of a weapon) on a particular class of
    offenders (offenders who already had been punished for the same conduct). Whitehorn,
    ¶¶ 36-42.
    ¶23   This Court’s Egelhoff decision appears to have assumed that the United States
    Constitution requires state courts to apply the federal retroactivity framework.       See
    
    Egelhoff, 272 Mont. at 125
    , 900 P.2d at 267 (“With regard to the question of retroactivity,
    the United States Supreme Court has additionally made its position more clear and we
    find this also to be binding upon us.”). In Danforth v. Minnesota, 
    552 U.S. 264
    , 
    128 S. Ct. 1029
    (2008), the United States Supreme Court clarified that its retroactivity
    analysis need not be followed by state courts. 
    Danforth, 552 U.S. at 280-81
    , 128 S. Ct. at
    12
    1041. Danforth noted that Egelhoff placed this Court among three state high courts that
    incorrectly concluded that states must apply the federal retroactivity framework.
    
    Danforth, 552 U.S. at 281
    n.17, 128 S. Ct. at 1042 
    n.17. Nonetheless, we have continued
    to apply the federal framework in the years since Danforth. In Reichmand, 
    2010 MT 228
    , 
    358 Mont. 68
    , 
    243 P.3d 423
    , we recognized this Court’s “right to craft its own
    unique retroactivity jurisprudence, using federal requirements as a floor,” before
    employing the Griffith principle that rules are retroactive on direct review to address a
    claim under a state constitutional right.6 Reichmand, ¶¶ 13-15. Just recently, in State v.
    Cook, 
    2012 MT 34
    , 
    364 Mont. 161
    , 
    272 P.3d 50
    , we recognized the distinction between
    substantive and procedural rules for purposes of determining retroactivity on collateral
    review. Cook, ¶ 17. We applied the federal framework to determine that the rule the
    petitioner invoked was not retroactive because, although it was new and procedural, it
    was not watershed. Cook, ¶¶ 17-19.
    ¶24    Against this backdrop of faithful application, Beach has not made a principled
    argument for departing from the United States Supreme Court’s retroactivity framework
    to resolve his petition. In both his briefs and in oral argument, Beach focused on showing
    that Miller is retroactive under the federal retroactivity framework. Beach’s briefing on
    applying a state-specific retroactivity standard is scant, and his oral argument raised the
    6
    Reichmand also suggested that “the U.S. Supreme Court’s retroactivity analysis for federal
    constitutional errors is binding upon the states when federal constitutional errors are involved.”
    Reichmand, ¶ 13 (emphasis in original). This statement is correct to the extent that it means that
    the federal doctrine effectively sets the floor for the retroactivity of federal rights in Montana.
    But this statement should not be taken to mean that this Court cannot provide greater
    retroactivity to federal rights than permitted under the federal standard—under Danforth, we are
    not required to employ the federal retroactivity analysis for either federal or state rights.
    13
    possibility of a different standard only briefly, in rebuttal to the State’s argument. In
    neither his briefs nor in oral argument did Beach specify what standard we should apply
    if not the retroactivity standard we have applied in previous cases.
    ¶25    In the limited argument Beach has developed on departing from the retroactivity
    framework, he has suggested that Miller should be applied retroactively to his case
    because Miller implicates fundamental rights found in Article II, Sections 15 and 22 of
    the Montana Constitution. Beach also recounts Whitehorn’s comment that “it is illogical
    for this Court to refuse to extend constitutional protections to citizens simply because
    their claims are raised by collateral review rather than by way of direct appeal.”
    Whitehorn, ¶ 42.     He fails to note, however, the very next line in that opinion:
    “Accordingly, we conclude that . . . this Court erred in failing to recognize and apply the
    foregoing case law that distinguishes a procedural rule from a substantive rule when
    addressing retroactivity.” Whitehorn, ¶ 42 (emphasis added). In Whitehorn, we applied
    the federal retroactivity framework, recognizing the illogic of not applying substantive
    rules retroactively when that would permit “the criminal process to rest at a point where it
    ought properly never to repose.” 
    Mackey, 401 U.S. at 693
    (Harlan, J., dissenting).
    ¶26    Beach has failed to explain why the cited provisions of the Montana Constitution
    require a different retroactivity model for Miller. See State v. Covington, 
    2012 MT 31
    ,
    ¶ 21, 
    364 Mont. 118
    , 
    272 P.3d 43
    . Beach has further failed to address why Miller
    requires retroactive application in light of the interests that collateral review affects and
    the purposes that it serves. We are not obligated to develop legal analysis that may lend
    14
    support to an appellant’s arguments. In re Estate of Bayers, 
    1999 MT 154
    , ¶ 19, 
    295 Mont. 89
    , 
    983 P.2d 339
    (1999).
    ¶27    Two of today’s dissenting opinions develop their own legal analyses, each
    proffering a new path for determining retroactivity not advanced by Beach. Justice
    Wheat offers an ad hoc approach, suggesting that the Court simply compare the interests
    of fairness and finality to determine the retroactivity of the rule invoked in this case.
    Dissent, ¶ 60. But his Dissent does not offer a measure by which to compare these
    interests. Nor does it acknowledge the aspects of fairness that the interest in finality
    subsumes—stability in the law, timely resolution of disputes, and closure for everyone
    involved in a case, including victims. Dissent, ¶¶ 63-65; see 
    Mackey, 401 U.S. at 691
    (Harlan, J., dissenting) (“No one, not criminal defendants, not the judicial system, not
    society as a whole is benefited by a judgment providing a man shall tentatively go to jail
    today, but tomorrow and every day thereafter his continued incarceration shall be subject
    to fresh litigation on issues already resolved.”).    The logical conclusion of Justice
    Wheat’s approach is that a conviction would never be final in this state until a reviewing
    court deems it “fair” to so declare.
    ¶28    Meanwhile, Justice Shea would embark on a novel state-specific approach to
    retroactivity by overruling several prior decisions of this Court. He posits that those
    decisions perpetuated Egelhoff’s mistaken assumption that we are bound to apply the
    federal retroactivity framework. Dissent, ¶ 97. Justice Shea faults the Court’s analysis in
    Reichmand, but overlooks our express, and correct, observation in that case that Danforth
    15
    permits this Court to adopt any retroactivity standard with regard to state constitutional
    rights. Reichmand, ¶ 13. In Reichmand, we examined the retroactivity of a new rule
    affecting a state constitutional right. Reichmand, ¶ 2. After acknowledging our ability to
    choose any standard, we applied the federal retroactivity framework to that state right.
    Reichmand, ¶ 15. We did likewise in Cook, where we reaffirmed that “[r]etroactive
    application is needed in situations that ‘necessarily carry a significant risk that a
    defendant stands convicted of an act that the law does not make criminal’ or faces a
    punishment that the law cannot impose upon him.” Cook, ¶ 17 (quoting 
    Schriro, 542 U.S. at 351
    , 124 S. Ct. at 2522-23). It cannot be said that the Court did not “voluntarily”
    make the federal retroactivity framework its own in these two cases. Dissent, ¶ 100.7
    ¶29    Most importantly, Justices Wheat and Shea’s respective theories could have been,
    but were not, argued by Beach. As a result, this Court has not had the benefit of the
    State’s position on the approaches that Justices Wheat and Shea would have us adopt.
    Under this Court’s policy of stare decisis, we keep faith with precedent “unless it is
    demonstrably made to appear that” our precedent “manifestly is wrong.” State ex rel.
    Perry v. Dist. Ct., 
    145 Mont. 287
    , 310, 
    400 P.2d 648
    , 660 (1965) (citation omitted). The
    burden of this demonstration is on the party seeking to overturn the precedent. See In re
    McCabe, 
    168 Mont. 334
    , 337, 
    544 P.2d 825
    , 827 (1975) (noting the petitioner’s failure to
    7
    The Dissent’s reference to State v. Maine, 
    2011 MT 90
    , 
    360 Mont. 182
    , 
    255 P.3d 64
    , does not
    bolster its analysis. Our decision in Maine was supported by precedent going back decades.
    Maine, ¶ 45 (Baker, J., concurring). In this case, our precedent, reaffirmed most recently in
    Reichmand and Cook, dictates a result in conflict with what Justice Shea proposes. In addition,
    Maine addressed arguments squarely presented and briefed by the parties. Maine, ¶ 27.
    16
    “demonstrate any sufficient reason for this Court to overturn” its prior construction); see
    also U.S. v. Int’l Bus. Mach. Corp., 
    517 U.S. 843
    , 856, 
    116 S. Ct. 1793
    , 1801 (1996)
    (“Though from time to time we have overruled governing decisions that are unworkable
    or are badly reasoned, we have rarely done so on grounds not advanced by the parties.”)
    (internal citations and quotations omitted).        Beach has not met his burden to so
    demonstrate, and it would be unwise for this Court to depart from long-settled precedent
    to apply an analysis that has not been developed or tested by the parties to the case. The
    Court accordingly will apply the same retroactivity framework in this case that it has
    applied to every previous collateral review case since Teague was decided.
    IV.
    A.
    ¶30    Before getting to the retroactivity of the rule Beach invokes, we must first
    establish that he, in fact, invokes a new rule. Beach argues that, under Miller, a sentencer
    must consider a juvenile’s youth before sentencing that juvenile to life without parole.
    The State responds that Miller does not establish this rule. Instead, the State argues,
    Miller merely bars the mandatory imposition of a life without parole sentence on a
    juvenile.    The State suggests that Miller’s language about required sentencing
    considerations is dicta.
    ¶31    Dictum is “[a]n opinion by a court . . . that is not essential to the decision and
    therefore not binding even if it may later be accorded some weight.” Black’s Law
    Dictionary 549 (Bryan A. Garner ed., 10th ed. 2009). Miller’s statements about required
    17
    sentencing considerations are not dicta. The Miller Court held that mandatory imposition
    of a life sentence is unconstitutional because a mandatory scheme prevents a sentencer
    from considering how a juvenile’s youth affects the proportionality of that sentence, and
    the Eighth Amendment requires a sentencer to so consider. The Supreme Court could not
    have been clearer when it said, “Although we do not foreclose a sentencer’s ability to
    [impose life without parole] in homicide cases, we require it to take into account how
    children are different, and how those differences counsel against irrevocably sentencing
    them to a lifetime in prison.” Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2469.
    ¶32    We think it clear that Miller establishes two rules. First, sentencing schemes that
    mandate life incarceration without the possibility of parole for juvenile offenders are
    unconstitutional. Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2469. Second, a sentencer must
    “follow a certain process” before imposing a life without parole sentence on a juvenile.
    Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2471. Beach invokes the second rule.
    ¶33    Under the retroactivity framework, new rules are treated differently from old rules.
    See 
    Penry, 492 U.S. at 319
    , 109 S. Ct. at 2947. An offender on collateral review
    generally cannot benefit from a new rule, whereas she can benefit from an old rule.
    
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 310
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1075. A rule is new unless dictated by precedent
    existing at the time the offender’s conviction became final. Teague, 489 U.S. at 
    301, 109 S. Ct. at 1070
    .
    ¶34    Beach has omitted argument on this point, seemingly conceding the novelty of
    Miller’s sentencing consideration rule. Indeed, Miller rests on the twin recognitions that
    18
    (1) children are different for sentencing purposes, and (2) life sentences without the
    possibility of parole are similar to death sentences when imposed on juveniles. See
    Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2463-66.         The Supreme Court did not fully
    recognize these principles until Roper in 2005 and Graham in 2010. Beach’s conviction
    became final in 1985. Although the case law existing in 1985 may have foreshadowed
    Miller’s sentencing consideration rule, see Eddings v. Oklahoma, 
    455 U.S. 104
    , 115, 
    102 S. Ct. 869
    , 877 (1982), these cases certainly did not dictate or compel such a rule. We
    conclude that Miller’s sentencing consideration rule is a new rule, subject to the general
    rule of non-retroactivity on collateral review.
    B.
    ¶35    A new rule is not retroactive on collateral review unless it is a substantive rule or a
    watershed procedural rule. 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 310
    -11, 109 S. Ct. at 1075-76. Since
    2012, many state and lower federal courts have wrestled with Miller’s retroactivity.
    These courts appear to agree that Miller creates a new rule subject to the general rule of
    non-retroactivity. See, e.g., In re Morgan, 
    713 F.3d 1365
    , 1366-67 (11th Cir. 2013);
    Diatchenko v. Dist. Atty. for Suffolk Dist., 
    466 Mass. 655
    , 667 (2013). The courts
    diverge, however, on whether Miller fits into one of the exceptions to the general rule.
    Courts that have held Miller retroactive generally conceive of Miller as creating a
    substantive rule. See, e.g., Illinois v. Davis, 
    6 N.E.3d 709
    , 722 (Ill. 2014); Iowa v.
    Ragland, 
    836 N.W.2d 107
    , 117 (Iowa 2013). By contrast, courts that have held Miller
    non-retroactive generally conceive of Miller as creating a procedural rule, but not a
    19
    watershed procedural rule. See, e.g., Michigan v. Carp, 
    496 Mich. 440
    , 495 (2014);
    Pennsylvania v. Cunningham, 
    81 A.3d 1
    , 26-29 (Pa. 2013).
    ¶36    Most of these courts have been concerned with whether Miller’s prohibition on
    mandatory life without parole sentences is retroactive.8 See, e.g., 
    Davis, 6 N.E.3d at 723
    ;
    
    Carp, 496 Mich. at 483
    n.13. But see Aiken v. Byars, 
    410 S.C. 534
    , 543-44 (2014).
    Because Miller’s mandatory sentencing rule has no application in Montana, the ensuing
    analysis does not concern—at least directly—the retroactivity of that rule. We focus
    instead on the retroactivity of Miller’s rule requiring consideration of a juvenile
    offender’s youth before imposing a life without parole sentence.
    ¶37    Beach includes only one sentence in his brief suggesting that Miller’s sentencing
    consideration rule may represent a watershed procedural rule. Beach instead has focused
    his retroactivity argument on showing that the Miller rule is substantive. The strategy
    makes sense considering that the United States Supreme Court effectively has interpreted
    the watershed procedural rule exception as a “null set.”              R. Fallon, J. Manning,
    D. Meltzer, & D. Shapiro, Hart and Wechsler’s The Federal Courts and the Federal
    System 1246 (6th ed. 2009); see also Sepulveda v. United States, 
    330 F.3d 55
    , 61 (1st Cir.
    2003) (watershed procedural rules under the federal retroactivity framework are
    “hen’s-teeth rare”).     The Supreme Court continuously has equated the watershed
    procedural rule exception with Gideon and Gideon alone. In this context, we cannot say
    that Miller’s rule is a watershed procedural rule.         Montana always has permitted a
    8
    It stands to reason that jurisdictions that at one time mandated juvenile life without parole
    sentences have more offenders who stand to benefit from Miller and to litigate its retroactivity.
    20
    sentencer to consider a juvenile offender’s youth when sentencing that offender to a term
    of years with no possibility of parole. Miller’s rule merely goes a step further by
    requiring that consideration. The rule’s effect on the fairness and accuracy of a criminal
    proceeding is not on par with Gideon. Accordingly, Miller’s sentencing consideration
    rule is not a watershed procedural rule.
    ¶38    Justice Cotter agrees with Beach that Miller announced a new substantive rule.
    Dissent, ¶ 115. A substantive sentencing rule is a rule that “prohibit[s] a certain category
    of punishment for a class of defendants because of their status or offense.” 
    Penry, 492 U.S. at 330
    , 109 S. Ct. at 2953. In other words, a substantive sentencing rule is a
    “categorical guarantee[] accorded by the Constitution, regardless of the procedures
    followed,” 
    Penry, 492 U.S. at 329
    , 109 S. Ct. at 2952, that “place[s] particular conduct or
    persons covered by the statute beyond the state’s power” to subject to a particular
    punishment, 
    Schriro, 542 U.S. at 352
    , 124 S. Ct. at 2522-23. In Miller, the Supreme
    Court specifically stated that it did “not categorically bar a penalty for a class of
    offenders or type of crime,” and instead mandated “only that a sentencer follow a certain
    process . . . before imposing” life without parole on a juvenile. Miller, 367 U.S. at ___,
    132 S. Ct. at 2471 (emphases added). Miller did not hold that juvenile life without parole
    sentences are categorically unconstitutional. Miller, 367 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2469.
    Miller “dictated what process must take place before a life-without parole sentence could
    be imposed, [but] it did not prohibit a state from imposing that penalty on a certain class
    21
    of offenders.” 7 W. Lafave, J. Israel, N. King, & O. Kerr, Criminal Procedure § 28.6(e)
    (3rd ed. 2007, 2014-2015 supplement).
    ¶39    Beach’s own summary of Miller defeats his suggestion that Miller is substantive.
    “Miller,” he explains, “prohibits a particular punishment (life-without-parole) for a class
    of defendants (juveniles) unless specific youth related factors are first considered.”
    (Emphasis added.)      In other words, under Miller, a sentencing court retains the
    constitutional authority to sentence a juvenile to life without parole. If Beach’s case were
    remanded for sentencing, a sentencing judge, upon following Miller’s sentencing
    consideration rule, could resentence Beach to the exact same sentence he received before.
    This differs from a substantive rule. For instance, regardless of the procedures followed,
    a sentencer after Graham could not resentence a juvenile non-homicide offender to life
    without parole; a sentencer after Roper could not resentence a juvenile to the death
    penalty; a sentencer after Atkins could not resentence an intellectually disabled offender
    to the death penalty; and a sentencer after Kennedy could not resentence a non-homicide
    offender to the death penalty. Because Miller’s sentencing consideration rule “regulates
    only the manner of determining” a sentence by requiring a certain process, and does not
    alter the range of punishment that Beach could receive, 
    Schriro, 542 U.S. at 353
    , 124
    S. Ct. at 2523, it is procedural and not substantive.9
    ¶40    Beach seeks to forestall this conclusion by reframing the required considerations
    under Miller as “elements” of a life without parole sentence imposed on a juvenile. The
    9
    Justice Wheat’s Dissent appears to agree, Dissent, ¶ 54, and Justice Shea’s Dissent does not
    appear to take issue with this analysis.
    22
    case on which Justice Cotter relies, Dissent ¶¶ 118-20, sounds a similar theme. See In re
    Willover, No. HO40757, 2015 Cal. App. LEXIS 322, *20-21 (stating that Miller created
    “a rule that sets forth the specific considerations to be made during a sentencing decision”
    of a juvenile homicide offender). An element is a certain fact that is essential to an
    offense or punishment. See Alleyne v. United States, 570 U.S. ___, ___, 
    133 S. Ct. 2151
    ,
    2155 (2013). By its terms, Miller requires only that a sentencer consider certain factors;
    it does not make the finding of “certain fact[s] essential” to a life without parole sentence.
    
    Schriro, 542 U.S. at 354
    , 124 S. Ct. at 2524.
    ¶41    The logical conclusion to Beach’s elements argument is that any new rule that
    conditions the imposition of a particular sentence on a particular procedure would be
    considered substantive. But that does not comport with cases holding such rules to be
    procedural only. See Beard v. Banks, 
    542 U.S. 406
    , 420, 
    124 S. Ct. 2504
    , 2515 (2006)
    (finding non-retroactive a rule prohibiting imposition of the death penalty by jury unless
    the jury can consider all mitigating factors); 
    Schriro, 542 U.S. at 354
    , 124 S. Ct. at 2524
    (concluding that a rule prohibiting imposition of the death penalty unless elements of that
    sentence are found by a jury is procedural and not substantive); Sawyer v. 
    Smith, 497 U.S. at 242
    , 110 S. Ct. at 2831 (finding non-substantive a rule that prohibits the
    imposition of the death penalty by a sentencer under the mistaken belief that
    responsibility for determining the propriety of the death penalty rests elsewhere). In all
    of these cases, just as in Beach’s case, the examined rules did not “prohibit[ ] a certain
    category of punishment for a class of defendants because of their status or offense,”
    23
    
    Penry, 492 U.S. at 330
    , 109 S. Ct. at 2953—the rules instead prohibited a certain
    category of punishment unless the sentencer followed a prescribed process.               This
    demonstrates a significant difference from the Willover case. The court in Willover
    determined that, “Because petitioner was sentenced at a time when the prevailing case
    law required a presumption of [life without parole], there is a ‘significant risk’ that
    petitioner ‘faces a punishment that the law cannot impose upon him.’” In re Willover,
    2015 Cal. App. LEXIS 322 at *21. No such presumption existed in Montana law at the
    time Beach was sentenced.
    ¶42    Finally, if the Miller considerations are elements of a life without parole sentence,
    Beach does not explain how his proposed solution to the constitutional infirmity of his
    sentence—resentencing by a judge who must consider these elements—is any more
    constitutional than his original sentence, considering that all elements necessary to raise
    the maximum allowable sentence for a crime must be found by a jury, not by a judge.
    See Apprendi v. New Jersey, 
    530 U.S. 466
    , 476, 
    120 S. Ct. 2348
    , 2355 (2000).
    C.
    ¶43    Beach makes three more arguments, all of which may bear on the Miller rule’s
    retroactivity in general, but do not bear directly on whether the Miller rule fits into one of
    the retroactivity framework’s exceptions.
    ¶44    First, Beach notes that the companion case in Miller was Jackson v. Hobbs, an
    appeal by a prisoner on collateral review. Because Jackson benefitted from Miller, and
    24
    Beach is similarly situated to Jackson on collateral review, Beach argues that fairness
    dictates that he too should benefit from Miller’s rule.
    ¶45    Retroactivity, however, is an affirmative defense to be raised by the government.
    “[A] federal court may, but need not, decline to apply [the retroactivity framework] if the
    [s]tate does not argue it.” Caspari v. Bohlen, 
    510 U.S. 383
    , 389, 
    114 S. Ct. 948
    , 953
    (1994). Arkansas (the state responding to Jackson’s petition for habeas corpus) did not
    argue to the Supreme Court that the rule Jackson sought was non-retroactive.10 Given
    this omission, the Supreme Court did not examine or decide the retroactivity of the Miller
    rule. Arkansas’s waiver of its retroactivity defense in Jackson’s appeal does not mean
    that the Supreme Court determined that Miller is retroactive.
    ¶46    Second, Beach argues that Miller is retroactive because the cases upon which it
    relies are retroactive.   Beach is correct that Roper and Graham are retroactive as
    substantive rules. See, e.g., In re Sparks, 
    658 F.3d 257
    , 262 (5th Cir. 2011) (concluding
    that Graham is substantive and retroactive); Little v. Dretke, 
    407 F. Supp. 2d 819
    , 823-24
    (W.D. Tex. 2005) (concluding that Roper is substantive and retroactive). Roper and
    Graham are similar to Kennedy and Atkins in that they “categorically bar a penalty for a
    class of offenders or type of crime.” Miller, 367 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2471. But
    Miller explicitly disclaimed creating a categorical bar to a type of punishment. Miller,
    367 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2471. In its effect, Miller more closely resembles two of
    the other cases upon which it relied—Woodson and Lockett, which invalidated mandatory
    10
    See Brief for Respondent, Jackson v. Hobbs, http://perma.cc/7bz4-vfyc (U.S. 2012)
    (No. 10-9647).
    25
    death penalty sentences and required individualized sentencing. 
    Lockett, 438 U.S. at 604
    ,
    98 S. Ct. at 2964-65; 
    Woodson, 428 U.S. at 303-05
    , 96 S. Ct. at 2991-92. Beach has not
    identified any cases holding that Woodson and Lockett qualify as retroactive under the
    current retroactivity framework.11
    ¶47    Third, Beach argues that it would be unjust to permit offenders on direct review to
    benefit from Miller but not to afford the same benefit to offenders on collateral review.
    In a case Beach cited as supplemental authority, and quoted in oral argument, the
    California Court of Appeal for the Second Judicial District made a similar point:
    We find particularly troubling the apparent inequity that would arise if the
    prospect of an individualized, discretionary judicial determination of
    whether a juvenile murderer should be afforded parole eligibility would
    depend solely upon the happenstance of the precise moment that the
    defendant’s conviction became final. No court that has rejected the
    retroactive application of Miller has advanced a rationale to resolve this
    inequity.
    In re Wilson, 
    233 Cal. App. 4th 544
    , 567 (2015). With this argument, the California
    court and Beach fail to recognize two things. First, Miller’s non-retroactivity is no more
    inequitable than the non-retroactivity of the rules in Beard, Schriro, or Sawyer, all of
    which similarly involved procedures meant to ensure the accuracy of sentences, yet
    11
    Beach cites Sumner v. Shuman, 
    483 U.S. 66
    , 72, 
    107 S. Ct. 2716
    , 2727 (1987) (invalidating a
    statute mandating a death sentence for a prisoner who kills someone while serving a life
    sentence), as an example of an instance when Woodson and Lockett were applied retroactively on
    collateral review. But Sumner does not address retroactivity under the current framework;
    indeed, Sumner does not appear to address a retroactivity argument at all. Moreover, Woodson
    was announced before Sumner’s conviction became final, meaning Woodson was not applied
    retroactively in Sumner. Beach also cites Campbell v. Blodgett, 
    978 F.2d 1502
    (9th Cir. 1992),
    Thigpen v. Thigpen, 
    926 F.2d 1003
    (11th Cir. 1991), and McDougall v. Dixon, 
    921 F.2d 518
    (4th
    Cir. 1990), to show Sumner’s retroactive application, but none of these cases appear to address
    Sumner’s retroactivity.
    26
    involved the harshest of punishments—the death penalty. Second, the concept of equity
    between offenders on direct and collateral review does not stand in a vacuum. For
    instance, Justice Wheat’s protest that it is unfair to not apply Miller by virtue of the
    “mere[]” timing of Beach’s conviction, Dissent, ¶ 73, ignores the unfairness of
    re-opening this case after a “mere” thirty years have passed without closure for the
    victim’s family.    The law strikes a balance between the interests of equity among
    offenders and finality of convictions. That balance is embodied in the principles of
    retroactivity that we have applied in our prior cases and that we apply again today.
    CONCLUSION
    ¶48    Because the Miller sentencing consideration rule is new and is neither a
    substantive rule nor a watershed procedural rule, we conclude that it is not retroactive to
    Beach’s claim on collateral review. Retroactivity is a threshold issue, 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 300
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1070, and Beach does not pass the threshold. Accordingly, we do
    not reach the merits in this case.
    ORDER
    ¶49    The petition for writ of habeas corpus is denied.
    DATED this 5th day of May, 2015.
    /S/ BETH BAKER
    We concur:
    /S/ JIM RICE
    /S/ JAMES B. WHEELIS, District Judge
    sitting in place of Chief Justice Mike McGrath
    27
    Justice Laurie McKinnon, specially concurring.
    ¶50    Beach asks this Court, once again, to ignore the important public interest in
    ensuring the finality of state court judgments and to conclude that, no matter how many
    years have passed since a petitioner’s conviction has become final, if he can scrape
    together enough developments in the law over thirty years, perhaps he might receive a
    better outcome at a new sentencing. Miller v. Alabama, 567 U.S. ___, 
    132 S. Ct. 2455
    ,
    2469 (2012), does not hold that life without parole sentences for juveniles are
    categorically unconstitutional and can never be imposed. Opinion, ¶ 10. Beach concedes
    that the holding of Miller does not apply to his case. Opinion, ¶ 11. Nevertheless, we go
    forward with an extensive retroactivity analysis of Miller after finding that consideration
    of youth at sentencing is a “new” procedural rule, Opinion, ¶ 34, though one that we
    ultimately conclude need not be applied retroactively, Opinion, ¶ 48. We do this in the
    context of Montana’s discretionary sentencing scheme, which specifically requires the
    sentencing judge to consider the individual characteristics, needs, circumstances, and
    potentialities of the person being sentenced.1 Montana has always required a judge to
    consider the individual characteristics of an offender—including age—in imposing a
    1
    At the time Judge Sorte sentenced Beach, the sentencing policy reflected in § 46-18-101, MCA
    (1978), provided:
    This chapter shall be liberally construed to the end that persons convicted of a
    crime shall be dealt with in accordance with their individual characteristics,
    circumstances, needs and potentialities; that dangerous offenders shall be
    correctively treated in custody for long terms as need; and that other offenders
    shall be dealt with by probation, suspended sentence, or fine whenever such
    disposition appears practicable and not detrimental to the needs of public safety
    and the welfare of the individual.
    28
    sentence.   There is nothing new about the rationale that juvenile offenders are less
    culpable than adult offenders, nor does the application of this rationale constitute a new
    rule in Montana. The significance of this rationale is to demonstrate that states with
    sentencing schemes mandating life without parole for juveniles violate the Eighth and
    Fourteenth Amendments, because such mandates fails to consider the youth of the
    offender.   Given our individualized and discretionary sentencing statutes and the
    obligations they already impose upon a judge to consider a person’s potential, needs, and
    individual characteristics, I am not sure of the value of a so-called new procedural rule
    requiring a judge to “‘follow a certain process,’” Opinion, ¶ 32 (quoting Miller, 567 U.S.
    at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2471), when that process is, in fact, already followed in Montana. In
    my opinion, Beach has failed to meet his burden of proving that Montana’s sentencing
    scheme is not consistent with the requirements of Miller.
    ¶51    The habeas corpus statute reflects a narrow scope of relief which, though equitable
    in nature, is an extraordinary remedy. Lott v. State, 
    2006 MT 279
    , ¶¶ 20-21, 
    334 Mont. 270
    , 
    150 P.3d 337
    . The writ is “not available to attack the validity of the conviction or
    sentence of a person who has been adjudged guilty of an offense in a court of record and
    has exhausted the remedy of appeal.” Section 46-22-101(2), MCA. We apply these
    principles routinely to other petitioners, and they should be applied equally to Beach.
    Beach received a facially valid sentence: Judge Sorte imposed a lawful sentence for
    Beach’s conviction of deliberate homicide after considering a PSI that not only specified
    Beach’s age, but set forth his juvenile history, family background, relationships, religion,
    29
    and any other relevant information for sentencing. Judge Sorte had full discretion in
    sentencing Beach, including the ability to find a statutory exception to the mandatory
    minimum based on Beach’s age. See § 46-18-222(1), MCA (1978). Unlike the fourteen-
    year-old defendants in Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2460, Beach was a few
    months shy of eighteen when he committed this offense, an adult when he confessed to
    law enforcement, an adult during his trial for homicide, and an adult when he was
    sentenced.
    ¶52       I cannot state my opinion more clearly and forcefully than the State, when it
    writes:
    Ted Nees’s letter eloquently expresses the anguish of Kim Nees’s family.
    The Nees family clearly thought their tragic entanglement with Beach
    ended back in 1984. Yet, Beach repeatedly manages to be the beneficiary
    of hearings and procedures that no other convicted criminal is allowed.
    Beach is entitled to nothing more.
    /S/ LAURIE McKINNON
    Justice Michael E Wheat, dissenting.
    ¶53       I agree with much of the plurality opinion, and I specifically join Section I of that
    opinion. In this case, however, I would depart from the nonretroactivity rule of Teague v.
    Lane, 
    489 U.S. 288
    , 
    109 S. Ct. 1060
    (1989), as applied by this Court in the line of cases
    beginning with State v. Egelhoff, 
    272 Mont. 114
    , 
    900 P.2d 260
    (1995).1 The rationale of
    1
    The plurality implies that we cannot consider whether to depart from this retroactivity
    framework because Beach did not argue that we should do so. However, we have addressed
    arguments and even issues not raised or supported by parties where failing to do so would cause
    substantial injustice. State v. Andersen-Conway, 
    2007 MT 281
    , ¶ 14, 
    339 Mont. 439
    , 
    171 P.3d 30
    those cases does not justify nonretroactivity in this case, and I would retroactively give
    Beach the benefit of the U.S. Supreme Court’s decision in Miller v. Alabama, ___ U.S.
    ___, 
    132 S. Ct. 2455
    (2012). In light of that decision, I would find Beach’s sentence to
    be unconstitutional and grant his petition for a writ of habeas corpus. For these reasons, I
    concur in Section I and dissent from the rest of the plurality’s opinion and its order.
    I. Retroactivity
    ¶54    I agree with the plurality that the retroactivity rule of Teague would preclude
    Beach from receiving the benefit of the procedural rule announced in Miller. We are not,
    however, limited by the retroactivity rule of Teague in state collateral review
    proceedings, and we are free to provide broader retroactive application of new rules than
    advocated by the Teague plurality. Opinion, ¶ 23 n.6; see also Danforth v. Minnesota,
    
    552 U.S. 264
    , 275, 277, 
    128 S. Ct. 1029
    , 1038-39 (2008) (“Neither Linkletter nor Teague
    explicitly or implicitly constrained the authority of the States to provide remedies for a
    broader range of constitutional violations than are redressable on federal habeas. . . . A
    close reading of the Teague opinion makes clear that the rule it established was tailored
    to the unique context of federal habeas and therefore had no bearing on whether States
    could provide broader relief in their own postconviction proceedings than required by
    that opinion.”). Although we have applied the nonretroactivity rule of Teague to state
    collateral review proceedings since first considering it in Egelhoff, I would depart from
    678. Given the importance of the constitutional issues at stake and the potential for substantial
    injustice resulting from an incorrect decision, we are not required to resolve the issues raised by
    the parties based on their reasoning alone.
    31
    that rule here. Considering the rationale and the interests upon which the nonretroactivity
    rule of Teague is based,2 the interests at stake in the rule announced in Miller, and the
    value this Court and the people of Montana place on those interests, I would retroactively
    give Beach the benefit of the rule announced in Miller.
    1. The rationale for the nonretroactivity rule of Teague
    ¶55    A plurality of the Supreme Court adopted a new rule governing retroactivity in
    
    Teague.3 489 U.S. at 305
    , 
    310, 109 S. Ct. at 1072-73
    , 1075. The general rule of
    nonretroactivity it adopted was an exercise of the U.S. Supreme Court’s power to
    interpret the federal habeas corpus statute. 
    Danforth, 552 U.S. at 278
    , 128 S. Ct. at
    1039-40. The purposes for the federal writ of habeas corpus provided the “relevant frame
    of reference,” and the resulting nonretroactivity rule was “tailored to the unique context
    of federal habeas.” 
    Danforth, 552 U.S. at 277
    , 
    279, 128 S. Ct. at 1039-40
    ; 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 306
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1073.
    ¶56    The plurality recognized two primary purposes for the writ. The first purpose,
    deterrence, provided the foundation for the general nonretroactivity rule. The plurality
    stated that “the threat of habeas serves as a necessary . . . incentive for trial and appellate
    courts throughout the land to conduct their proceedings in a manner consistent with
    established constitutional standards.” 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 306
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1073. In
    2
    This Court has never provided reasoning for adopting the retroactivity rule of Teague. See,
    e.g., State v. Cook, 
    2012 MT 34
    , ¶¶ 17-19, 
    364 Mont. 161
    , 
    272 P.3d 50
    ; State v. Reichmand,
    
    2010 MT 228
    , ¶¶ 13-15, 
    358 Mont. 68
    , 
    243 P.3d 423
    ; 
    Egelhoff, 272 Mont. at 126
    , 900 P.2d at
    267.
    3
    The rule was adopted by a majority of the U.S. Supreme Court in Penry v. Lynaugh, 
    492 U.S. 302
    , 313-14, 
    109 S. Ct. 2934
    , 2944 (1989).
    32
    order to perform this deterrence purpose, the plurality reasoned, rules need not be applied
    retroactively. Instead, “the habeas court need only apply the constitutional standards that
    prevailed at the time the original proceedings took place.” 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 306
    , 109
    S. Ct. at 1073.
    ¶57    Having decided that nonretroactivity was consistent with purposes of habeas
    corpus, the plurality considered the interests of comity and finality to better define the
    scope of review. It decided that nonretroactivity of new rules is preferred. 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 307-08
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1073-75. The interest of finality is the interest in reducing a
    controversy to a final judgment not subject to further judicial revision. 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 306
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1073. This interest, of course, weighed in favor of nonretroactivity.
    The plurality considered the interest to be important, because “[w]ithout finality,” it said,
    “the criminal law is deprived of much of its deterrent effect.” 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 309
    ,
    109 S. Ct. at 1074. The interest of comity also weighed in favor of nonretroactivity. The
    plurality reasoned that “the application of new rules to cases on collateral review . . .
    continually forces the States to marshal resources in order to keep in prison defendants
    whose trials and appeals conformed to then-existing constitutional standards.” 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 310
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1075. It decided that the “costs imposed upon the State[s]
    by retroactive application of new rules of constitutional law on habeas corpus . . .
    generally far outweigh the benefits of this application.” 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 310
    , 109
    S. Ct. at 1075 (quoting Solem v. Stumes, 
    465 U.S. 638
    , 654, 
    104 S. Ct. 1338
    , 1347 (1984)
    (Powell, J., concurring)) (modifications in original). Based on the deterrence purpose of
    33
    habeas corpus and the scope of review dictated by comity and finality, the plurality
    concluded that a general rule of nonretroactivity was appropriate for federal habeas
    corpus review. 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 310
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1075.
    ¶58    The limited exceptions the plurality recognized to this rule were based on a second
    purpose for federal habeas corpus, namely “to assure that no man has been incarcerated
    under a procedure which creates an impermissibly large risk that the innocent will be
    convicted.” 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 312
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1076. This was a relatively slight
    consideration for the plurality, however, as “[t]he Court has never defined the scope of
    the writ simply by reference to a perceived need to assure that an individual accused of
    crime is afforded a trial free of constitutional error.” 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 308
    , 109 S. Ct.
    at 1074.   The plurality, therefore, drew the exceptions to the nonretroactivity rule
    narrowly, concluding that only where the fundamental fairness of a proceeding was
    implicated or where “bedrock procedural elements . . . vitiate the fairness of a particular
    conviction,” would there be an impermissibly large risk of unfairness requiring
    retroactive application of a new rule. 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 311
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1076
    (emphasis in original). Such cases, the plurality declared, would be few and far between.
    See 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 311
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1076.
    ¶59    In crafting its rule, the plurality ultimately concluded that while fairness weighed
    in favor of retroactive application of new rules, it was a relatively slight consideration
    and was generally outweighed in the context of federal habeas review by considerations
    34
    of finality, comity, and the writ’s deterrence purpose. 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 306
    , 
    309-10, 109 S. Ct. at 1073-75
    .
    2. The rationale of Teague does not justify nonretroactivity in this case
    ¶60    Balancing these same interests in the context of this case and the Montana writ of
    habeas corpus, I would depart from the rule of Teague. Nonretroactive application of
    Miller will lead to unfair results, and unlike in Teague, the relevant countervailing
    interests are not sufficient to justify such results in this case. More specifically, our writ
    serves a different purpose than the federal writ, and, in this context and considering the
    rule we are asked to apply, fairness outweighs considerations of comity and finality.
    Therefore, the rationale of the Teague plurality does not justify application of its
    nonretroactivity rule in this case, and we should give Beach the benefit of Miller.
    a. The purposes for our writ of habeas corpus
    ¶61    We have recognized that “Montana’s guarantee of the privilege of habeas corpus
    embodies a fundamental, intrinsic principle: the right to challenge the cause of one’s
    imprisonment.” Lott v. State, 
    2006 MT 279
    , ¶ 7, 
    334 Mont. 270
    , 
    150 P.3d 337
    . Rather
    than a mere deterrent, the writ is the “birthright of the people” and “one of the most
    important safeguards of the liberty of the subject.” Lott, ¶ 6. Indeed, our Constitution
    guards the writ more completely than the Federal Constitution. Compare Mont. Const.
    art. II, § 19 with U.S. Const. art. I, § 9. Rather than primarily a deterrent to the courts, the
    writ in Montana is a tool for achieving justice. See Order, Paranteau v. Green 6-7, No.
    OP 13-0769 (Mar. 4, 2014); Lott, ¶¶ 7, 9, 20. Thus, I cannot say, as the Teague plurality
    35
    did, that the primary purpose of the writ can readily be served in all cases by merely
    “apply[ing] the constitutional standards that prevailed at the time the original proceedings
    took place.” 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 306
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1073.
    b. Comity does not affect this decision
    ¶62    Interests of comity played a central role in how the Teague plurality reached its
    rule. 
    Danforth, 552 U.S. at 279-80
    , 128 S. Ct. at 1040-41; 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 308
    -10,
    109 S. Ct. at 1074-75. Comity is generally of no concern in state collateral review
    proceedings. 
    Danforth, 552 U.S. at 279-80
    , 128 S. Ct. at 1041. Except in limited
    circumstances, this is so in Montana, and this is the case today. The Court’s decision
    here will not disrupt the proceedings of any other sovereign, and for that reason comity
    does not weigh against retroactive application of Miller. If anything, comity instead
    weighs in favor of retroactive application. See 
    Danforth, 552 U.S. at 279-80
    , 128 S. Ct.
    at 1041 (“[C]onsiderations of comity militate in favor of allowing state courts to grant
    habeas relief to a broader class of individuals than is required by Teague.”); Kills on Top
    v. State, 
    279 Mont. 384
    , 420, 
    928 P.2d 182
    , 204 (1996) (“[C]onsiderations of federalism
    and comity counsel respect for the ability of state courts to carry out their role as the
    primary protectors of the rights of criminal defendants.”).
    c. Finality carries less weight here than it did in Teague
    ¶63    As in Teague, interests of finality do weigh against retroactive application of
    Miller, but we need not give finality the same weight as the Teague plurality. The
    Supreme Court has stated, “finality of state convictions is a state interest, not a federal
    36
    one. It is a matter that States should be free to evaluate, and weigh the importance of,
    when prisoners held in state custody are seeking a remedy for a violation of federal rights
    by their lower courts.” 
    Danforth, 552 U.S. at 279-80
    , 128 S. Ct. at 1041 (emphasis in
    original).   I would afford finality less weight than the Teague plurality in today’s
    decision.
    ¶64    While I agree with the Teague plurality that finality is important to conservation of
    State resources, 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 310
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1075, the plurality only considered
    the effect on State resources from overturning a conviction. Here, Beach does not contest
    his guilt nor does he ask for a new trial. Rather, he merely asks to be resentenced. While
    allowing such relief does impose a burden on the State, it does not impose nearly the
    same burden that overturning a conviction and requiring a new trial would. For this
    reason, the importance of finality does not weigh as heavily here as it did in Teague or as
    it would in many state collateral review proceedings.
    ¶65    I also agree with the Teague plurality that “[w]ithout finality, the criminal law is
    deprived of much of its deterrent effect.” 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 309
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1074.
    However, finality is less important to preserving the deterrent effect in this case than it
    was in Teague. The deterrent effect of criminal law is at the heart of the rule that we are
    asked to apply. In Miller, Graham v. Florida, 
    560 U.S. 48
    , 
    130 S. Ct. 2011
    (2010), and
    Roper v. Simmons, 
    543 U.S. 551
    , 
    125 S. Ct. 1183
    (2005), the U.S. Supreme Court
    recognized that juvenile offenders are less deterred by criminal sentences than adult
    offenders. It is partly for this reason that it prohibited certain sentences and required
    37
    individualized consideration to support others.4 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2465
    ; 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 72
    , 130 S. Ct. at 2028-29; 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 571-73
    , 125 S. Ct. at 1196-97.
    Here, we cannot say that retroactive application will harm the deterrent effect of the law,
    because we cannot say that the law was ever a deterrent to Beach or to similarly situated
    individuals. 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2465
    , 2469. At the very least, it served as less of a
    deterrent than it would in most cases. Correspondingly, there is less harm from depriving
    the law of its deterrent effect in this case, and finality carries less weight than it did in
    Teague.
    d. Nonretroactive application of Miller is unfair
    ¶66       The countervailing interest of fairness is of more importance here than it was in
    Teague, given the purposes for our state writ, as discussed above. This heightened
    interest of fairness weighs in favor of retroactivity here, because nontretroactive
    application of Miller creates unfair results. This is clear upon examination of the rule we
    are asked to apply and, based on that rule, the unfair distinctions the plurality draws in its
    decision.
    i. The rule of Miller
    ¶67       We are asked to apply the rule of Miller in this case. Miller is the latest decision
    in a line of cases that includes Roper and Graham, and its rule can only be fully
    4
    See Part I.2.d.i., below for a more complete discussion of these cases.
    38
    understood in the context of those cases.5 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2463-69
    . These cases
    stand for the rule that the Eighth Amendment prevents any criminal punishment that
    lacks a legitimate penological justification, and that to determine whether there is such
    justification, courts must take into account the characteristics attendant to juvenility that,
    for example, make juvenile convicts less culpable and more reformable.
    ¶68    In Roper, the U.S. Supreme Court decided that the Eighth Amendment prohibits
    states from imposing the death penalty on juvenile 
    offenders. 543 U.S. at 568
    , 125 S. Ct.
    at 1194. It explained that when compared to adults, juveniles are less mature, less
    responsible, more vulnerable to negative influences and outside pressures, and more
    likely to be rehabilitated. 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 569-70
    , 125 S. Ct. at 1195-96. These
    differences, the court decided, render juvenile offenders less culpable for their crimes
    than adults. 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 571
    , 125 S. Ct. at 1196. Based on this diminished
    culpability and lack of maturity, the court reasoned that the penological purposes for the
    death penalty – retribution and deterrence – apply with less force to juveniles than adults.
    Ultimately, it decided that “neither retribution nor deterrence provides adequate
    justification for imposing the death penalty on juvenile offenders,” and that the death
    penalty is a disproportionate punishment when applied to juveniles. 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 572
    , 125 S. Ct. at 1196. Because the Eighth Amendment requires punishments to be
    proportionate to the crime and culpability of an offender, the court decided that
    5
    For the sake of convenience, we have and will continue to refer to the rule we are asked to
    apply as the rule of Miller. The rule might more accurately, however, be referred to as the rule
    expressed in Miller in light of Graham and Roper.
    39
    sentencing juveniles to death violates the Eighth Amendment. Roper, 543 U.S. at 
    568, 125 S. Ct. at 1194
    .
    ¶69    Applying much the same analysis, the U.S. Supreme Court decided in Graham
    that the Eighth Amendment prohibits imposing life sentences without the possibility of
    parole on juveniles that have not committed homicide.           
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 74
    ,
    130 S. Ct. at 2029-30. It again analyzed the penological purposes for the sentence and
    decided that, given the differences in maturity and culpability of a juvenile, the
    penological purposes do not justify imposing such a sentence on juveniles. 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 67-74
    , 130 S. Ct. at 2026-30. In particular, it recognized that imposition of a
    sentence of life without parole is an implicit decision that a juvenile is incorrigible and
    will forever be a danger to society. 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 74
    , 130 S. Ct. at 2029-30. The
    penalty, it said, “forswears altogether the rehabilitative ideal,” since it “deprives the
    convict of the most basic liberties without giving hope of restoration.” 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 69-70
    , 
    74, 130 S. Ct. at 2027
    , 2030. This kind of irrevocable judgment that denies an
    offender the right to reenter society, it reasoned, is not appropriate in light of juveniles’
    “capacity for change and limited moral culpability.” 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 74
    , 130 S. Ct.
    at 2030.
    ¶70    The U.S. Supreme Court again applied this general analytical framework in Miller.
    The decision in that case differed from Roper and Graham in that it did not categorically
    prohibit a type of punishment for a class of individuals. 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2471
    . The
    court relied on those cases’ analyses, however, and decided that, based on the
    40
    characteristics attendant to juvenility, a sentence of life imprisonment without parole
    imposed on a juvenile homicide offender will usually not have legitimate penological
    justifications. 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    . It decided, though, that it might be justified for
    particular juveniles, based on their particular characteristics. 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    .
    It, therefore, required sentencing courts, as a condition to the constitutionality of a life
    without parole sentence imposed on a juvenile homicide offender, to consider the
    penological justifications for the sentence in light of the offender’s juvenility and
    attendant capacity for rehabilitation and diminished culpability. 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    .
    ¶71     This line of cases stands for the proposition that the Eighth Amendment prevents
    any criminal punishment that lacks legitimate penological justification, and that to
    determine whether there is such justification, courts must take into account the
    characteristics attendant to juvenility that make juvenile offenders less culpable and more
    likely to be reformed. For some sentences, such as the death penalty and life sentences
    without parole for non-homicide offenders, there will never be legitimate penological
    justifications for imposing the sentence on juveniles. 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 74
    , 130 S. Ct.
    at 2030; Roper, 543 U.S. at 
    568, 125 S. Ct. at 1194
    . For other sentences, such as life
    sentences without parole for homicide offenders, there may but usually will not be
    legitimate penological justifications. To conform to the Eighth Amendment in such
    circumstances, sentencing courts must consider the characteristics of the particular
    juvenile offender. 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    .
    41
    ii. The effect of the plurality’s decision not to apply Miller
    retroactively
    ¶72    The plurality, by choosing not to apply the rule of Miller retroactively, implicitly
    makes several fine and unfair distinctions between similarly situated offenders, and it
    decides that constitutional protections can legitimately be extended or withheld upon
    these distinctions alone.
    ¶73    If a sentence identical to Beach’s was imposed today on an offender identical to
    Beach, the Court should have no trouble disposing of the threshold retroactivity issue and
    considering whether the sentence is unconstitutional. See Opinion, ¶¶ 12, 48; 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    . Yet, according to the plurality, that same question of constitutionality
    cannot be reached now merely because of the timing of Beach’s conviction and
    sentencing. This aspect of the plurality’s decision draws two distinctions.
    ¶74    First, the plurality decides that there is a difference between the sentences that this
    society can constitutionally impose and the sentences this society can constitutionally
    enforce. If Beach’s sentence does not comply with Miller, then this society could not
    impose the same sentence on him today. The plurality decides, though, that we can
    continue to enforce the same sentence we now recognize as unconstitutional. This is
    illogical, especially since a sentence to life without parole is a judgment by a court that an
    offender will never be fit to reenter society. 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    ; 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 74
    , 130 S. Ct. at 2030. If we now recognize that a certain type of offender may be able
    to reenter our society, we should not prevent the offender from doing so based merely on
    the values of the past society that sentenced him or her.
    42
    ¶75    The second distinction this aspect of the plurality’s decision draws is between
    offenders based purely upon when the offender appears in court. It decides that a mere
    60 days – the time for filing an appeal to this Court, after which postconviction
    proceedings are the only means of relief – will mean the difference between an offender
    receiving constitutional protection or not. See M. R. App. P. 4(5)(b). As we have stated,
    “selectively applying the Constitution to people who are similarly situated based merely
    on the circumstances or timing of their appearance in court is the antithesis of the
    judiciary’s responsibility.” State v. Whitehorn, 
    2002 MT 54
    , ¶ 41, 
    309 Mont. 63
    , 
    50 P.3d 121
    . The rule of Miller is unquestionably of constitutional importance, and the plurality
    decides today to selectively apply it to otherwise similarly situated persons based solely
    on the timing of the offender’s appearance in court.
    ¶76    Another aspect of the plurality’s decision draws a third unfair distinction,
    distinguishing and treating disparately those sentences that are on their face penologically
    unjustified from those that lack penological justification based upon more individualized
    circumstances. While this is not a distinction the plurality explicitly makes, it is the
    practical effect of its opinion. As discussed above, the U.S. Supreme Court decided in
    Graham and Roper that death sentences and life without parole for non-homicide
    offenders would never have legitimate penological justifications when imposed on
    juveniles. 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 74
    , 130 S. Ct. at 2030; Roper, 543 U.S. at 
    568, 125 S. Ct. at 1194
    . The Court would have no trouble applying this rule retroactively, as it is a
    categorical prohibition. See Opinion, ¶¶ 38-39.
    43
    ¶77       Illogically, however, the plurality refuses to apply the virtually indistinguishable
    rule of Miller. The real distinction between Miller and Roper or Graham is that the court
    in Miller decided that certain sentences are usually penologically unjustified rather than
    categorically prohibited. 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    . Because the sentence was not
    always prohibited, the Supreme Court allowed it under Miller based on the individual
    circumstances of the particular offender. 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    . Here, if Beach’s
    sentence is equivalent to a sentence of life without parole and if the proper procedures
    were not followed in imposing it,6 his sentence probably lacks penological justification
    and is unconstitutional. We would have no way of definitively knowing whether it is
    justified since an individualized determination was not made. By not applying Miller
    retroactively, the plurality implicitly decides that we need not ensure that Beach’s
    sentence was proportional and constitutional merely because, regardless of Beach’s own
    circumstances and despite the severe risk that the sentence will be unconstitutional, the
    type of sentence might occasionally be constitutionally applied to juveniles. See Opinion,
    ¶¶ 38-39; 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    .
    ¶78       Thus, the plurality’s decision distinguishes between sentences that we can decide
    are unconstitutional based only on the sentence and bare demographic facts of the
    offender and those that we can tell are unconstitutional only after individualized
    consideration.       This is unfair.      A sentence that lacks penological justification is
    disproportionate and violates the Eighth Amendment regardless of the analysis required
    6
    These questions are resolved below, in Part II.
    44
    to reach that conclusion.      To extend and withhold the protections of the Eighth
    Amendment based on how closely we must examine the circumstances is an untenable
    and unfair basis for Constitutional protections.
    e. Finality does not justify nonretroactivity in this case
    ¶79    The plurality’s decision results in an unfair distinction.       Given the level of
    importance we give fairness and remediation in Montana habeas corpus proceedings,
    only a strong countervailing interest could justify nonretroactive application of Miller.
    As discussed above, the only countervailing interest in this case is finality, and it is of
    slight importance here. It is not sufficient to justify nonretroactivity in spite of the
    resulting unfair consequences.
    ¶80    Unlike the U.S. Supreme Court, this Court serves as “the primary protector[] of
    the rights of criminal defendants.” Kills on 
    Top, 279 Mont. at 420
    , 928 P.2d at 204
    (quoting Cabana v. Bullock, 
    474 U.S. 376
    , 391, 
    106 S. Ct. 689
    , 699 (1986)).
    Accordingly, when analyzing Eighth Amendment protections, we have stated that
    “[c]onventional notions of finality of litigation have no place where life or liberty is at
    stake and infringement of constitutional rights is alleged.” Kills on 
    Top, 279 Mont. at 400
    , 928 P.2d at 192 (holding that res judicata does not bar reconsideration of the
    constitutionality of a petitioner’s death sentence during postconviction relief
    proceedings); see also State v. Southwick, 
    2007 MT 257
    , ¶ 16, 
    339 Mont. 281
    , 
    169 P.3d 698
    (holding that res judicata does not prevent this Court from correcting a facially illegal
    sentence). While this statement taken alone may be overbroad and while the relevant
    45
    cases may be distinguishable from the present situation on their facts, the general
    principle is meritorious; this State, its people, and this Court place more value on fairness
    than finality, at least in the context of the Eighth Amendment. At the very least, where
    the interests bear comparable importance in a particular matter, finality should give way
    to fairness. As discussed above, this principle comports with the purposes for Montana’s
    writ of habeas corpus.
    ¶81    The plurality’s decision to adhere to Teague today turns this preference on its
    head. Here, fairness and the remedial purpose of our writ of habeas corpus are weighty
    compared to the relatively less important interest of finality.        For this reason, and
    considering how we have weighed these interests in the past, finality and nonretroactivity
    should give way to fairness and retroactive application of Miller.
    II. Beach
    ¶82    The State argues that we should not grant Beach’s petition for habeas corpus, even
    if Miller is applied retroactively.       It contends that Beach’s sentence was not
    unconstitutional under the rule of Miller because Miller only applies to sentences of life
    without parole that were mandatorily imposed by statute. The State concludes that
    Beach’s sentence is not unconstitutional because it was neither mandatorily imposed nor
    a sentence of life without parole. Additionally, it argues, the sentencing court did, in fact,
    consider Beach’s age when sentencing him. For this reason, it again concludes that
    Beach’s sentence was not unconstitutional under the rule of Miller. I disagree.
    46
    ¶83    While applied in that case to a mandatory sentence of life without parole, the court
    in Miller was concerned with the “irrevocable judgment about [an offender’s] value and
    place in society” that kind of sentence makes. 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2465
    (quoting
    
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 74
    , 130 S. Ct. at 2030) (alteration in original). Life without parole,
    it said, “forswears altogether the rehabilitative ideal,” deciding that the offender is
    “incorrigible.” 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2465
    (quoting Graham, 560 U.S. at 73-
    74, 130 S. Ct. at 2029-30
    ). Because “incorrigibility is inconsistent with youth” and juveniles are thus
    often more reformable than adults, the court concluded that the sentence would not
    always be penologically justified and therefore could not be mandatorily imposed.
    
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2465
    , 2468-69.           It stated that the sentence might still be
    constitutionally imposed on juveniles, but only after individualized consideration of that
    juvenile’s characteristics. 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    .
    ¶84    Here, the court’s decision applies with the same force to Beach’s sentence.
    Because he was sentenced on May 11, 1984, to 100 years’ imprisonment without the
    possibility of parole, the earliest Beach could have been released was when he was 72
    years old. This means that his sentence exceeded his life expectancy at the time of
    sentencing, and that it is near or in excess of his life expectancy now. See IIA National
    Center for Health Statistics, Vital Statistics of the United States § 6, 577 (U.S.
    Department of Health and Human Services 1984) (reporting the life expectancy at birth
    for a white male born in 1961 as 67.55 years, and reporting the expectation of life at
    twenty years old for a white male born in 1961 as 50.25 years); National Center for
    47
    Health Statistics, United States Life Tables, 2010, National Vital Statistics Reports, Nov.
    6, 2014, at 3 (reporting that in 2010 the expectation of life for a 40 year old white male
    was 38.5 years). Thus, the sentence provided Beach with no meaningful opportunity for
    release and no “meaningful opportunity” to demonstrate the “maturity and rehabilitation”
    sufficient to reenter society. 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 75
    , 130 S. Ct. at 2011. As in Miller,
    the sentence imposed upon Beach forswears the rehabilitative ideal based upon the
    implicit decision that Beach, even as a juvenile, was incorrigible. As in Miller, the
    sentence deprived him of the most basic liberties without giving hope of restoration.
    
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2465
    ; see 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 69-70
    , 130 S. Ct. at 2027. Thus, for
    the purposes of Miller, Beach’s sentence is the functional equivalent of life without
    parole. Cf. Lockyer v. Andrade, 
    538 U.S. 63
    , 79, 
    123 S. Ct. 1166
    , 1176-77 (2003)
    (Souter, J., dissenting) (“because Andrade was 37 years old when sentenced, the
    substantial 50-year period amounts to life without parole”); 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 70-71
    ,
    130 S. Ct. at 2028 (citing Harmelin v. Michigan, 
    501 U.S. 957
    , 996, 
    111 S. Ct. 2680
    ,
    2702 (1991) (“In some cases . . . there will be negligible difference between life without
    parole and other sentences of imprisonment – for example, . . . a lengthy term sentence
    without eligibility for parole, given to a 65-year-old man.”); Sumner v. Shuman, 
    483 U.S. 66
    , 83, 
    107 S. Ct. 2716
    , 2726 (1987) (“[T]here is no basis for distinguishing, for the
    purposes of deterrence, between an inmate serving a life sentence without the possibility
    of parole and a person serving several sentences of a number of years, the total of which
    exceeds his normal life expectancy.”). According to Miller, then, Beach’s sentence could
    48
    only be constitutionally imposed if the sentencing court considered whether the sentence
    was penologically justified in light of Beach’s juvenility. 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    .
    ¶85    It is of little importance that Beach’s chronological age was on the PSI and
    available to the sentencing judge. In order to constitutionally impose Beach’s sentence, it
    would not have been enough for the sentencing judge to be aware of Beach’s
    chronological age. Knowing that Beach was a juvenile, the court would still need to
    consider Beach’s particular circumstances and characteristics and to determine whether,
    in light of these characteristics, his culpability and inability to be reformed warrant the
    severe sentence. 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    .
    ¶86    Here, there is no indication in the record or otherwise that the District Court made
    these considerations.   It issued a sentence that effectively decided that Beach was
    incorrigible without considering that as a juvenile he was more likely to be reformed. It
    effectively sentenced him to life imprisonment without parole, and it did so without
    considering that as a juvenile Beach may have been more susceptible to outside pressure,
    less cognizant of consequences, and correspondingly less culpable and less likely to be
    deterred. 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2465
    -69. In doing so, it made “youth (and all that
    accompanies it) irrelevant to imposition of that harshest prison sentence” and created “too
    great a risk of disproportionate punishment.” 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    .
    ¶87    For these reasons, Beach’s sentence does not comply with the rule announced in
    Miller. It is, therefore, unconstitutional. I would grant Beach’s petition for this reason
    and I would order that he be resentenced.
    49
    /S/ MICHAEL E WHEAT
    Justice James Jeremiah Shea, dissenting.
    ¶88   I respectfully dissent from the plurality’s opinion. I write separately to note that
    we appear to be adopting the federal retroactivity framework in this case and to express
    my reservations about doing so.        This decision marks the first time we have
    acknowledged that we are not bound by the federal retroactivity framework, yet we
    decide to follow it anyway. In my view, this raises two concerns.
    ¶89   First, the plurality adopts the federal retroactivity framework on the premise that
    we have consistently applied this framework and, therefore, stare decisis compels us to
    continue to do so. However, closer scrutiny of our retroactivity jurisprudence in this
    regard reflects that it finds its origin in the mistaken premise that we were bound to
    follow the federal framework when, in fact, we were not. I would decline to perpetuate
    this mistake in this case. If we elect to continue on this path, however, I believe it is
    incumbent upon us to acknowledge it is by choice and not federal mandate.
    ¶90   Second, the federal framework is contrary to controlling Montana law.           The
    federal framework reflects the U.S. Supreme Court’s interpretation of the federal habeas
    corpus statutes. Montana’s habeas statutes—which I contend should be applied in this
    case—compel a different result.     Our own habeas corpus statutes indicate different
    restrictions than those created by the federal framework. I believe the conflict between
    the restrictions our statutes impose on retroactivity and the restrictions the federal
    50
    framework imposes should be resolved in favor of our statutes, rather than the U.S.
    Supreme Court’s interpretation of the federal statutes.
    ¶91    The plurality’s position appears to be that we should apply Teague in this case
    because we have consistently applied Teague, even since the Supreme Court has made it
    clear that we are not compelled to do so, and Beach has not demonstrated that our prior
    jurisprudence is manifestly wrong. Moreover, Beach has only pointed out that we are
    free to adopt a more expansive retroactivity rule, but has not developed or tested any
    alternative rule. I address first the plurality’s concerns about the stare decisis effect of
    our prior jurisprudence, and then the concern about the lack of an alternative rule. I
    would submit that stare decisis does not compel us to follow Teague, that there is in fact
    an alternative retroactivity rule contained in our own habeas statutes and pre-Egelhoff
    opinions, and that we are bound to follow that rule rather than Teague.
    ¶92 I. Stare Decisis Is Inapplicable When Our Prior Precedent is Based on Manifest
    Legal Error
    ¶93    In State v. Egelhoff, we mistakenly assumed we were bound by the federal
    retroactivity framework. Specifically, we held: “[Teague’s] view of retroactivity for
    cases on collateral review is binding upon this Court.” State v. Egelhoff, 
    272 Mont. 114
    ,
    126, 
    900 P.2d 260
    , 267 (1995) (emphasis added). In 2008, the U.S. Supreme Court
    explained that we were wrong in Egelhoff, and that we are not bound to follow federal
    retroactivity rules.   In Danforth v. Minnesota, the U.S. Supreme Court held that
    “[s]ince Teague is based on statutory authority that extends only to federal courts
    applying a federal statute, it cannot be read as imposing a binding obligation on state
    51
    courts.” Danforth v. Minnesota, 
    552 U.S. 264
    , 278–79, 
    128 S. Ct. 1029
    , 1040 (2008).
    As the plurality correctly notes, the U.S. Supreme Court explicitly addressed our
    mistaken interpretation of Teague as being binding upon us. See 
    Danforth, 552 U.S. at 281
    , 128 S. Ct. at 1042 (citing Egelhoff and noting Montana as one of only three state
    courts to mistakenly assume we were bound by federal retroactivity rules).
    ¶94       This Court has only addressed Danforth once, in State v. Reichmand,
    
    2010 MT 228
    , 
    358 Mont. 68
    , 
    243 P.3d 423
    .            The Reichmand opinion contains two
    significant mistakes.     First, we held in Reichmand that we voluntarily adopted the
    retroactivity rule in Teague, stating: “In State v. Egelhoff . . . we chose to adopt two
    [retroactivity] rules from Griffith and Teague and applied them to our own retroactive
    application of new state rules.” Reichmand, ¶ 14 (emphasis added). In fact, we did not
    choose to adopt the Teague retroactivity rule in Egelhoff; we mistakenly concluded we
    were bound to follow the Teague retroactivity rule. 
    Egelhoff, 272 Mont. at 126
    , 900 P.2d
    at 267.
    ¶95       Second, Reichmand mistakenly summarized the holding in Dansforth as stating
    that states may adopt their own retroactivity rules for new state constitutional errors, but
    not for new federal constitutional rules:
    The U.S. Supreme Court recently held that each state has the right to craft
    its own unique retroactivity jurisprudence, using federal requirements as a
    floor.    That is, the U.S. Supreme Court’s retroactivity analysis
    for federal constitutional errors     is binding      upon      the states
    when federal constitutional errors are involved. Danforth’s unequivocal
    grant of flexibility allows states to hand-pick retroactivity rules for
    application of new state rules.
    52
    Reichmand, ¶ 13 (emphasis in original) (citation omitted). At first blush, this seems
    correct—and indeed it would be correct if retroactivity arose from the new constitutional
    rules themselves.     Danforth, however, held that retroactivity arises not from the
    constitutional rule itself, but from the remedy—that is, the federal habeas corpus statutes.
    Since the federal retroactivity framework derives from the federal habeas statutes—which
    are applicable only to federal courts—it cannot be binding on state courts. Danforth’s
    holding states this clearly: “Since Teague is based on statutory authority that extends only
    to federal courts applying a federal statute, it cannot be read as imposing a binding
    obligation on state courts.” 
    Danforth, 552 U.S. at 278
    –79, 128 S. Ct. at 1040. Thus,
    Reichmand’s assertion that the federal framework “is binding upon the states
    when federal constitutional errors are involved” is incorrect.
    ¶96    Reichmand’s summary of Danforth mirrors the Danforth dissent’s argument, not
    the majority opinion. The Danforth dissent argued that retroactivity arises from the
    opinion granting the new constitutional right, not the federal habeas statutes. Thus, the
    dissent reasoned that states are free to craft whatever retroactivity rules they wish for new
    state constitutional rules, but are bound by the federal retroactivity framework for new
    federal constitutional rules. Specifically, the dissent argued:
    State courts are the final arbiters of their own state law; this Court is the
    final arbiter of federal law. State courts are therefore bound by our rulings
    on whether our cases construing federal law are retroactive. . . . States [can]
    apply their own retroactivity rules only to new substantive rights under
    their own law, not to new federal rules announced by this Court.
    53
    
    Danforth, 552 U.S. at 291
    –92, 
    295, 128 S. Ct. at 1047
    , 1049 (Roberts, C.J., dissenting)
    (internal quotations omitted). It appears that in Reichmand we mistakenly summarized
    the dissenting opinion in Danforth, rather than the actual holding.
    ¶97    To summarize, we mistakenly believed ourselves bound by the federal
    retroactivity rules in Egelhoff. The U.S. Supreme Court pointed out our mistake, and
    effectively overruled it, in Danforth.       Reichmand addressed Danforth, but misread
    Egelhoff as a voluntary adoption of the federal rule, and then perpetuated the mistaken
    belief that we must follow the federal framework when determining the retroactivity of
    new federal constitutional rules. The only case in which we addressed retroactivity since
    Reichmand, was State v. Cook, 
    2012 MT 34
    , 
    364 Mont. 161
    , 
    272 P.3d 50
    , which
    followed Reichmand and the federal rules without substantive discussion. This is the
    jurisprudence upon which the plurality relies in determining that Teague articulates the
    appropriate retroactivity rule in Montana.
    ¶98    The plurality opinion acknowledges the mistake we made in Egelhoff, but not its
    broader implication. As the plurality points out: “Under this Court’s policy of stare
    decisis, we keep faith with precedent ‘unless it is demonstrably made to appear that’ our
    precedent ‘manifestly is wrong.’” Opinion, ¶ 29 (quoting State ex rel. Perry v. District
    Court, 
    145 Mont. 287
    , 310, 
    400 P.2d 648
    , 660 (1965) (internal quotations omitted)).
    Since the U.S. Supreme Court has explicitly told us our precedent is wrong, and we have
    never corrected that mistake, I contend that qualifies as “‘demonstrably made to appear
    that’ our precedent ‘manifestly is wrong.’”
    54
    ¶99    This case marks the first time that a party has asked us to reconsider our
    retroactivity rule in light of Danforth.      The parties in Reichmand did not mention
    Danforth, much less ask us to depart from federal retroactivity jurisprudence.        See
    generally Appellant’s Brief and Appellee’s Brief, State v. Reichmand (DA 09-0057). It is
    clear that neither Egelhoff nor Reichmand voluntarily adopted Teague as Montana’s
    retroactivity rule, since Egelhoff erroneously concluded the federal rules were binding
    upon us, and Reichmand erroneously concluded that Egelhoff was a voluntary adoption of
    the federal rules. The Court’s opinion here marks the first time we have acknowledged
    that we are not bound by federal retroactivity rules and, therefore, marks our first
    conscious, voluntary adoption of Teague. A plurality of this Court seems to favor this
    course of action and, consequently, may adopt Teague as our rule. However, I am
    concerned that the only basis for our adoption of the federal framework is “precedent”
    that is merely ostensible at best and manifestly wrong at worst.
    ¶100 The plurality asserts that we voluntarily adopted the federal framework in
    Reichmand, contending: “After acknowledging our ability to choose any standard,
    [Reichmand] applied the federal retroactivity framework.” Opinion, ¶ 28. However,
    Reichmand was grounded upon the misapprehension that we had already chosen to adopt
    the federal framework in Egelhoff, as we unambiguously expressed: “In State v. Egelhoff,
    we chose to adopt [the federal framework] and applied them to our own retroactive
    application of new state rules. . . . Thus, Goetz will retroactively apply to Reichmand if
    the requirements established in Egelhoff are met.” Reichmand, ¶¶ 14–15. It is beyond
    55
    dispute that we did not choose to adopt the federal retroactively framework in Egelhoff;
    we mistakenly believed ourselves bound to adopt it.1             Since Reichmand failed to
    acknowledge that mistake—instead erroneously characterizing our adoption of the
    federal framework in Egelhoff as a “choice”—I remain unconvinced that this Court has
    ever voluntarily adopted the federal framework before today. If the plurality sees fit to
    do so with this opinion, that is certainly its prerogative. I submit only that we are
    creating precedent today rather than following it.
    ¶101 II. The Appropriate Retroactivity Rule Under Montana Law
    ¶102 As Justice Harlan noted of the U.S. Supreme Court’s retroactivity jurisprudence
    prior to Teague: “Clearly, it is at least fair to regard this issue as not yet settled by this
    Court. Consequently, I go on to inquire how it ought to be resolved.” Mackey v. United
    States, 
    401 U.S. 667
    , 688, 
    91 S. Ct. 1160
    , 1165 (1971) (Harlan, J., concurring and
    dissenting).
    ¶103 Since the federal retroactivity rules are based on the federal habeas corpus statutes,
    a natural place to begin an analysis of the correct retroactivity rule for Montana would be
    the Montana habeas corpus statutes. The Montana writ of habeas corpus is defined by
    § 46-22-101(1), MCA, and provides that “every person imprisoned or otherwise
    restrained of liberty within this state may prosecute a writ of habeas corpus to inquire into
    1
    It is also worth noting that Egelhoff did not involve any new state rules. The Egelhoff opinion
    was based entirely on federal law as evidenced by the U.S. Supreme Court’s reversal of our
    decision there. See Montana v. Egelhoff, 
    518 U.S. 37
    , 
    116 S. Ct. 2013
    (1996). Thus, Egelhoff
    could not have adopted the federal retroactivity rules and applied them to new state rules.
    56
    the cause of imprisonment or restraint and, if illegal, to be delivered from the
    imprisonment or restraint.” Section 46-22-101(1), MCA.
    ¶104 “In the construction of a statute, the office of the judge is simply to ascertain and
    declare what is in terms or in substance contained therein, not to insert what has been
    omitted or to omit what has been inserted.” Section 1-2-101, MCA. We should not,
    then, insert restrictions into our own habeas corpus statute that the Legislature has chosen
    to omit. Moreover, “When a statute is equally susceptible of two interpretations, one in
    favor of natural right and the other against it, the former is to be adopted.” Section
    1-2-104, MCA. To the extent we might interpret the habeas statute to include restrictions
    against natural rights, we are instructed not to do so if the statute is equally susceptible of
    an interpretation in favor of natural rights.
    ¶105 This being noted, the seemingly broad right granted by § 46-22-101(1), MCA, is
    appropriately constrained by § 46-22-102, MCA, which places a restriction on what sorts
    of claims may be raised in a habeas proceeding, and which may be subject to the
    retroactive application of new constitutional rules on habeas review.            This statute
    provides: “A person may not be released on a writ of habeas corpus due to any technical
    defect in commitment not affecting the person’s substantial rights.” Section 46-22-102,
    MCA. Unlike § 46-22-101(2), MCA, which we held unconstitutional in Lott v. State,
    
    2006 MT 279
    , 
    334 Mont. 270
    , 
    150 P.3d 337
    , § 46-22-102, MCA, comports with both the
    57
    protection of the writ enshrined in the Montana Constitution and the historical purposes
    of habeas corpus.2
    ¶106 Thus, I believe that the only restriction with support in Montana law would be a
    restriction that prevents claims that raise only technical defects that do not affect the
    petitioner’s substantial rights. An appropriate definition of a “technical defect” can be
    located in Coleman v. State, 
    194 Mont. 428
    , 
    633 P.2d 624
    (1981), a habeas case that
    predates Egelhoff’s mistaken determination that we were bound by Teague. In Coleman,
    we held that a new constitutional rule was not retroactive because it was “not one aimed
    at overcoming an aspect of the criminal trial that substantially impairs its truth-finding
    function thereby raising questions as to the accuracy of guilty verdicts in past trials.”
    
    Coleman, 194 Mont. at 503
    , 633 P.2d at 670. Based on that reasoning, an appropriate
    definition of a “technical defect” would be one that does not raise significant questions as
    to the accuracy of the verdict or the sentence.
    ¶107 A technical defect restriction on habeas review would mean that some categories
    of new constitutional rules appropriately would never be retroactive. For example, new
    search and seizure rules and the attendant exclusionary rule would not be retroactive
    because their violation does not undermine confidence in the validity of a conviction or
    sentence. As we noted in Coleman: “[T]he purpose of the exclusionary rule to deter
    2
    “‘From the time of the Magna Charta, the Great Writ of Habeas Corpus has been liberally
    employed as a means of guaranteeing that [justice] be accomplished and that a miscarriage of
    justice will be remedied. For at its heart, the writ represents an acknowledgment of the principle
    that the rights of freedom of the individual are worthy of protection.’” Lott, ¶ 20 (quoting State
    v. Perry, 
    232 Mont. 455
    , 462–63, 
    758 P.2d 268
    , 273 (1988) (overruled on other grounds by State
    v. Clark, 
    2005 MT 330
    , 
    330 Mont. 8
    , 
    125 P.3d 1099
    )) (citation omitted).
    58
    police misconduct is not served at the post-appeal stage and application of the
    exclusionary rule deflects the truth-finding process.”     
    Coleman, 194 Mont. at 503
    ,
    633 P.2d at 670. Since our own habeas statutes forbid only habeas claims based on
    “technical defects,” and our prior habeas jurisprudence suggests an appropriate definition
    of “technical defect,” I believe we compound our previous errors by adopting Teague
    when we clearly are not bound to do so, and we have a more compelling alternative.
    ¶108 Since there is a statutory basis for a Montana-specific retroactivity rule, I submit
    we are bound to follow the Montana-specific rule over one based on Teague. The U.S.
    Supreme Court has stated that the federal retroactivity framework arises from
    interpretation of the federal habeas corpus statutes, not the U.S. Constitution: “Teague is
    based on statutory authority that extends only to federal courts applying a federal statute,
    it cannot be read as imposing a binding obligation on state courts.” 
    Danforth, 552 U.S. at 278
    –79, 128 S. Ct. at 1040 (emphasis added). Since the federal retroactivity framework
    finds no basis in the U.S. Constitution, the Montana Constitution, nor the statutes of this
    state, our adoption of it here can only be characterized as common law. Where the
    common law and statute conflict, the statute shall take precedent. Section 1-1-108,
    MCA, states:
    In this state there is no common law in any case where the law is declared
    by statute. But where not so declared, if the same is applicable and of a
    general nature and not in conflict with the statutes, the common law shall
    be the law and rule of decision.
    At a minimum, this means that before we may adopt a common law rule, we must
    ascertain that it is “not in conflict with the statutes.” Comparing the one restriction
    59
    placed on habeas corpus by our statutes and Teague’s restrictions based on the distinction
    between substantive and procedural rights evinces a conflict between Teague and
    Montana statutes. Therefore, I contend we are compelled to follow our statutes over
    Teague.
    ¶109 Similarly, I believe our prior resolution of a similar issue regarding restrictions on
    which fundamental rights may be asserted in a collateral proceeding dictates that we
    should follow Montana statutory law rather than the U.S. Supreme Court’s non-binding
    opinions. In State v. Maine, we rejected the U.S. Supreme Court’s restriction on which
    constitutional rights may be asserted in a collateral challenge to a prior conviction. State
    v. Maine, 
    2011 MT 90
    , ¶¶ 31–32, 
    360 Mont. 182
    , 
    255 P.3d 64
    . Maine addressed whether
    defendants could collaterally attack a prior conviction as unconstitutional when that
    conviction was being used to enhance punishment for a later crime—in effect, the
    question was whether you can hold a mini-habeas proceeding attacking a prior conviction
    in the middle of sentencing for a later crime. At the time that we were deciding Maine,
    the U.S. Supreme Court had decided Custis v. United States, 
    511 U.S. 485
    , 
    114 S. Ct. 1732
    (1994), in which it held that such a collateral attack could occur only if the prior
    conviction violated Gideon. The State asked us to adopt Custis out of considerations of
    finality and judicial economy. See Maine, ¶¶ 16–17 (citing Custis). We rejected the U.S.
    Supreme Court’s reliance on judicial economy and finality as justification for limiting
    which constitutional rights may be asserted on collateral review because we saw no
    principled basis for distinguishing between fundamental rights. We held: “[W]e disagree
    60
    with the premise that some [fundamental] rights are sufficiently ‘unique’ to merit
    consideration in collateral challenges, while others are not so deserving. . . . [T]he
    existence of administrative burdens in evaluating collateral challenges does not justify
    limiting the particular rights which may be asserted.” Maine, ¶¶ 31–32. The concurrence
    further noted:
    While the strong interest in finality of judgments supports placing a limit on
    collateral attack of underlying convictions, there is no textual basis for a
    rule that allows such attack for the violation of one fundamental right but
    not for the violation of another, equally fundamental right. I therefore
    agree with the Court’s decision to reject that artificial distinction in favor of
    a rule of convenience.
    Maine, ¶ 45 (Baker, J., concurring). That reasoning is instructive in the present case.
    Similar to Custis, Teague allows some constitutional rights to be asserted on collateral
    review, but not others. As the Maine concurrence made clear, where there is no basis in
    Montana law for the particular distinctions the federal courts make between fundamental
    rights, we should decline to follow the federal rule.         Teague’s distinction between
    substantive and procedural rights finds no basis in Montana law.                   The same
    considerations that led us to reject Custis should apply with equal force in considering
    whether to adopt Teague.
    ¶110 I agree whole-heartedly with the Maine concurrence that the strong interest of
    finality of judgments supports placing a limit on collateral attacks, and that any such limit
    should arise from a textual basis. While there is no such textual basis for limitations on
    which rights may be asserted in the type of proceeding discussed in Maine, our habeas
    statutes and pre-Egelhoff opinions constitute an appropriate textual basis for limitations
    61
    on collateral attack in habeas proceedings. For that reason, I believe the appropriate—
    indeed, the mandatory—course would be to follow the statutes’ limitations rather than
    Teague’s, which have no basis in Montana law.
    ¶111 I share the plurality’s concern about the parties neither proposing nor testing a
    retroactivity rule alternative to Teague. I am not convinced, however, that Beach’s
    failure to propose an alternative necessarily means we cannot inquire into the appropriate
    retroactivity rule.
    ¶112 I would note that the parties in Teague did not ask the U.S. Supreme Court to
    reexamine its retroactivity rules, nor did they develop or test a new proposed rule as the
    plurality suggests must be done before this Court can adopt a new rule. Rather, the
    Teague Court sua sponte adopted a new rule because it determined that its retroactivity
    analysis needed to be clarified in light of the lack of a unifying theme in its prior
    precedent. 
    Teague, 489 U.S. at 300
    , 109 S. Ct. at 1069–70. If the lack of a unifying
    theme is sufficient for the U.S. Supreme Court to sua sponte reexamine its rules and
    adopt an entirely new approach, then I contend a line of precedent founded on a mistaken
    legal assumption warrants similar reexamination of our own rules when a party has
    expressly asked us to do so.
    ¶113 More importantly, the circumstances here do not implicate our usual concern
    about adopting a new rule that was not argued by the parties. Whether we adopt Teague
    or some other rule, we will be adopting a rule that was not argued by the parties. No
    party has ever asked us to adopt Teague; therefore, its merits have never been tested in
    62
    the manner the plurality suggests must happen before we adopt a new rule. The plurality
    asserts that we adopted the federal framework in Reichmand. Opinion, ¶ 28. Assuming
    that were correct, then we adopted the federal framework without any of the argument the
    plurality asserts is a necessary antecedent to adoption of a new rule. Thus, we have either
    already adopted a rule that no party has ever argued, or we must do so here. Moreover,
    the rule I am proposing we adopt is merely a plain-language interpretation of our habeas
    statutes. It is our job to state what the relevant law is when deciding a case, and the
    habeas statutes’ plain language provides us ample guidance to state the appropriate
    retroactivity rule for Montana.
    ¶114 This case provides us with the choice of either grounding our retroactivity rule on
    Montana statutory law or on a precedent that both the U.S. Supreme Court, and the
    plurality, recognize was incorrectly decided. I would choose the former. Retroactivity
    should not rest on a distinction between substantive versus procedural as per Teague, but
    rather should be an analysis as to whether the claim raises merely a technical defect that
    does not affect the person’s substantial rights as per § 46-22-102, MCA. I submit that the
    right to be sentenced in conformity with the Eighth Amendment of the U.S. Constitution
    and Article II, § 22 of the Montana Constitution is a substantial right which merits
    retroactive application. In this case, since Miller, Roper, and Graham have held that
    sentencing a youth implicates these substantial rights, and the record is completely
    devoid of any indication that the sentencing judge “[took] into account how children are
    different, and how those differences counsel against irrevocably sentencing them to a
    63
    lifetime in prison” when sentencing, Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2469, I would
    remand the case for the District Court to consider Beach’s youth at the time he committed
    the crime. Some juvenile offenders may commit crimes so heinous that they warrant
    incarceration for life. Indeed, it may be that Beach merits the same sentence, even after
    considering his youth at the time of the crime. But before that sentence is imposed, the
    District Court should explicitly consider whether Beach was “‘the rare juvenile offender
    whose crime reflects irreparable corruption,’” and not “‘the juvenile offender whose
    crime reflects unfortunate yet transient immaturity.’” Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct.
    at 2469 (quoting 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 573
    , 125 S. Ct. at 1197; 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 68
    ,
    130 S. Ct. at 2026).
    /S/ JAMES JEREMIAH SHEA
    Justice Patricia Cotter, dissenting.
    ¶115 I dissent from the Court’s denial of Beach’s petition. While I agree with some of
    the arguments set forth in both Justice Wheat’s and Justice Shea’s dissents, I write
    separately to assert that, even if one were to accept the Plurality Opinion’s analysis of
    retroactivity, reversal and remand is still required because the Miller sentencing
    consideration rule is a substantive rule which should be applied retroactively to Beach’s
    claim on collateral review.
    ¶116 In Schriro v. Summerlin, the United States Supreme Court held that substantive
    rules apply retroactively, and it included as a substantive rule one which “alters the range
    64
    of conduct or the class of persons that the law punishes” and “place[s] particular conduct
    or persons covered by the statute beyond the State’s power to punish.” It observed that
    within this category are rules that prohibit punishment for a class of defendants because
    of their status or offense. 
    Schriro, 542 U.S. at 352
    -53, 124 S. Ct. at 2522-23. Youth is
    clearly a “status.” As observed in Wilson, 
    233 Cal. App. 4th 544
    (2015) (review granted
    April 15, 2015, S224745, briefing deferred), the Schriro court concluded that “[s]uch
    rules apply retroactively because they carry a significant risk that a defendant . . . faces a
    punishment that the law cannot impose upon him.” In re 
    Wilson, 233 Cal. App. 4th at 559-60
    (quoting 
    Schriro, 542 U.S. at 352
    , 124 S. Ct. at 2523) (internal quotation marks
    omitted). Here, that punishment is Beach’s effective sentence of life without parole.
    ¶117 As the Plurality Opinion correctly observes, Miller requires a sentencing court to
    “‘follow a certain process’ before imposing a life without parole sentence on a juvenile.”
    Opinion, ¶ 32.     The Plurality Opinion seizes upon the reference to “process” and
    concludes citing Schriro that the sentencing consideration rule under Miller “regulates
    only the manner of determining a sentence,” (Opinion, ¶ 39), and is therefore procedural.
    I disagree. I would conclude, as did the Court of Appeals of California on April 16,
    2015, that Miller announces a new substantive rule, which should be retroactively applied
    to cases on collateral review.
    ¶118 In Willover, the court addressed the 1999 conviction and sentence of a 17-year-old
    defendant who was convicted of two counts of first-degree murder, together with other
    crimes. In re Willover, 2015 Cal. App. LEXIS 322 (Cal. App. 6th Dist. Apr. 16, 2015).
    65
    Willover was sentenced to two consecutive life without parole terms (LWOP) for the
    first-degree murders, with additional imprisonment terms imposed for the other crimes.
    The court noted that at the time of the 1999 sentencing hearing, a California statute had
    been construed as creating a presumption in favor of life without parole as the appropriate
    penalty for juveniles convicted of “special circumstance murder.” In re Willover, 2015
    Cal. App. LEXIS 322 at *9. However, the sentencing scheme was not mandatory.
    ¶119 Apropos of the foregoing reference by the Plurality Opinion to “process,” and
    citing cases from other courts around the country, the Willover court concluded that
    Miller
    effectively “alter[ed] the range of conduct or the class of persons that the
    law punishes” [
    Schriro, 542 U.S. at 353
    , 124 S. Ct. at 2523], in that it
    barred LWOP sentences for juvenile homicide offenders unless the
    sentencing court determines, after a consideration of a number of
    case-specific substantive factors, that the defendant is “‘the rare juvenile
    offender whose crime reflects irreparable corruption.’ [citations].” [
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    ]. Miller did not simply set forth a new rule regulating
    “the manner of determining the defendant’s culpability,” but a rule that sets
    forth the specific considerations to be made during a sentencing decision.
    [
    Schriro, 542 U.S. at 353
    , 124 S. Ct. at 2523].
    In re Willover, 2015 Cal. App. LEXIS 322 at *20-21 (emphasis in original). Thus, the
    court concluded that Miller announced a substantive rule.
    ¶120 The Willover court also found it significant that when the Supreme Court granted
    relief in Miller, it granted relief in the companion case of Jackson v. Hobbs, directing that
    the defendant in that case also be given a new sentencing hearing. In re Willover, 2015
    Cal. App. LEXIS 322 at *21. Notably, Jackson arose on collateral review, and yet the
    66
    Supreme Court saw no reason to direct a different outcome in that case, suggesting that
    the Miller court may have considered its decision substantive.
    ¶121 As the Plurality Opinion observes at ¶ 35, there is a split of authority on the
    question of whether Miller announces a procedural or a substantive rule. In fact, the
    Supreme Court very recently granted a petition for writ of certiorari in Montgomery v.
    Louisiana, No. 14-280, on the question of whether Miller should be applied retroactively.
    See State v. Montgomery, 
    141 So. 3d 264
    , 2014 La. LEXIS 1538 (2014), cert. granted,
    sub nom. Montgomery v. Louisiana, 
    2015 U.S. LEXIS 1942
    (U.S. Mar. 23, 2015). In
    concluding that the rule in Miller is procedural rather than substantive, the Plurality
    Opinion finds company in the decisions of other courts. However, so too does this
    Dissent. The question is clearly unsettled.
    ¶122 Among the factors cited in Miller as appropriate for consideration at sentencing
    are “chronological age and its hallmark features-among them, immaturity, impetuosity,
    and failure to appreciate risks and consequences.”      
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2468
    .    In
    
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 79
    , 130 S. Ct. at 2032, the Supreme Court stated: “Life in prison
    without the possibility of parole gives no chance for fulfillment outside prison walls, no
    chance for reconciliation with society, no hope. Maturity can lead to that considered
    reflection which is the foundation for remorse, renewal, and rehabilitation.”         The
    Supreme Court recognized that life without parole “forswears altogether the rehabilitative
    ideal” and “improperly denies the juvenile offender a chance to demonstrate growth and
    maturity.” Graham, 560 U.S. at 73-
    74, 130 S. Ct. at 2029-30
    .
    67
    ¶123 I would conclude that the rule in Miller is substantive and that Beach should be
    resentenced. I would direct the court on remand to take into account Beach’s youth at the
    time his crime was committed, as well as Beach’s demonstration of growth and maturity
    over the past thirty years. As Willover instructs, I would direct the court to determine
    upon consideration of these factors whether Beach is or is not “the rare juvenile offender
    whose crime reflects irreparable corruption.” In re Willover, 2015 Cal. App. LEXIS 322
    at *20 (quoting 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    ). I therefore dissent from the Court’s denial of
    Beach’s petition.
    /S/ PATRICIA COTTER
    68